Administrative Severability Clauses
abstract. Severability clauses can help administrative agencies minimize the damage caused by judicial review and can make the regulatory environment more efficient, participatory, and predictable. Yet agencies rarely include these clauses in their rules because courts tend to treat administrative rules with severability clauses the same as those without. Courts have treated administrative severability clauses in this way largely because they have mistakenly analogized them to severability clauses contained in statutes. While Congress routinely includes severability clauses in statutes that are drafted in distinct iterations, by different committees with legislative staff who often lack the time and expertise to consider the clauses’ potential ramifications, administrative agencies use these clauses with more care. This Article proposes a Chevron-style deference framework for administrative severability clauses. Under this framework, after a reviewing court has set aside a challenged regulatory provision, the court should defer to a promulgating agency’s opinion on severability as expressed through a severability clause, unless the remainder of the rule itself would suffer from legal defects resulting from the court’s invalidation of the challenged provisions. This framework would better promote the overarching goals of administrative law than do current judicial doctrine and agency practice.
authors. Charles W. Tyler is a law clerk to the Honorable Goodwin Liu, Associate Justice, Supreme Court of California; Yale Law School, J.D. 2013. E. Donald Elliott is Adjunct Professor of Law, Yale Law School, and Senior of Counsel, Covington & Burling LLP. For their suggestions and encouragement, we thank Ali Deich, Arthur Ewenczyk, Heather Gerken, Abbe Gluck, Daniel Hemel, Chris Hu, Rob Katz, Daniel Markovits, Jerry Mashaw, Tracey Meares, Ben Moskowitz, Janice Ong, Nick Parrillo, Judith Resnik, Stan Richards, Rebecca Schonberg, Travis Silva, Andrew Tutt, and Ke Wu. The views set forth in this Article are the personal views of the authors alone and do not necessarily reflect the views of the institutions with which they are affiliated or their clients.
Introduction
“Judicial review controls administrative action in the same way that tornadoes control the rice crop in Arkansas: they appear unpredictably, wreak havoc, and then depart.”
—Jerry Mashaw1
This Article explores a topic overlooked in legal scholarship: severability clauses in administrative regulations. “Administrative severability clauses,” as we call them, are provisions of administrative rules that clarify whether an agency intends for a rule to remain in effect if a court were to invalidate a portion of the rule.2 A recent example, to which we return at several points in the Article, helps to illustrate the function and potential importance of these clauses.
The Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) recently published a proposed rule, commonly referred to as the “Clean Power Plan.”3 Political analysts have dubbed it the “centerpiece” of the Obama Administration’s strategy on climate change.4 The Clean Power Plan aspires to reduce greenhouse gas emissions by thirty percent below 2005 levels before 2030 by requiring states to meet certain carbon pollution emissions goals.5 To set those goals, the EPA has identified four measures, which the proposed rule terms “building blocks” and which the agency has determined together make up the “best system of emission reduction.”6 The building blocks are: (1) making existing coal plants more efficient; (2) using existing gas plants more effectively; (3) increasing reliance on renewable and nuclear energy sources; and (4) improving end-use energy efficiency.7 Like many environmental regulations, the Clean Power Plan is an example of cooperative federalism. While states are free to formulate their own plans for reducing greenhouse gas emissions, they must implement plans that will at least match the emissions reductions that the EPA has determined could be achieved by implementing the four building blocks.
Since the EPA’s emissions goals are derived from the building blocks, regulated entities opposed to the Clean Power Plan—and there are many—are likely to challenge the building blocks in court. The agency may therefore be concerned that a court will vacate the entire Clean Power Plan if a court finds that just one of the building blocks is invalid. Likely in order to manage this risk, the EPA inserted a severability clause into the proposed rule’s text. The clause provides that if a court invalidates one or more of the building blocks, the remainder of the rule should stay in effect, and the states’ adjusted emissions targets should be based on the remainder of the building blocks.8
The Clean Power Plan’s severability clause will become relevant in litigation if a discontent stakeholder challenges the rule and the reviewing court sets one or more of the building blocks aside. The court will then have to make what we call the “severability decision”; it will have to choose between invalidating only the challenged provision, invalidating the challenged provision and several other provisions, or invalidating the entire rule.
In the absence of the severability clause, the severability decision requires a reviewing court to apply a fairly well-established doctrinal framework. But when a rule contains a severability clause, such as the one contained in the Clean Power Plan, it raises an important question that courts and commentators have largely overlooked. Who should decide whether an invalidated provision of a rule is severable? We call this the “who-decides question.” The who-decides question implicates the level of deference that a reviewing court should give to a promulgating agency’s opinion on the severability of a rule expressed in a severability clause.
Once raised, the who-decides question involves some of the most basic issues in administrative law—issues about the allocation of decision-making authority in the federal government. When an agency has expressed its view on severability, should a court defer to the agency, as it would when an agency reasonably interprets an ambiguous statute pursuant to a congressional delegation of lawmaking authority?9 If a rule is within an agency’s bailiwick because it was promulgated pursuant to a statutory delegation of authority, does the severability of the rule also fall within its bailiwick, or is the severability decision intrinsically within the judicial power? Does a severability clause constitute an interpretation of the agency’s own rule, qualifying it for Seminole Rock deference (that is, deference accorded to an agency’s interpretation of its own regulations)?10 If courts should give some measure of deference to an agency’s opinion on severability, how much? Do some of the agency’s statements on severability, but not others, deserve deference?
The visibility of the Clean Power Plan’s severability clause notwithstanding, these questions remain mostly under-theorized. Until the last two decades, only three articles had been devoted to severability doctrine in either statutes or rules.11 And courts have analyzed the doctrine in little more depth. Former Chief Judge of the Ninth Circuit John Clifford Wallace once lamented that “[t]he test for severability has been stated often but rarely explained.”12 To be sure, theoretical analysis of the severability of statutes has become more robust in recent years. The severability doctrine has figured prominently in recent debates in both Congress13 and the Supreme Court,14 and scholars have responded with full articles on the subject.15 But the analysis of administrative severability doctrine continues to lag behind. There have been no law review articles addressing severability in administrative law, and we have found only one secondary source even mentioning the difference between the severability analyses in the statutory and administrative contexts.16
The dearth of scholarship is probably due, in part, to the answer that the agencies and the courts currently give to the who-decides question. Agencies tend to include severability clauses in their rules infrequently and sporadically. Even when an agency does include a severability clause in a rule, the current doctrine suggests that a reviewing court should not defer to it. Thus, the current judicial doctrine and agency practice regarding administrative severability represents one possible allocation of decision-making authority: namely, courts make the severability decision de novo without regard to the existence of a severability clause. As a result, these relatively insignificant clauses have not received much attention from commentators.
This Article maintains that current judicial doctrine and agency practice regarding severability are misguided. We think that courts should defer to administrative severability clauses and that agencies should more frequently include them in their rules. We propose a deference framework for administrative severability clauses, similar to the Chevron and Seminole Rock frameworks, under which both courts and agencies would play a role in the severability decision.
