The Dignity of the South
CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS: General, is it—is it the government’s submission that the citizens in the South are more racist than citizens in the North?1 |
At oral argument in Shelby County v. Holder, at least four (and probably five) Justices sounded ready to hold that section 5 of the Voting Rights Act (VRA)—which applies special scrutiny to changes in the election procedures of certain states and counties, mainly in the South—exceeds Congress’s enforcement power under the Reconstruction Amendments. According to the argument advanced by Shelby County, Alabama, the heart of the problem with the Act is that its differential treatment of covered and non-covered states offends the “equal dignity”2 of the covered states.3
The equal dignity of the states, this argument runs, obligates Congress either to treat all states equally, or to have a strong justification for doing otherwise. As for the justification in the case of section 5, the conservative Justices sounded skeptical. As Chief Justice Roberts demonstrated in a dramatic set-piece at oral argument,4 the formula for deciding which jurisdictions are covered and which are not does not turn on contemporary voter registration figures or current discriminatory laws. Instead, the formula is about history. The covered jurisdictions are those that disenfranchised many or most of their minority citizens under Jim Crow, using devices such as literacy tests that the VRA itself long ago consigned to the history books.
This argument from the equal dignity of the states is both more and less novel than it might seem.The idea that states have dignity, and that this dignity has some constitutional force—although not, to be sure, because of any specific piece of constitutional text—emerged as an important theme in the “new” federalism jurisprudence of the 1990s. In a series of sovereign immunity cases, most prominently Alden v. Maine,5 conservative Supreme Court majorities held that it would violate states’ “dignity” if Congress could use its Article I powers to make states subject to lawsuits for money damages without their consent.6 In those cases, dignity enters the picture in a hierarchical way: it is one state versus the federal government. The invocation of dignity is meant to evoke a pre-democratic idea of the dignity of the sovereign, an idea that predates the modern conceptions of human dignity that are now so central to the constitutional law and jurisprudence of many nations and international bodies.7 In other words, the dignity claim here is about the sovereignty of a state—any state. Maine will do as well as South Carolina. What seems novel, in the Shelby County variant of the dignity-of-states argument, is the comparativeelement: here, what is supposed to be undignified is the federal government treating some states differently from others.
Four years ago, in Northwest Austin Municipal Utility District Number One v. Holder (NAMUDNO),8 the Court heard a challenge to the constitutionality of section 5 that was more or less parallel to Shelby County. In that case, the Court stopped at the water’s edge, declining to plunge into the depths of striking down the statute. But in dicta, the Court strongly signaled that this comparative state equality element was at the heart of the case against section 5. The Court invoked what it called a “fundamental principle of equal sovereignty” of the states.9 This principle has a nice ring to it. But as a constraint on the federal government’s power to treat states unequally, it has no basis either in constitutional text or in existing constitutional doctrine.10 In South Carolina v. Katzenbach, in 1966, the Court actually considered and rejected this same argument against section 5 of the VRA, holding that South Carolina’s invocation of a “doctrine of the equality of the states” posed no problem because “that doctrine applies only to the terms upon which States are admitted to the Union,” not to a statutory provision like section 5.11 Rather audaciously, the NAMUDNO Court quoted this very sentence from Katzenbach as support for the idea that a “doctrine of the equality of the states” exists—concealing the part about how “that doctrine applies only to the terms upon which States are admitted to the Union” behind a strategically placed ellipsis.12
Leaving aside the murky provenance of this principle, to which I will return below, something remains mysterious about the shape of it. Objecting to differential treatment sounds like a claim about equality. That is apparently the way South Carolina tried and failed to sell it to the Court in 1966. But where does dignity come into the picture? Why argue that a difference in treatment—as between, say, Massachusetts and Mississippi, or Maine and South Carolina—violates the Southern states’ dignity?