This Article proceeds in three Parts. Part I explains the severability decision and the who-decides question in more detail. In Part I.A, we discuss the current severability doctrine. As we explain, the doctrinal test for severability consists of two questions: (1) whether the promulgating agency would have intended for the remainder of a regulation to stay in effect; and (2) whether the remainder of the regulation is workable.
In Part I.B, we consider which institution—the reviewing court or the promulgating agency—is best suited to answer each of these questions. We conclude that when a promulgating agency has expressed an opinion on severability through a severability clause, it has offered an answer to the intent and workability questions. Because the promulgating agency is better equipped than a court to assess both its own intent on severability and the workability of a regulatory remainder, the agency’s answers to those questions deserve deference. This preliminary discussion will serve as helpful background for our thesis that the current doctrine and practice on severability clauses misallocates decision-making authority and for our proposal of a deference framework for administrative severability clauses.
Part II describes the current judicial doctrine and agency practice on administrative severability clauses and shows that the doctrine and practice do not follow the allocation of decision-making authority suggested in Part I. In Part II.A, we explain that federal courts for decades have declined to take severability clauses in statutes at face value. We then explain that the doctrinal treatment of statutory severability clauses has been applied to administrative severability clauses because courts have reflexively analogized the two.
In Part II.B, we explain that agencies do not generally include severability clauses in their rules. Instead, agencies usually offer their opinions on severability only when required to do so in litigation. Our research suggests that agencies behave in this way because promulgating severability clauses through notice-and-comment procedures often entails significant ex ante and ex post costs that courts do not reward through greater deference. In light of the discussion in Part I, we conclude that judicial doctrine and agency practice regarding severability are misguided. Courts should develop a framework for deferring to administrative severability clauses that would create greater incentives for agencies to include severability clauses in their rules.
Part III outlines our proposed deference framework for administrative severability clauses. In Part III.A, we debunk the primary doctrinal obstacle to such a framework. We argue that it is a mistake to evaluate administrative severability clauses through the same prism used to evaluate statutory severability clauses. Congress and the agencies have different institutional capacities and incentives. In Congress, severability clauses are often thrown in to far-reaching statutes that are drafted in several iterations, by several committees with legislative staff members who often lack the time and expertise to consider the clauses’ potential ramifications adequately. By contrast, administrative agencies are more unified organizations that operate in a narrower regulatory space and have staff with greater expertise; agencies can therefore devote more resources to considering the potential consequences of a severability clause. As a result, administrative severability clauses are a more useful guide to the severability decision than statutory severability clauses. The analogy between statutory and administrative severability clauses is thus misplaced.
In Part III.B, we articulate a framework that courts can use to evaluate whether to sever an invalid provision from a rule containing a severability clause. When a court invalidates a provision of an administrative rule containing a severability clause, the court should first determine whether the remainder of the rule contains residual legal defects. For example, the court should determine whether the remainder of the rule is unconstitutional, ultra vires, arbitrary and capricious, or otherwise unlawful. If possible, the court should remove those residual legal defects by setting aside additional provisions of the rule. The court, however, should defer to the agency’s severability decision if it determines that the remainder does not contain inextricable, residual legal defects. We also argue that courts should give Chevron-style deference only to administrative severability clauses, rather than informal agency opinions on severability. We acknowledge that agencies should be provided with some incentive to opine on severability before litigation commences because informal agency opinions on severability will often be better than no opinion at all. To encourage agencies to clarify their positions on severability, even if not through notice-and-comment procedures, we propose that courts give Skidmore deference to informal agency actions, such as litigation briefs, that opine on severability.17
The use of severability clauses in regulations is a fairly nascent experiment in administrative law. While the case law on these devices is problematic, it is not so entrenched that it could not easily be changed by a panel of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit (D.C. Circuit) or the U.S. Supreme Court. This Article shows that deference to severability clauses in rules would have significant benefits for complex and ambitious regulatory schemes like the EPA’s Clean Power Plan. Since the EPA is scheduled to promulgate the final rule implementing the Plan in the summer of 2015, now is an auspicious time for the courts to reconsider their approach to administrative severability clauses.
I. severability in administrative law
A. The Severability Decision
Questions of severability arise after a discontented stakeholder challenges a provision of a statute or regulation and the reviewing court invalidates the challenged provision as unconstitutional, ultra vires, arbitrary and capricious, supported by insubstantial evidence, or otherwise unlawful. Having invalidated the challenged provision, the reviewing court’s scrutiny turns to what we call the statutory or regulatory “remainder”—the part of the statute or rule that would remain absent the invalid provision. Assessing the remainder gives rise to the severability decision—the remedial choice between invalidating the challenged provision alone, the challenged provision and some of the remainder, or the entire statute or rule.
Courts and commentators have spent a good amount of time and energy theorizing the severability decision. The Supreme Court has developed a fairly useful test for making that decision. That test was first developed as the Court considered the severability of congressional statutes. But, as we shall see, the Supreme Court and the D.C. Circuit have repurposed the test for use in determining the severability of administrative regulations.
1. The Severability of Statutes
The leading case laying out the Court’s modern severability doctrine is Alaska Airlines, Inc. v. Brock.18 In that case, several airlines challenged the employee protection program provisions of the Airline Deregulation Act.19 Following the Court’s landmark decision in Chadha,20 which held legislative veto provisions unconstitutional, the Court held that the Deregulation Act’s legislative veto provision was unconstitutional and that the challenged provision was severable from the statutory remainder.21 Writing for the Court, Justice Blackmun explained: “Unless [1] it is evident that the Legislature would not have enacted those provisions which are within its power, independently of that which is not, the invalid part may be dropped if [2] what is left is fully operative as a law.”22 Alaska Airlines holds that courts should ask two questions when considering how to remedy invalid statutory provisions.23
First, would Congress have enacted the remainder without the unlawful provision? Call this the “intent question.” To answer this question, the reviewing court investigates Congress’s intent at the time it enacted the relevant statute. Ideally, the reviewing court would find evidence of Congress’s actual intent—that is, evidence that Congress considered the possibility that the challenged provision would be struck down and intended the remainder of the statute to stay in effect (or not) under those circumstances. Evidence of actual intent, however, is often unavailable. In the absence of such evidence, courts look for evidence of putative intent—that is, evidence of what Congress would have wanted had it thought about the possibility that the challenged provision would be struck down. So the intent question often requires a counterfactual inquiry. It requires the reviewing court to recreate the bargain between stakeholders that led to the statute’s final text to determine what the lawmakers likely would have wanted had they known that the reviewing court would strike down the challenged provision.24
The second question that courts are required to ask is whether the statutory remainder is “fully operative as a law.” In other words, is the remainder workable? Call this the “workability question.” To answer this question, the court must determine whether the statute is “capable of functioning independently” of the challenged provision.25 Often courts answering this question will consider the interdependence of the relevant statute’s provisions. If the reviewing court answers either question in the negative, it will strike down the entire statute.