The answer is staring us in the face. It is deeply intertwined with section 5’s regional focus and its history-driven trigger. The dignitary harm here lies in treating the South—the former Confederacy—differently from most of the rest of the nation in a particular way that carries with it an implication that the past is not dead.13 Section 5 holds that the states with the worst histories of Jim Crow disenfranchisement from the middle part of the twentieth century remain, even today, under a cloud of suspicion that other states are not under, a cloud that can be lifted only through a formal judicial bailout process.14 Section 5 thus places the Southern states under a regime of regional federal oversight that is a faint echo, especially in its geographic outline, of Reconstruction itself.15The chief indignity of this regime, for the Southern states, is its implication, which Chief Justice Roberts so forthrightly brought to the surface at oral argument: “General,” he asked, “is it the government’s submission that the citizens in the South are more racist than citizens in the North?”16
In comparison with the recent sovereign immunity cases in which the Court has invoked the dignity of the states, much seems novel here. Beyond the sovereign dignity of an individual state, we have the suggestion of comparative “equal dignity” or “equal sovereignty” between states, a regional South-versus-North assertion of the equality or dignity of the South as a region, the indignity of the suggestion that the past is not even past, and perhaps even—getting a bit personal—the suggestion that the citizens of the South might even today be “more racist” than those of the North. (The Solicitor General wisely demurred on that point at oral argument.17)
However, in a different and more important sense, none of this is new at all. These seemingly novel elements themselves have a history—and a life outside the courts. They are linked to an important set of sharply contested claims about the meaning of the Civil War and the meaning of Reconstruction that Americans have been fighting about for the past 150 years. The legal significance of these contested claims is that they affect how we understand, even today, state sovereignty and the balance of federal and state power.
This Essay is short, so I will be blunt. A historical memory of a “War Between the States,” followed by a reunion between noble blue and gray on equal terms—with Reconstruction a best-forgotten corrupt interregnum in between—might well yield the conclusion that antebellum understandings of state sovereignty remain largely intact, even today. However, such a conclusion cannot be sustained if we instead remember the Civil War and Reconstruction as a radical transformation of the South through federal military and civilian power, with a series of amendments specifically ratifying the use of that federal power to establish the equal citizenship of Southern blacks.
The latter story is not as kind to the Southern states. It is not as protective of their dignity. To remember what actually happened between 1861 and 1870 is to remember a shattered nation reconstructed on new foundations,18 where the terms of readmission of the conquered South were based, fundamentally, not on principles of equal sovereignty, but on military conquest, surrender, and occupation. It is to remember a series of amendments that remade the Constitution, shifting weighty new powers to the federal government, above all in the enforcement of the rights of racial minorities. Indeed, as Akhil Amar has recently argued, the process of ratification of the Reconstruction Amendments itself put the lie to any semblance of a claim that the conquered Southern states reentered the Union as equal sovereigns.19 Those states alone were forced to adopt the Fourteenth Amendment as a condition of readmission, remaking the constitutional order on new terms far less amenable to claims of either the sovereign dignity or the equality of the Southern states.
But even before the bodies were buried on the battlefields of the Civil War, a counter-narrative began to emerge to challenge the story just outlined.20 A remnant of the defeated South began to tell a different story of the War and, later, of Reconstruction—a story that over the next 150 years would become incalculably influential in American political life and historical memory. According to this counter-narrative, the North and the South were equally to blame for the War, which was not about slavery but rather about state sovereignty, a noble cause which history somehow vindicated despite the South’s defeat. Moreover, according to this counter-narrative, the North is equally as racist as the South and probably always was; to claim otherwise is a kind of regional libel, an insult to Southern dignity. Finally, and perhaps in tension with these other elements, as this counter-narrative developed it came to include an idea that the “New” South sloughed off any racist past long ago—and thus, any present-day implication that the South is more racist than the North is an insult, an indignity, to the region and its people.21
Recent judicial invocations of the dignity of states in the sovereign immunity and anti-commandeering cases bore only an oblique, ambiguous relationship to these claims of historical memory. In Shelby County, the relationship is much more direct. Here, state “equal dignity” is colliding with congressional power not under the Commerce Clause but under the Reconstruction Amendments themselves. The subject matter of the conflict is the very heart of the Reconstruction Power: the federal enforcement of minority rights.22 In this context, it is hard to avoid the larger historical import of asserting the equal dignity of the states—and in particular, the equal dignity of the Southern states—as a constraint on the exercise of federal power. In this light we should not be surprised to see “equal dignity” claims yoked to claims that the South is not “more racist” than the North, and claims that it is an indignity to the South to assert that history leaves the region under any continuing cloud.