2. The Severability of Administrative Rules
The Court’s test for the severability of administrative regulations repurposes the Alaska Airlines statutory severability test. The first Supreme Court case to assess the severability of administrative regulations was K-Mart Corp. v. Cartier, where the Court considered whether a subsection of a Customs Service regulation violated the Tariff Act of 1930.26 The Tariff Act prohibited the importation of foreign merchandise bearing a trademark owned by a United States’ citizen (or a corporation organized within the United States) without the owner’s written consent. The Customs Service regulation permitted foreign manufacturers to import trademarked goods into the United States if they had received the U.S. trademark owner’s authorization to use its trademark, but not necessarily its authorization to import goods bearing the trademark into the United States.27 The Court held that the regulation violated the Tariff Act.28 Writing for the majority, Justice Kennedy reasoned that the invalid subsection of the Customs Service regulation was severable from the remainder because invalidating the subsection would “not impair the function of the statute as a whole” and because “there is no indication that the regulation would not have been passed but for its inclusion.”29 Although Justice Kennedy’s analysis did not cite any cases, he applied the same test for the severability of statutes that the Court had articulated in Alaska Airlines just one year earlier.
Since the K-Mart decision, courts have applied the same test to determine the severability of administrative provisions and the severability of statutory provisions.30 For example, in Davis County Solid Waste Management v. EPA, the D.C. Circuit reconsidered the issue of whether an invalid provision of an EPA rule could be severed from the remainder of the rule.31 As in the case of statutes, the court held that severability depends on: (1) whether there is any “‘indication that the regulation would not have been passed but for [the] inclusion’ of the [invalid] standards” and (2) whether severance would “‘impair the function of [the remainder of the rule].’”32 Here again, severability was made to depend on the intent and workability questions.
B. The Who-Decides Question
The current severability doctrine may be useful for making the severability decision when an agency has not included a severability clause in its rule. But courts and commentators have generally not considered which institution should make that decision when an agency has included a severability clause in a rule. This is the who-decides question.
Perhaps the simple answer to the who-decides question is that the reviewing court must decide. After all, the severability decision concerns a remedial issue in litigation. Courts are the “tornadoes,” in Mashaw’s analogy, and they must determine what is left in their wake.33 But this simplistic answer overlooks the ways in which a severability clause could affect a reviewing court’s severability analysis.
When an agency includes a severability clause in a rule, it states whether it would promulgate the rule without certain portions. More specifically, a severability clause can be seen as the agency’s affirmative answer to the two component questions of the severability test: the agency (1) intends for the remainder to stay in effect; and (2) believes that the remainder is workable. In light of the agency’s opinion on severability, the question becomes whether a reviewing court should defer to that opinion or substitute its own judgment for that of the agency.
In this way, when an agency has included a severability clause in a rule, the who-decides question raises questions familiar from scholarly discussions of the Chevron doctrine. Just as we need a doctrine for determining whether a reviewing court should defer to an agency’s interpretation of a federal statute, so too we need a doctrine for determining whether a reviewing court should defer to an agency’s opinion on severability expressed through a severability clause. We now consider whether a reviewing court should defer to a promulgating agency’s answer to the intent and workability questions.
1. Agency Intent
The first question for the reviewing court to consider is whether the promulgating agency would have wanted the remainder to stay in effect had it contemplated that a court would invalidate the challenged provision.34 On its face, an administrative severability clause is the agency’s affirmative answer to that question.35 A typical administrative severability clause, for example, reads as follows: “The provisions of this part are separate and severable from one another. If any provision is stayed or determined to be invalid, it is the Commission’s intention that the remaining provisions shall continue in effect.”36
The case for judicial deference on the intent question is straightforward. The regulatory text is strong evidence of the agency’s intent.37 When an administrative rule contains a severability clause, it is odd for a court to conduct an independent inquiry into whether the agency intended for the remainder to stay in effect. To do so amounts to a search for the agency’s putative intent when the rule already contains a statement of the agency’s actual intent.
Moreover, when a court searches for putative intent under these circumstances, it likely lacks a coherent objective. Recall that the inquiry into an agency’s putative intent attempts to recreate the bargain between stakeholders that gave rise to the regulation. But the court must suppose that the severability clause, as part of the regulatory text, is itself part of the regulatory bargain.38 It is therefore questionable whether the court could properly find that the regulatory bargain implies that the challenged provision is inseverable. Consequently, we think there is a compelling case for judicial deference to the plain meaning of a severability clause with respect to the promulgating agency’s intent.
2. Workability of the Remainder
The second question for the reviewing court to consider is whether the remainder is workable. Unlike the intent question, severability clauses do not always address this aspect of the severability decision expressly. Still, it is fair to read a severability clause as providing the agency’s opinion on workability because workability is such a prominent consideration—perhaps the most prominent consideration—in the severability decision. Therefore, like the intent question, courts should give deference to the agency’s opinion on workability when it is expressed in a severability clause. Below, we provide four reasons that the regulatory environment would benefit if courts gave deference to the agency’s answer to the workability question, expressed through an administrative severability clause.
a. Expertise
Agencies are often better equipped than courts to determine whether a regulatory remainder is workable because they have greater subject-matter expertise. Agency expertise has several sources. First, agencies are highly specialized. Federal agencies are differentiated by subject matter, and each agency’s staff spends most of its time and resources addressing issues related to the agency’s particular substantive domain. As a result, the staff becomes more knowledgeable about the policies and methods that work in that domain.39 Second, agency personnel usually include staff members who have advanced training in fields such as economic analysis and the scientific disciplines. The EPA’s staff, for example, includes scientists and economists tasked with evaluating the EPA’s regulatory and enforcement efforts. Similarly, the Securities and Exchange Commission employs economists and lawyers with advanced training in economics to determine the best rules for detecting and preventing securities fraud.40 Finally, executive-branch agencies are subject to review by the Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs (OIRA), whose staff of economists and other experts requires agencies to justify major rulemakings through cost-benefit analysis.41 “[J]udges,” by contrast, “are not expert in the field.”42 They are generalists who decide cases across various subject matters. Judges also have relatively limited resources and staff who rarely have highly advanced training in economics and related disciplines. Finally, courts have limited investigative powers and must decide each case based on the facts that are presented by the parties.
An agency’s superior subject-matter expertise typically means that the agency is better able than courts to make informed policy judgments. This is one reason why, under Chevron, a reviewing court will defer to an agency’s reasonable interpretation of an ambiguous statute that the agency is charged with implementing. Similarly, agencies are better equipped to determine whether a regulatory remainder is workable because, in many instances, this inquiry requires a deep understanding of the subject matter of the regulation itself.
Consider, for example, the Clean Power Plan. As explained above, the Plan sets carbon pollution emissions goals for the states by identifying four “building blocks,” which the agency has determined together make up the “best system of emission reduction.”43 The Plan’s severability clause provides that if a court sets aside any of the building blocks, then the remainder of the Plan should stay in effect.44 If a federal court invalidates one of the building blocks, the court must determine whether the remainder of the regulation is workable in the absence of the invalid provision. This inquiry inherently involves determining whether the remaining building blocks could sensibly be thought to constitute the “best system of emission reduction.”45 Put plainly, this is a question that the EPA—the agency with experience implementing the Clean Air Act—is best equipped to answer.46
The Clean Power Plan is not unique in this respect. Many regulatory schemes are very technical and complex, and they often involve highly interdependent provisions.47 In fact, every indication is that regulatory schemes are becoming more complex each year.48 Further, as we explain below, agencies rarely use severability clauses. Thus, when an agency does include a severability clause in a rule, it may indicate that the rule is especially technical and complex and that the agency fears that a court may incorrectly associate complexity with the rule’s supposed inability to function absent a challenged provision.
In light of the highly technical and complex nature of modern regulation and the agency practice of only rarely including severability clauses in rules, generalist judges should defer to an expert agency that has offered its opinion through an administrative severability clause on the workability of a regulatory remainder. A court should not substitute its policy judgment for the agency’s.49 Instead, courts should defer to the expert agency’s opinion on whether the remainder is workable.
b. Accountability
Deference to the agency’s answer to the workability question as expressed in a severability clause also makes the regulatory scheme more accountable to the public. To understand the significance of democratic accountability in this context, one must realize that the severability decision imposes upon the public a regulatory scheme not approved in its exact form by the agency. It has long been a fundamental principle of administrative law that a reviewing court may not affirm an agency decision on a ground different from that adopted by the agency to justify its action.50 This principle, generally called the Chenery doctrine, reflects the fact that Congress has given the authority to make rules to the expert agency and not to the court. When the court affirms on a ground not adopted by the agency, it invades the proper province of the agency by substituting its judgment for the agency’s. Severability raises similar issues. When a court upholds a portion of an administrative rule but sets aside others, the court leaves in place a regulatory scheme different from the scheme promulgated by the agency. And if the reviewing court sets aside the remainder, it creates a regulatory scheme (or perhaps deregulatory scheme) that the agency purposefully rejected by promulgating the rule.
These considerations do not lead us to the conclusion, which at least one scholar has reached, that severing a challenged provision of a rule constitutes unconstitutional judicial lawmaking.51 Rather, they underscore the importance of allocating the workability question to the institution with the greater democratic pedigree. The workability question implicates compromises among constituents’ interests—compromises that led to the creation of various regulatory objectives ultimately memorialized in the final rule. More direct lines of accountability to constituents provide agencies with a better understanding of these compromises and therefore with a better understanding of whether a regulatory remainder will adequately serve those regulatory objectives.52
Many scholars of administrative law have argued that agencies have more direct lines of accountability to the public than the courts.53 Agency procedural requirements for rulemaking are one line of accountability. When an agency disseminates a proposed rule, including one containing a severability clause, it must provide a “[g]eneral notice of proposed rule making”54 and “give interested persons an opportunity to participate in the rule making through submission of written data, views, or arguments.”55
These procedural mechanisms for maintaining accountability between the public and the agencies can be significant to an agency’s decision to promulgate a severability clause because the severability of regulatory provisions is often sufficiently important to induce stakeholders to comment formally. For example, in a comment on a proposed Fish and Wildlife Service (FWS) Rule, the Alaska Oil and Gas Association (AOGA) wrote:
Regardless of the form of the final rule, AOGA urges FWS to make a finding of severability. A severability finding would determine that the provisions of this rule, and the various applications of the rule, are distinct and severable from one another. . . . A severability finding would ensure that if any provision or application of the 4(d) rule is stayed or invalidated, such a stay or invalidation will not affect other provisions or applications to other persons or circumstances.56
When the public does participate, agencies are required to respond to the public’s comments in a reasoned fashion.57 Moreover, an agency’s final rule must be a “logical outgrowth” of the agency’s proposed rule,58 and the agency must address relevant and significant comments raised during the rulemaking in its statement of basis and purpose.59 These notice-and-comment requirements serve to “reintroduce public participation and fairness to affected parties after governmental authority has been delegated to unrepresentative agencies.”60 Notice-and-comment requirements thus give the public an opportunity to exercise accountability over an agency’s decision to promulgate a severability clause.
Courts are less responsive to the wishes of the President and Congress than federal administrative agencies.61 The federal courts are subject to a variety of controls by the democratic branches, including control over the federal courts’ budget and jurisdiction. But at the level of individual judges, the political branches have no official influence over the decisions of courts in particular cases.62 Of course, the President with the advice and consent of the Senate appoints individual judges. But once confirmed, federal judges enjoy lifetime appointments and undiminished pay, and they can be removed by the political branches only through the Constitution’s onerous impeachment procedures. Indeed, part of the attraction of placing some decisions in the hands of federal judges is that they enjoy a great degree of removal from the whims and impulses of the political branches and of public opinion.
To be sure, one should not overestimate the democratic responsiveness of administrative agencies to the popular will. Unlike agency heads, career agency staff members are not subject to the political pressures imposed by Congress or the President.63 Many statutes also provide exemptions to participation-enhancing notice-and-comment procedures. The Administrative Procedure Act (APA), which controls agency procedures when a more specific organic act does not, exempts an agency from undertaking notice and comment for rules regulating certain subject matters, such as foreign affairs, national security, and internal personnel matters.64 There are also exemptions if the rule is an interpretive rule or policy statement, or when the agency has good cause not to follow notice-and-comment requirements.65 Further, even when agencies do follow notice-and-comment procedures, these procedures are often more a means for ensuring favorable judicial review than they are a means of facilitating genuine public participation.66
But even if we cannot be uniformly sanguine about the power of formal procedural requirements to ensure genuine accountability and participation, we still maintain that agencies are also more responsive than the courts to representatives in the legislative and executive branches.67 The heads of executive-branch agencies are appointed and removable by the President. The heads of so-called “independent” agencies are also appointed by the President (though they can usually be removed only for cause), and the budgets of such agencies are prepared by the Office of Management and Budget.68
Agencies are also subject to oversight by Congress. They are subject to the budgetary control of congressional committees, and their heads frequently testify before Congress. As a result of these formal and other informal mechanisms of oversight, William Eskridge and Lauren Baer have argued that “agencies usually have institutionally superior access to the original expectations of the legislators . . . . [and] also have better knowledge than courts about current congressional expectations.”69 Further, some theorists posit that procedural requirements on regulation, such as notice-and-comment procedures, are means for Congress to intervene more easily when an agency is not adequately addressing the concerns of powerful constituencies.70
In short, the public and representatives in the executive and legislative branches maintain comparatively robust controls for holding agencies accountable in relation to the courts. Thus, when an agency opines on the workability of a regulatory remainder, it is in a better position than a court to know how the remainder will affect citizens and other entities.
c. Rule of Law
When a reviewing court defers to an administrative severability clause, it also promotes two important aspects of the rule of law: predictability and stability.71
Predictability benefits both agencies and regulated entities by encouraging efficient investment.72 When regulated entities evaluate which resources to invest in complying with the law most efficiently, an important consideration, especially for sophisticated actors, is how courts will treat recently promulgated administrative rules. If certain provisions of a rule are unlikely to survive judicial review, then entities may make different investment choices from the choices they would make if the provisions were likely to survive.