The North—the Union—won the War. But to a remarkable extent, the South’s twentieth-century apologists won the peace. That is why we are having a conversation right now about the equal dignity of the Southern states rather than the equal dignity of Southern black voters.23
I. Southern Dignity and Historical Memory
For many American Civil War buffs even today, the dominant memory and imagery of the Civil War is of a series of heroic battles between noble soldiers in uniforms of blue and gray, enlisting and fighting, brother against brother, “in obedience to a blindly accepted duty,” as Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. put it in “The Soldier’s Faith,” his famous 1895 speech to Harvard’s graduating class.24 For Holmes, the manly virtues of ordinary soldiers on both sides transcended the substance of any causes for which they may have fought. This imagery places North and South on an equal footing: all war aims aside, North and South were the banners under which great men marched and died.
The early stirrings of this way of remembering the War were in part a story of Northern and Southern white veterans coming to terms with a common experience of horrific slaughter, suffering, and loss. But the dominance of this view in the twentieth century was ultimately the product of an organized campaign by the losers of the War to win the peace—a campaign that David Blight, in his remarkable history of the War and Reconstruction in American memory, calls “one of the most highly orchestrated grassroots partisan histories ever conceived.”25 This campaign reshaped the terms of reunion in the decades following Reconstruction in a way calculated to restore the lost dignity of the South.
Reconstruction was a powerful indignity to Southern whites, one that piled an inversion of the racial political order on top of humiliating military defeat and economic desolation. In opposition to Reconstruction, Southerners began to forge a combination of themes into a powerful ideology: Southern honor and virtue, the perfidious and dishonorable character of the federal occupation, principles of state sovereignty and the equal treatment of the states, and opposition to racial equality.26 Benjamin H. Hill, a former Confederate senator from Georgia, argued in 1868 that the Northern occupiers aimed to “dishonor” the South, and that the presidential election of that year turned “upon the glorious ancestral doctrine that the States are equal and that white blood is superior.”27 (This glorious doctrine did not carry the day; Ulysses S. Grant and the Republicans won, leading to the passage of the Fifteenth Amendment.)
One of the great scenes in Blight’s book is an event that turned out to be a preview of reunion on the South’s terms: the unveiling, in 1875, of a statue of Confederate General Stonewall Jackson in Richmond. The recently elected Democratic Governor of Virginia, James Kemper, declared the event a reminder of the “respect” due the South, and a harbinger of “actual reconciliation,” which would mean the “equal honor and equal liberties of each section.”28 There would be decorations by the Ku Klux Klan along the parade route, but there was a dispute about whether to allow black marchers in the parade. Some argued that this would be “an indignity to the memory of Jackson and an insult to the Confederates.”29 In the end, the black marchers did not march.30 The moment encapsulates Blight’s story: it illustrates the disastrous implications of reconciliation for black civil rights. For Northern and Southern whites to “clasp hands across the bloody chasm”31 with equal dignity and equal moral standing, it was necessary to submerge or forget much of what the War was about—specifically, that one side fought to keep black people enslaved, and the other side, by the end of the War, fought for their freedom. In a nation that has repudiated slavery, this means the Civil War has a right side and a wrong side. Forgetting that took effort and determination.