Similarly, greater predictability in the law allows agencies to determine how to use rulemaking resources most efficiently. Without severability, the probability that a court will set aside any particular provision is partly a function of the probability that a court will set aside any other provision in the same rule. Thus, the assessment of how best to regulate (for an agency) or how best to comply with the law (for regulated entities) is to some extent a function of how likely a court is to find potentially unlawful provisions severable. An agency’s regulatory choices, for example, will depend on the probability it assigns to the possibility that a court will set aside certain provisions. If an agency is fairly certain that a court will defer to a severability clause, however, it may choose to promulgate a set of controversial regulations as a single rule rather than dispersing the regulations across several rules.
By adhering to a deference framework for administrative severability clauses, courts would mitigate some of the uncertainty in this probabilistic assessment. This point follows from the timing in which a severability clause appears in the interbranch dialogue. While a reviewing court can determine the workability of a regulatory remainder only after invalidating a challenged provision in litigation, an agency can use a severability clause to answer the workability question at the time the final rule is promulgated. So if federal courts deferred to severability clauses, the workability question would be one less element of possible uncertainty in the law.
Judicial deference to administrative severability clauses also promotes greater stability in regulatory schemes. A “remand-and-repromulgation cycle,” as we call it, occurs when a regulation passes back and forth between an agency and the courts. If an agency could reliably influence how a reviewing court would make the severability decision by including a severability clause in a rule, then it could reduce the number of times it must re-promulgate a regulatory remainder that a court has erroneously invalidated.73
Reducing these cycles would save agencies and regulated entities costs caused by legal flux.74 Agencies would save scarce resources in two ways. Ex ante, an agency’s drafting costs will be reduced because, assured in the knowledge that a severability clause will prevent the vacatur of an entire rulemaking, the agency will not have to engage in as rigorous of an assessment of the likelihood that each provision of a rule will be struck down. In this way, judicial deference to administrative severability clauses would partially offset some of the drawbacks associated with agency ossification.75 Ex post, agencies will save costs associated with re-promulgating rules already put through notice and comment.76 These costs are significant. One study, which one of the authors and Peter Schuck conducted in 1989, concluded that post-remand proceedings at the agency level took an average of seventeen months to complete.77
True, to receive deference on its answer to the workability question, the agency must draft a severability clause and take it through notice and comment. This process involves non-negligible costs, especially when the regulatory scheme is highly technical or complex. The agency may also incur costs associated with litigation over the meaning and scope of the severability clause.78 But on average these costs pale in comparison to the average costs of redrafting a rule and taking it back through notice and comment.
Reducing the incidence of remand-and-repromulgation cycles would also save costs for regulated entities. A regulated entity, relying on an unchallenged portion of a rule and caught in such a cycle, must first adapt to the agency’s rule, readapt to a regulatory vacuum after vacatur, and adapt for a third time to the original rule’s valid provisions after the agency re-promulgates those provisions.79 But if a court’s deference to an administrative severability clause prevented the court from erroneously invalidating the remainder, then the regulated entity would only need to adjust once.
Despite an administrative severability clause, there may be times when the remainder may turn out to be unworkable. This might occur, for example, when the agency does not correctly foresee what part of the rule might be struck down or how the regulatory remainder might function in the absence of the invalid portion. In these circumstances, a court’s deference to the severability clause may entail additional costs for regulated entities. In particular, regulated entities relying on an unchallenged portion of a rule will have to change their behavior when the agency first promulgates the rule and also when the agency changes the rule after deciding that the remainder is unworkable. However, these occasions are likely to be rare for two reasons. First, the agency’s expertise with respect to the workability question suggests that when the agency includes a severability clause, the remainder of the statute will be workable. Second, if agencies (and commenters) know that their judgments about severability are likely to carry dispositive weight with the courts in the future, they can be expected to devote more time and attention to these issues. This will lead to more accurate projections of workability. Together, these considerations suggest that the aggregate costs of correcting for ill-conceived severability clauses are still likely outweighed by the cost-savings of preventing remand-and-repromulgation cycles.
Bearing in mind that courts currently do not defer to administrative severability clauses, one might also argue that there is a certain irony in advocating for change in the law as a way of making the law more stable.80 As the Supreme Court has explained in a different context, “[w]hat is of paramount importance is that Congress be able to legislate against a background of clear interpretive rules, so that it may know the effect of the language it adopts.”81 One might then think that courts should not change their treatment of administrative severability clauses because lawyers in the agencies should have a stable background against which to draft administrative rules.
If, however, an agency could reliably predict whether a court will defer to a severability clause, then the agency could reliably predict “the effect of the language it adopts.”82 While changing the doctrine would disrupt the judicial background against which agencies currently regulate, the change would ultimately give the agencies more control over the consequences of their rules. We therefore advocate a change in the secondary rules of administrative law to make the primary rules more stable.83
d. Efficiency
Finally, if agency regulatory (or, for that matter, deregulatory) actions are generally socially beneficial, then judicial deference to the agency’s answer to the workability question promotes the development of efficient rules.84 When a court erroneously invalidates an entire rule that the agency would not itself rescind, society bears the costs associated with a “regulatory gap” (or, in the case of deregulation, a “regulatory glut”) between invalidation and re-promulgation of the regulatory remainder. Moreover, this gap or glut may prove indefinitely long because agencies are sometimes able to promulgate a rule that they cannot, for political or fiscal reasons, later re-promulgate.85 For example, the inter-state air pollution rules were upheld by the Supreme Court in EPA v. EME Homer City Generation, L.P.86 after almost a twenty-year delay stretching back over three presidential administrations to the 1998 NOx SIP call.
Another potential efficiency gain, which is more controversial, derives from the fact that judicial deference to administrative severability clauses promotes dynamic agency interpretations of statutes.87 If courts would generally defer to administrative severability clauses, then a promulgating agency, knowing that a reviewing court is unlikely to vacate the entire rule, can more freely promulgate regulatory provisions that interpret statutes in new ways. As a consequence, the agency can more dynamically interpret statutes with rules containing a severability clause than rules without.88 The Clean Power Plan provides a good example of this phenomenon. Some experts doubt that a final rule based on the Clean Power Plan would be a valid exercise of the agency’s delegated authority under the Clean Air Act.89 The EPA is aware of these criticisms, and one aspect of its strategy for dealing with them was to include the severability clause, hoping that a reviewing court will defer to that clause if the court sets aside one or more of the four building blocks.
One potential rejoinder to the efficiency argument is that severability clauses make controversial rules more likely to be partially set aside, either because (1) expressing a position on the severability of a particular provision puts a target on the tenuous provision; or (2) courts are more willing to invalidate regulatory provisions when they need not invalidate the entire rule. On this view, even someone who thinks that agency actions generally conduce to the social good may thus conclude that an agency should not include a severability clause in a rule that is likely to be litigated because doing so makes a regulatory provision more likely to be set aside.
With respect to the first concern, we doubt that agency opinions on severability actually make legally suspect provisions of administrative rules significantly more likely to be challenged. Elite law firms scrutinize every rule that affects concentrated interests, either on the instructions of their existing clients or in the hope of attracting new ones. We doubt that there are many potentially problematic provisions that would be noticed only if the agency included a severability clause.