That effort began with high-ranking ex-Confederate officials, who after the War turned to historical research and memoir and created historical societies to set the record straight and undermine Northern historians’ narratives of the War’s meaning.32 Meanwhile, an emerging genre of Southern sentimental literature, which won tremendous nationwide popularity, aimed to “model the pathos of Uncle Tom’s Cabin, but in reverse,” portraying “Southern martyrdom under ruthless abolition outrages.”33 Women’s organizations such as the United Daughters of the Confederacy, along with confederate veterans’ groups, elaborately ranked, condemned, and promoted school history textbooks as well as history books in libraries, with the aim of “vindicating the South.”34 At Columbia University, the historian William Dunning, along with political scientist and law professor John W. Burgess and their students, created what came to be known as the Dunning School of the scholarship of Reconstruction.35 According to the Dunning School, the Radical Republicans in Congress, “[m]otivated by an irrational hatred of Southern ‘rebels’” and a partisan desire to consolidate power, forced black suffrage on the defeated South, leading to a “sordid period” of gross misrule by Northern “carpetbaggers,” the “scalawags” who aided them, and black Southerners fundamentally “incapable” of self-government.36 Justice, on this view, was on the side of the Southerners who rebelled successfully against Reconstruction through legal and extralegal means, including Klan violence, throwing off the yoke of federal power by 1877 and restoring states’ sovereignty and “home rule.”37 The assault on federal authority and the veneration for the Klan were encapsulated in D.W. Griffith’s 1915 movie The Birth of a Nation, a blockbuster in the North as well as the South.
The Dunning School’s story of Reconstruction dominated American textbooks and popular understandings for the first half of the twentieth century, where it undoubtedly helped justify Jim Crow. In 1935, W.E.B. Du Bois published a monumental challenge to this story in Black Reconstruction in America, but few whites were ready to listen.38 However, by the time of South Carolina v. Katzenbach in the mid-1960s, the opinions of both historians and ordinary Americans were turning against the Dunning School narrative. The civil rights movement was shifting the ground from which the Civil War and Reconstruction were viewed; the narratives that had preserved the equal dignity of the South began to be perceived not as authoritative history but as regional special pleading. As Eric Foner explains, it required “not simply the evolution of scholarship but a profound change in the nation’s politics and racial attitudes to deal the final blow to the Dunning School.”39 When Southern opponents of school integration made claims on states’ rights, even reviving versions of Calhoun’s antebellum concepts of nullification and interposition, this ultimately convinced few outside the South. Claims that the North and the South were equal or similarly situated in terms of racial history (for instance, the Southern Manifesto’s claim that separate but equal “began in the North—not in the South”40) did not convince the rest of the nation. In the 1960s, claims of the “equal dignity” of the Southern states would have been too redolent of massive resistance and opposition to civil rights to be taken seriously as legal arguments outside the South.
Back in 1888, William Dunning himself wrote an early article exploring the idea of a principle of the equality of the states and whether that principle survived the Civil War and Reconstruction.41 His focus was the terms of admission of new states to the union. He concluded that as a matter of positive law, “the theory of equal states” is “finally defunct,” although it could still perhaps be “galvanized into life by a powerful act of judicial construction.”42 In other words, even Dunning, the principal figure in the movement to refashion the history of Reconstruction in terms that preserved the South’s dignity, acknowledged that the Civil War had altered the balance of federal and state power in a way that rendered obsolete a whole range of antebellum arguments that the sovereignty or dignity of the states constrained federal power. The article opens with these sentences: “In respect to the question of ultimate political supremacy under the constitution of the United States, the result of the civil war gave an answer that was decisive. No argument based in any particular upon the principle of state-sovereignty can ever again be tolerated in the arena of constitutional debate.”43 I make no claim here about the precise range of arguments Dunning imagined the War took off the table. But notice that Dunning was making no claim in these sentences about the Reconstruction Amendments. He was stating what was, at the time, obvious: that the War itself had worked a decisive structural change in the balance of federal and state sovereignty, one that entailed “the sweeping invasion by national legislation of the region hitherto deemed sacred to state rights” and “an enormous increase of the central government’s dignity and power.”44 This change would have occurred even if the Reconstruction Amendments had never existed.45 It was an outcome of the War itself.
II. A Revival of State Dignity
A century after the War’s conclusion, mainstream Americans had come to view the War not as a “War Between the States”—a phrase that carries an implication of a fight among equally sovereign states—but as the “Civil War,” a conflict wholly within a single sovereign nation.46 The United States had become a singular noun (“The United States is . . .”) rather than a plural one (“The United States are . . .”).47 This modern understanding is compatible with some range of residual conceptions of state sovereignty. For instance, states are sovereign in that they possess the power to make law. However, on this modern understanding, there is no room for claims that our constitutional order requires new limits on federal power as a way of respecting the dignity of the states as independent sovereigns.48 In the 1950s and 1960s, when Southern leaders invoked “the dual system of Government” and states’ “rights,” it was plain that this was just sectional talk, Southern opposition to the Second Reconstruction echoing Southern opposition to the first.49
Nonetheless, for Americans growing up and going to school in, say, the 1950s, the Dunning School history of Reconstruction left a deep mark. In 1961, an article surveying the landscape of U.S. history textbooks then in wide use found that the books told a story of Reconstruction that today seems incredible—an “uncomplicated tale” of good and evil, in which hateful Radical Republicans imposed corrupt misrule on the South and “[t]he oppressed whites turned naturally to the Ku Klux Klan for help to restore the government to the people” and throw off the yoke of federal power.50 In the 1960s and 1970s, even as most non-Southern politicians rejected the hard “states’ rights” talk associated with massive resistance, a softer, gentler rhetoric of states’ rights and state sovereignty, as a constraint on federal power, found its way into the political mainstream. This rhetoric was not exclusive to the Republican Party, but it was especially strong there, as that party staked a new, and wildly successful, claim on the allegiance of Southern whites, including those sympathetic to massive resistance.51 In the 1970s, William Rehnquist joined the Court and began to give voice to the idea of “the sovereignty of the States” as a constraint on federal power.52
Beginning in the mid-1990s, the Rehnquist Court upended prevailing understandings of federal and state power and sovereignty in what some have called the “Rehnquist Revolution.”53 In a series of mostly 5-4 decisions, the Court imposed new restrictions on Congress’s powers under both the Commerce Clause54 and the Reconstruction Power.55 Those changes need not have invoked any claims about the sovereignty or dignity of the states; for instance, the Court could have relied on arguments about enumerated powers. But in fact the Rehnquist Court gave state dignity claims a starring role. At the center of the Rehnquist Revolution was a doctrine of sovereign immunity, whose “preeminent purpose,” as Justice Thomas explained for one of those 5-4 majorities, “is to accord States the dignity that is consistent with their status as sovereign entities.”56 Although sometimes styled as a (frankly rather convoluted) interpretation of the Eleventh Amendment, this principle of state dignity was really derived “not from the Eleventh Amendment but from the structure of the original Constitution itself.”57 The Court similarly held that the federal government’s “commandeering” of state officials was “fundamentally incompatible with our constitutional system of dual sovereignty” as established in 1789.58 A basic question looms behind these holdings. How did the Rehnquist Court understand their relationship to structural changes after the original Constitution was written—in particular, the fundamental changes wrought by the events of 1861-70? The Court did not say. In dissent in one of the anti-commandeering cases, Justice White put it bluntly. “One would not know from reading the majority’s account,” he wrote, “that the nature of federal-state relations changed fundamentally after the Civil War.”59