With respect to the second concern—that courts are more willing to set aside provisions contained in rules with a severability clause—we have two observations. First, the argument assumes that courts should leave in place a socially beneficial yet unlawful provision. One might disfavor unlawful regulatory provisions on principle, however, even if they are in fact socially beneficial. Second, even assuming that unlawful yet socially beneficial regulations are desirable, one must weigh the costs of relinquishing those regulations against the costs of erroneous vacatur of entire rules. Although it is impossible to quantify these social costs, we think the latter, even if less frequent, are likely to be greater in the aggregate.
***
To summarize the argument thus far, the severability decision involves two questions: (1) would the agency have intended the regulatory remainder to stay in effect in the absence of the challenged provision?; and (2) is the remainder lawful? We have argued that a promulgating agency, rather than a reviewing court, is best positioned to answer these questions. As the next Part explains, however, this is not the modern doctrine on administrative severability clauses. In fact, the D.C. Circuit has stated that severability clauses will rarely be dispositive of the severability decision.90
II. the strange dearth of administrative severability clauses
The previous Part argued for a particular allocation of decision-making authority on severability in administrative law: courts should defer to agency-promulgated severability clauses. For that division of labor to materialize, however, agencies must promulgate rules containing severability clauses, and courts must develop a framework for deferring to them.
In this Part, we turn our sights to judicial doctrine and administrative practice and show that neither condition obtains. In Part II.A, we focus on the courts. Federal judicial doctrine on administrative severability clauses is largely a re-application of the doctrine on statutory severability clauses to the administrative context. We briefly survey the doctrine on statutory severability clauses, explaining that it does not require courts to defer to severability clauses. We then show that this doctrine has been transmogrified into a doctrine of administrative law. In Part II.B, we show that administrative agencies rarely incorporate severability clauses into their rules. We posit that agencies usually do not consider including severability clauses in their rules because they do not receive a deference pay-off when they do. We conclude, therefore, that if courts want to capture the potential benefits of administrative severability clauses discussed in Part I, then they need to develop a framework for evaluating administrative severability clauses that would give these clauses some appreciable measure of deference.
A. De Novo Review by the Courts
Just as courts have applied the same test to determine the severability of both statutes and administrative rules,91 they have applied the same framework for evaluating the effect of severability clauses. This section therefore begins with a brief overview of the development of judicial doctrine on statutory severability clauses.92
According to John Nagle, severability clauses began to appear in state and federal statutes in the late nineteenth century and had become common by 1910.93 Before the appearance of severability clauses, the federal courts had long presumed that partially unconstitutional statutes were severable, unless the provisions of the statutory remainder were so intertwined with the challenged provisions as to make the remainder unworkable.94
The U.S. Supreme Court first addressed the emerging phenomenon of statutory severability clauses in the 1914 Ohio Tax Cases.95 There, the Court accepted the statute’s severability clause at face value. The Court, in leaving the remainder in place, assumed that the severability clause meant that the legislature intended for the statutory remainder to stay in effect.96
In the subsequent two decades, the Court moved further and further away from the literalist approach to severability clauses. In Hill v. Wallace, decided in 1922, the Court maintained that a severability clause expresses the legislature’s intent for the remainder of a statute to stay in effect97 but declined to defer to the clause’s plain meaning.98 The Court for the first time noted a basis on which a reviewing court might second-guess the plain meaning of a severability clause: to wit, the interconnectedness of the statute’s provisions might demonstrate that the legislature would have intended for the court to strike the entire statute down, notwithstanding the severability clause.99 And in Dorchy v. Kansas, decided in 1924, the Court for the first time advised that a severability clause “provides a rule of construction which may sometimes aid in determining [legislative] intent. But it is an aid merely; not an inexorable command.”100
In 1928, the Court announced an even greater departure from a literal construction of severability clauses. In Williams v. Standard Oil Co., the Court confirmed that interconnectedness was a basis for doubting a severability clause’s ostensible meaning and also added a second basis: a court could disregard a severability clause if there were “considerations which make evident” that “the legislature would not have been satisfied with what remains [after a court strikes down the challenged provision].”101 More significantly, the Court reversed the presumption in favor of severability for statutes that do not contain a severability clause. The Court held that a severability clause creates a presumption of severability, but the absence of such a clause creates a presumption “that the legislature intends an act to be effective as an entirety.”102
The early twentieth-century doctrine on severability clauses began to crystallize in Carter v. Carter Coal Co.103 According to Carter Coal, statutes are presumed inseverable.104 A severability clause creates a presumption of severability, but that presumption can “be overcome by considerations which establish ‘the clear probability that . . . the Legislature would not have been satisfied with [the remainder].’”105 Legislative intent determines whether “the provisions of a statute are so interwoven that[,] one being held invalid[,] the others must fall.”106 Robert Stern offered the following synopsis of the law at the time: “Separability clauses are thus now significant only because of their absence. Like articles of clothing, if they are present little attention is paid to them, but if they are absent they may be missed.”107
Carter Coal’s view of the significance of severability clauses largely persists, except that the Court no longer presumes that a statute is inseverable when a statute does not contain a severability clause. The leading modern case on statutory severability is Alaska Airlines. According to that widely cited case:
[W]hen Congress has explicitly provided for severance by including a severability clause in the statute[,] . . . the inclusion of such a clause creates a presumption that Congress did not intend the validity of the statute in question to depend on the validity of the constitutionally offensive provision. . . . [But] Congress’ silence is just that—silence—and does not raise a presumption against severability.108
Alaska Airlines thus acknowledged that severability clauses create a presumption of severability, but it confirmed that statutes without a severability clause are not presumed inseverable.109 As noted earlier, Alaska Airlines also retained the two bases for finding a statute containing a severability clause nonetheless inseverable: “Unless it is evident that the Legislature would not have enacted those provisions which are within its power, independently of that which is not, the invalid part may be dropped if what is left is fully operative as a law.”110
The Court has not clarified the strength of the presumption in favor of severability created by a severability clause, but the case law suggests that the presumption is rather weak. The Court has repeatedly said that “a severability clause is an ‘aid merely; not an inexorable command’”111 and that “whatever relevance such an explicit clause might have in creating a presumption of severability, . . . the ultimate determination of severability will rarely turn on the presence or absence of such a clause.”112
The behavior of subsequent courts has borne out these observations. In several cases involving the severability decision, lower courts have ignored the existence of a severability clause.113 And in Buckley v. Valeo, the Court held the remainder of the Federal Election Campaign Act to be severable from its unconstitutional provisions without citing the Act’s severability clause.114 Even when courts do not totally ignore a severability clause, the common trope is for a federal court opinion dealing with statutory severability issues to begin with a rhetorical nod in the direction of a severability clause but then to analyze the severability decision as if the clause did not exist.