We have little access to the views of most of the Justices of the Rehnquist Court about the meaning of the Civil War and Reconstruction. But in the case of Chief Justice Rehnquist, we know quite a bit, because the Chief Justice wrote a book-length history of a pivotal moment in Reconstruction, Centennial Crisis: The Disputed Election of 1876.60 Centennial Crisis is an odd book, remarkable as much for what it does not contain as for what it does. At the time of its publication in 2004, the book was viewed by many readers as “an allegory, and apologia, for the Supreme Court’s ruling in Bush v. Gore.”61 And fair enough: as told by Rehnquist, Centennial Crisis is the story of a heroic Supreme Court Justice who braves partisan criticism to cast the decisive vote to resolve a disputed election that might otherwise have torn the nation apart.62 But Rehnquist’s book may be more interesting as a window into his view of the meaning of Reconstruction and the Civil War. As Eric Foner delicately explained in a critical review, “Rehnquist remains locked into an antiquated view of the Reconstruction era long abandoned by scholars,” a view extremely reminiscent of the Dunning School.63 As Foner explains, Rehnquist describes Reconstruction by the Radical Republicans in Congress as a “‘Carthaginian Peace’ (that is, the total subjugation of the defeated party by the victor after a war)”;64 Rehnquist sees “racial hostility”65 in the South but misses the “reign of terror aimed at overturning Reconstruction and restoring white supremacy.”66 In short, Rehnquist misses the true stakes and the key result of the 1876 crisis—the rollback of Reconstruction and federal power, with disastrous consequences for black civil rights in the South that would take a century to undo—because he has embraced a different story of the War and Reconstruction, one far more preoccupied with the excesses and corruption of the Northern occupiers.67 Relying primarily on secondary sources from an era when Dunning School narratives were dominant, rather than on modern historians, Rehnquist did his part to help revive for a contemporary audience a view of Reconstruction and its ending that restores some of the dignity of the South.68
Today, going well beyond the invocations of dignity in the sovereign immunity cases, Justice Scalia is apparently ready to make novel claims on structural principles of state sovereignty as though the Civil War never occurred. Last Term, Justice Scalia opened his blistering dissent in Arizona v. United States, which he read from the bench, with these words: “The United States is an indivisible ‘Union of sovereign States.’”69 He proceeded to excoriate the majority for depriving Arizona of “the defining characteristic of sovereignty: the power to exclude from the sovereign’s territory people who have no right to be there.”70 In the ensuing discussion of Arizona’s sovereignty, Justice Scalia cites Madison; the Kentucky and Virginia Resolutions; the Massachusetts Resolutions in Reply to Virginia; a 1758 treatise on the Law of Nations; and a case from 1837.71 The Civil War is nowhere to be found. It is as though the War did nothing at all to alter the valence and viability of arguments based “upon the principle of state-sovereignty.”72 Which is to say, it is as though the War’s meaning were its narrowest possible meaning—the one most protective of the dignity of the South.
III. Southern Dignity and Section 5
At trial in Shelby County, section 5’s defenders offered evidence that even though the coverage formula has not been altered in decades, it continues to do a rather effective job of covering those jurisdictions that have the worst ongoing (post-1982) records of violations of the VRA.73 To the dissenting judge on the panel below, Judge Stephen Williams, this seemed surprising and improbable. How could a formula based only on decades-old history accurately predict where discrimination, racially polarized voting, and so on, would be the most prevalent today? “[S]ometimes a skilled dart-thrower can hit the bull’s eye throwing a dart backwards over his shoulder,”74 he allowed, but in this case he thought Congress had not.
The question of how near or far the present trigger formula might be from some imagined “bull’s eye” is not my subject here. It is surely true that a different trigger formula might have covered even more of the present violations of the VRA across the United States—and that Congress declined to debate such a formula in part because it did not want to have a debate about which Members’ present-day districts are more racistthan others.75 Nonetheless, it is illuminating to think through the assumptions built into Judge Williams’s memorable image, especially in light of the panel majority’s conclusion that Congress indeed hit its target.