Several of the Court’s recent decisions illustrate this treatment of severability clauses. In National Federation of Independent Businesses v. Sebelius (NFIB), both the majority opinion and Justice Ginsburg’s separate opinion stated that the Court would follow Congress’s explicit instruction that the Medicaid expansion be severed from the rest of the Act.115 However, the majority opinion then proceeded to determine—as if it were a totally separate inquiry—“what Congress would have intended in light of the Court’s constitutional holding.”116
Consider also the Court’s decision last Term in Executive Benefits Insurance Agency v. Arkison.117 In an earlier case, Stern v. Marshall, the Supreme Court considered the constitutionality of a particular provision of the Bankruptcy Code. Under section 157, bankruptcy courts may proceed to final judgment on certain “core” claims118 and may offer proposed findings of fact and conclusions of law on certain “non-core” claims.119 In Stern, the Court held that bankruptcy courts lack constitutional authority to enter final judgment on state-law counterclaims labeled as “core” under section 157(b).120 In Arkison, the Court considered whether Stern created a “gap” in the statute. According to the “gap” theory, bankruptcy courts lack constitutional authority to enter final judgment on certain core claims under Stern and lack statutory authority to make proposed findings of fact and conclusions of law as to those claims under section 157.121 The Court noted that the statute contains a severability clause and held that the clause “closes the so-called ‘gap.’”122 However, as in NFIB, the Court then proceeded to analyze severability under the Alaska Airlines test as if the severability clause did not exist.123 The Court’s reasoning in NFIB and Arkison shows that the presumption in favor of severability is weak. Indeed, if the Court took severability clauses at anything like face value, then those clauses would not so quickly be set to one side. Much of what Robert Stern said in 1937 continues to be true today: “if [severability clauses] are present[,] little attention is paid to them.”124
We do not intend to criticize the courts’ treatment of statutory severability clauses. Indeed, in Part III, we suggest that considerations of institutional competence may justify this treatment (though a full consideration of that issue is outside the scope of this Article). Rather, the point has been to set the stage for our discussion of administrative severability clauses. Earlier in the Article, we observed that the federal courts have, without much reflection, treated the severability of administrative regulations as not relevantly different from the severability of statutes. We noted that the Supreme Court’s first and most substantial discussion of severability in administrative law contained no citations but simply repurposed the Alaska Airlines test for use in cases involving the severability of regulations.125 Similarly, after an extensive discussion of the statutory severability doctrine in Alliance for Community Media v. FCC, a panel of the D.C. Circuit wrote: “The [severability] analysis differs little in the context of invalidating provisions of regulations promulgated by an agency.”126 Courts have thus assumed that the severability of statutes and of administrative regulations raise virtually identical considerations.
Unlike the case law on statutory severability clauses, the case law on administrative severability clauses is rather scarce. As the next section illustrates, the scarcity is due primarily to the fact that administrative agencies rarely include severability clauses in their rules. The cases that do exist, however, suggest that the federal courts also view administrative severability clauses as raising identical considerations to statutory severability clauses. Like severability clauses in statutes, administrative severability clauses create a “presumption” of severability.127 And as in the case of statutes, this presumption is largely unimportant under current jurisprudence. Indeed, borrowing from the Supreme Court’s cases on statutory severability clauses, the D.C. Circuit in reviewing a Transit Authority regulation has stated that the “determination of severability will rarely turn on the presence or absence of [a severability clause].”128 We conclude that the doctrine on administrative severability clauses, like the doctrine on statutory severability clauses, requires a reviewing court to recognize only a weak presumption in favor of severability and does not require the court to defer to an administrative severability clause.
The analysis in Part I suggested that regulatory schemes would benefit if courts deferred to administrative severability clauses. Accordingly, we think a reviewing court should adopt more than a weak presumption in favor of severability when the agency has chosen to include a severability clause in its rule. As we explain in the next section, the federal courts’ treatment of administrative severability clauses has likely created a feedback loop between judicial doctrine and agency practice. Under the doctrine, courts do not defer to severability clauses, and this leads agencies to not promulgate these clauses—a consequence that in turn stunts the development of administrative severability doctrine.
B. Neglect in the Agencies
This Article began by inspecting the severability clause in the EPA’s ambitious Clean Power Plan. Such clauses are rare. We have identified twenty-one agencies that included a severability clause in at least one of their rules between 2000 and 2014.129 Among these agencies, the Federal Trade Commission (FTC) generated the highest volume of severability clauses. From 2000 to 2014, the FTC promulgated 206 rules, thirteen (6.3%) of which contained a severability clause. After the FTC, the next most active users of severability clauses from 2000 to 2014 were the EPA (with seven final rules containing a severability clause), followed by the Federal Communications Commission and the Forest Service (each with five) and the Federal Railroad Administration (with four). All other agencies have included severability clauses in their rules in three or fewer instances from 2000 to 2014.130 The normative significance of our data—for example, whether they support the claim that agencies include severability clauses in their rules too infrequently—is of course debatable. However, we think it is fair to conclude from the data that agencies infrequently include severability clauses in their rules.
Instead of including severability clauses in final rules, agencies tend to clarify their positions on severability only when required to do so in litigation—that is, they formulate a position on severability only after they become concerned that particular provisions of their rules are in jeopardy.131 In conversation, supervising lawyers at several agencies indicated that severability was not a priority during notice and comment; rather, agency personnel assumed that they would consider severability only when it became an imminent issue in litigation. An informal survey of several former EPA General Counsels, including one of the co-authors, indicated that the topic of including a severability clause rarely came up, and when it did, agency general counsel staffs were often reluctant to imply that there was even a possibility that portions of their rule might be set aside. This attitude, while understandable, is myopic.
Waiting until litigation to opine on severability can have significant drawbacks. While severability clauses must be promulgated according to statute-prescribed procedural formalities—most commonly, notice-and-comment procedures—positions developed in litigation do not require such procedures. Indeed, trial and appellate briefs are typically confidential until the time they are filed, and they are often reviewed only by a handful of agency lawyers. As a consequence of these procedural differences, severability arguments raised in litigation do not benefit regulatory regimes along the dimensions discussed in Part I—expertise, accountability, the rule of law, and efficiency—at least not to the same extent as severability clauses.
Severability opinions expressed through briefs are less likely to reflect the agency’s subject-matter expertise. Agency staff with advanced training in scientific and economic analysis, for example, will often review legislative rules, but not review legal briefs. The benefits of review by agency staff became particularly evident in Davis County I and II. In Davis County I, operators of several existing municipal solid waste (MSW) combustor units challenged EPA’s 1995 MSW combustion standards. The court held that the 1995 standards, as applied to small MSW combustors, exceeded EPA’s statutory authority under section 129 of the Clean Air Act.132 On the advice of the EPA’s counsel at oral argument, the court vacated the entire rule rather than severing the ultra vires provision.133 In Davis County II, however, the EPA petitioned for rehearing on the severability issue, conceding that the agency’s counsel had not fully grasped the workability of the regulatory provisions that would remain after the court’s ruling.134 The Court of Appeals reinstated the standards except as applied to small MSW combustors and cement kilns.135 This was a close call for the agency and presumably for communities that are affected by pollution from MSW combustors. Had the agency’s position on severability been expressed through a severability clause, rather than through a lawyer at oral argument, the agency’s administrative expertise could have been brought more directly to bear on the severability question confronting the court.