It seems that Judge Williams’s expectation is that history would notpredict present discrimination—that is, his expectation is that the geographic distribution of voting rights violations today would likely not match the old contours of the Confederate or Jim Crow South. That is why he analogizes the congressional trigger formula to a dart-thrower “throwing a dart backwards over his shoulder.”76 But is that really what is going on? Perhaps a better analogy, instead of throwing darts, would be that we are searching for an old house that used to be in a certain neighborhood. We discover that despite many renovations and transformations, the house is still there, in the same location where it always was. Perhaps this is unexpected, but it is surely not a shock. History shifts, and memory changes, but rarely, if ever, is the past entirely erased. As William Faulkner, the great novelist of the South who spent a lifetime exploring this theme, famously wrote: “The past is never dead. It’s not even past.”77
After the oral argument in Shelby County, one enterprising pair of researchers actually decided to try to answer the Chief Justice’s question with which this Essay began. They took a look at some explicit measures of racial attitudes and found that, using their preferred statistical technique, “the six fully covered states in the South are, by our measure, six of the seven most prejudiced in the nation.”78 I do not think Chief Justice Roberts would be at all impressed with this evidence if it were before him. Indeed, I am not even sure which way its inclusion would cut. The reason is that the Chief Justice’s question was not empirical. He was not asking whether the citizens of the South are, as a factual matter, “more racist” than the citizens of the North. Rather, he was asking whether the United States was making a claim that would amount to an insult, a dignitary harm, to the South as a region and to its people. Underneath his question was the suggestion that section 5’s trigger formula itself might amount to such a dignitary harm.
This is why Justice Kennedy, at oral argument, mused openly about the possibility of replacing the trigger formula with some mechanism of individualized, state-by-state judicial decisionmaking. In that event, a judge, not a formula, would decide whether extra oversight in the form of preclearance is required in a given jurisdiction.79 This approach, relying entirely on a so-called “pocket trigger” or “bail-in” mechanism,80 with no statutory formula, has a number of drawbacks, but one great virtue: it elides questions of regional dignity and historical memory. It facilitates an exclusive focus on present violations, and an end to the uncomfortable suggestion, currently inscribed in the United States Code, that some states have a long history of discrimination more intense than that of other states—and that this history lingers, in certain respects relevant to voting rights enforcement, up to the present day.
IV. The Present
There are a variety of options open to the Court in reconciling the VRA with its “new” federalism. The simplest solution is to uphold section 5 based on the record of post-1982 violations explored in detail by the court below, and to continue to allow jurisdictions to bail out of section 5 coverage81 if and when they wish to show that the past is dead. However, regardless of the outcome it reaches in Shelby County, the Court should find a way to reason about the case that avoids inscribing into the Constitution a principle of the equality, dignity, or “equal dignity” of the states. In post-1865 America, the roots of such a principle are to be found in the losing arguments of Reconstruction’s opponents. They saw outrageous regional insult and indignity and outrageous violations of state sovereignty in the federal statutes that began the work the VRA continues—and, indeed, in the very Reconstruction Amendments the Court is now interpreting, which they bitterly opposed. Particular Justices of the Court may well be unaware of either the roots or the implications of a principle of the equal dignity of the states—but that does little to alter either the roots or the implications, which are profound. To elevate a principle of the equal dignity of the states to the status of a constitutional constraint on the Reconstruction Power, in a case about federal protection for minority voting rights, would be to inscribe into the Constitution some of the core constitutional claims, unsuccessful even in their own time, of the defeated Confederacy and its apologists.
I doubt very much that the Justices’ motives match those of past advocates for the “dignity” of the South from either the end of Reconstruction or the era of massive resistance to civil rights. Instead, it seems likelier that some claims of both of those groups are finding their way into the law by a more circuitous route—a route that is a testament to those groups’ success in injecting their views of the Civil War, Reconstruction, and the dignity of the South into mainstream American historical memory. When most of the Rehnquist Court, and much of the present Court, encountered Reconstruction as schoolchildren in the 1940s, 50s, and early 60s, Dunning School narratives were utterly dominant; reunion between North and South on equal terms was framed as an unalloyed good.82 The conservative Justices then spent many politically formative years in a period in which a soft rhetoric of states’ rights and state sovereignty was part of the atmosphere of conservative politics, a highly successful accommodation of the politics of Southern whites.83 It is not surprising, in this light, that ideas of state dignity or sovereignty might hold some appeal for some Justices; nor is it surprising that they might be uncomfortable with federal legislation—section 5—that singles out the South for special federal oversight in a way that recalls Reconstruction and explicitly holds that the Jim Crow past is relevant in the present. None of this alters the valence, or the implications, of the step the Court seems poised to take. Even if they are not doing it intentionally or knowingly, constraining Congress’s Reconstruction Power with a principle of the equal dignity of the states—and most pointedly, the Southern states—would substantially advance the grand historical project of the original advocates of the equal dignity of the South.
This particular way of paring back Congress’s Reconstruction Power is all the more pointed because, in fact, federal law routinely treats one state differently from another in ways large and small, because states differ in their circumstances in innumerable respects. Compared to its neighbors, one state might have more military bases, more native Alaskans, more citizens without health insurance, or a more congenial mountain redoubt for the permanent storage of the nation’s radioactive waste.84 An equal dignity of the states principle would presumably continue to allow such differences in treatment where circumstances warrant. Therefore, to apply an equal dignity of the states principle in Shelby County to strike down section 5 would be to assert that the one salient difference in circumstances among the states that the Constitution requires Congress to ignore is the fact that certain states recently spent most of a century openly defying the Reconstruction Amendments by denying their minority citizens the right to vote.
Conclusion
The great constitutional theorist Charles Black observed that one of the profound effects of the Fourteenth Amendment was to deny each state the right to decide who is a citizen of the state and who is not: federal law is now the exclusive arbiter of who is a citizen of either Massachusetts or Mississippi.85 This, Black argued, is “another nail in the coffin of the theory that our States are ‘sovereign.’”86 He added: “That coffin can use all the nails it can get, because it yawns every now and then, on some inauspicious midnight, to give up its undead, clad perhaps in the senatorial toga of Calhoun.”87
Black’s writing aims for the universal and the transcendent in our Constitution. He also writes from the particular point of view of a person born in Texas in 1915, who attended the university where I now teach in a world before Sweatt v. Painter.88 Then as now, the Fourteenth Amendment was the law. But the University of Texas in those segregated days had prominent statues of four leaders of the Confederacy situated along its grassy south mall, at the bottom of which an impressive fountain was dedicated to a certain conception of the dignity of the South: “To the men and women of the Confederacy who fought with valor and suffered with fortitude that states rights be maintained and who not dismayed by defeat nor discouraged by misrule builded from the ruins of a devastating war a greater South.”89 Today, those Confederate statues, that fountain, and its bold dedication, are still here.90 Today they are joined on the campus by a number of competing monuments and inscriptions, such as a statue of the Rev. Martin Luther King, Jr., erected in a different era with a different message. However, pace Judge Williams and his memorable dart-thrower, the Confederate statues have not scattered—they have not wandered off to a random assortment of locales such as Massachusetts and Maine. They remain right where they were built. They run with the land.
For citizens of the states and covered jurisdictions of the former Confederacy, there is a certain honesty, even a certain dignity—albeit not the kind of dignity this Essay has heretofore discussed—in facing the past dead on. It is no small thing to acknowledge squarely and repudiate the full century of resistance after 1865 to the Constitution that was forged in the War—and all the continuing reverberations of that resistance in politics, economics, and law. The past is never dead. It’s not even past. And some of the ideas that animated apologists for the Confederacy during that long, dark chapter, from the death of Reconstruction through the resistance to the VRA, refuse to die. “States’ rights” may finally rest in peace, but now the sovereign “equal dignity” of the states seems poised to rise, zombie-like, in clothes just new enough to avoid any obvious shades of the “senatorial toga of Calhoun.”
It is time, long past time, to inter these concepts for good and let them rest with the Confederate dead.
Joseph Fishkin is an Assistant Professor, University of Texas School of Law. He would like to thank Jack Balkin, Joseph Blocher, Justin Driver, Shelley Fisher Fishkin, Willy Forbath, Cary Franklin, Heather Gerken, Justin Levitt, and Zachary Price for helpful comments.
Preferred citation: Joseph Fishkin, The Dignity of the South, 123 Yale L.J. Online 175 (2013), http://yalelawjournal.org/forum/the-dignity-of-the-south.