An administrative severability clause is also a more accountable and participatory way for an agency to express its opinion on severability than a litigation brief. As noted, to include a severability clause in a legislative rule pursuant to the APA, an agency must provide a “[g]eneral notice of proposed rulemaking,”136 give “interested persons an opportunity to participate in the rule making” by submitting comments,137 and address significant comments in its statement of basis and purpose.138 By contrast, for reasons of legal strategy, positions developed in litigation almost never involve participation by the public; at most, a few litigants aligned with the agency may be consulted.
Severability clauses can also make regulatory schemes more predictable and stable than positions on severability developed in litigation, due to the greater prospectivity and formality of severability clauses. A severability clause in a rule will always be promulgated far in advance of a legal brief opining on severability. Therefore, a rule with a severability clause creates reliance interests that adjust for the possibility that some of the rule’s provisions may be invalidated and severed from the rest. By contrast, an agency develops a position on severability in litigation only after regulated entities have begun to plan their affairs around a rule’s substantive provisions. Similarly, procedural requirements for promulgating severability clauses make regulatory schemes more stable at the margins because these requirements must be satisfied in order to rescind these clauses once they are in effect.139 Consequently, one expects fewer changes in an agency’s position on severability when the change is announced through a severability clause rather than in a legal brief.
In light of the potential drawbacks of waiting until litigation to develop a position on severability, why do agencies choose to wait rather than include a severability clause in the text of a rule? While more research needs to be done on this question,140 one way to approach it is to compare an agency’s decision whether to include a severability clause in a rule with the choice between interpreting a federal statute using a legislative rule or using an informal agency action.
Under Chevron, an agency interpreting a federal statute can choose either to pay now or pay later.141 The agency can “purchase” Chevron deference for its interpretation by investing agency resources in costly notice-and-comment procedures. If the agency does so, then its reward is less judicial scrutiny. Alternatively, the agency can choose not to invest in formal procedures. But if it does so, the agency might later have to “purchase” judicial approval through stronger interpretive arguments evaluated under the less deferential Skidmore framework.
The courts’ doctrine on administrative severability clauses, however, does not share Chevron/Skidmore’s incentive structure. Promulgating a severability clause through notice-and-comment procedures can be costly. It may entail significant ex ante costs associated with investigating and reflecting on the various regimes that might result from an enforceable severability clause. Furthermore, the agency may believe that a severability clause entails higher expected ex post costs. For example, an agency may be concerned that a severability clause will make weaknesses in its regulatory program easier to detect. Or an agency may think that a severability clause will weaken its position in litigation, either because a court may wonder why the agency included a severability clause if the agency believed that the regulatory program was lawful142 or because the court may feel it easier to partially invalidate a rule that contains a severability clause.143
Under current judicial doctrine, the agency receives little payoff for incurring these ex ante and ex post costs. As explained in the previous section, courts tend not to give substantial deference to severability clauses, preferring instead to conduct the same severability analysis that they would perform in the absence of a severability clause. This lack of deference may often be the decisive factor for an agency considering whether to include a severability clause in a rule. For example, the National Indian Gaming Commission responded to a comment requesting that it include a severability clause in one of its rules as follows:
The Commission . . . addressed [the suggestion that the Commission include a severability clause in its rule] in the previous preamble, stating that severability clauses are not conclusive of an agency’s intent and that “the ultimate determination of severability will rarely turn on the presence or absence of such a clause.”144
Thus, an agency considering whether to include a severability clause in a rule may conclude that the potential benefits are not worth the candle. The absence of a deference framework specifically for administrative severability clauses is a critical feature of a vicious cycle in which courts do not defer to severability clauses, so agencies do not include them, so courts have no occasion to reconsider whether they should defer to them.
Our aim here is not to suggest that agencies should include a severability clause in every rule. Even if rulemaking were costless, including a severability clause in a rule would not be advisable under some circumstances. First, severability is not advisable when the rule’s efficacy depends on the interconnectedness of its provisions.145 Second, a severability clause might prove to be misguided if the agency does not know whether it would want a court to sever a challenged provision.146 Third, there may be some provisions that are severable and others that are not, and it may be difficult to predict which combinations should result in severability. Finally, although a regulatory remainder left standing may be preferable to the court’s invalidation of the entire rule, the benefits of that regulatory remainder will not always outweigh the drafting costs of promulgating a severability clause.
Our point here is that the current doctrine on administrative severability clauses does not give agencies adequate incentives to include these clauses in their rules even though these clauses can often benefit regulatory schemes more than agency positions on severability developed in litigation. As we have explained, even if courts adopt our proposal by developing a deference framework for administrative severability clauses, an agency will sometimes have good reasons for not including a severability clause in a rule. However, a framework for severability clauses would ensure that agencies will be compensated for their upfront investment in drafting severability clauses and would thereby expand an agency’s options for creating the best regulatory scheme with its scarce resources.
III. deference to administrative severability clauses
This Part proposes a deference framework for severability clauses. Before introducing that framework, we first debunk the primary argument against judicial deference to administrative severability clauses—namely, that severability clauses are not the best evidence of the agency’s intent regarding severability. We then explain the framework that courts should follow when reviewing an administrative severability clause.
A. Disassociating Statutory and Administrative Severability Clauses
Part I demonstrated that regulatory schemes containing severability clauses would benefit in several important ways if courts deferred to an agency’s opinion on the intent and workability questions expressed in a severability clause. Part II, however, showed that courts tend not to defer to severability clauses. Rather, courts typically give a rhetorical nod to the existence of a severability clause but then conduct their own de novo review of agency intent and workability. This doctrinal treatment of administrative severability clauses is symptomatic of the federal courts’ tendency to treat severability analysis in administrative law as substantially the same as severability analysis for statutes. The key, then, to understanding why courts hardly defer to administrative severability clauses is to understand their treatment of statutory severability clauses.
Severability clauses ordinarily state in plain terms that Congress intends for a court to sever an unconstitutional provision from a statute’s remainder. Federal courts typically regard clear statutory text as strong evidence of Congress’s intent.147 Why then do courts look past the plain text of a severability clause to analyze severability de novo? The accepted explanation is that statutory severability clauses are boilerplate provisions.148We have not seen this argument systematically developed, but it might proceed in the following way: severability clauses are not reliable evidence of Congress’s intent because they are generally added to statutes without much (or any) consideration by members of Congress or their staffs. Therefore, a reviewing court is justified in looking past a severability clause because Congress was likely much more concerned with the statute’s substantive provisions than with the severability clause.
We hear the ring of truth in the claim that Congress is institutionally ill-equipped to have an informed view of the workability of severability clauses. In particular, several features of the legislative process in Congress (which we describe below) justify a court’s scrutiny of a statutory severability clause’s apparent meaning. If the rulemaking process within the administrative agencies shared these features, then the parallel treatment of statutory and administrative severability clauses might be justified. However, in several important ways, the rulemaking process is substantially different from the process of drafting statutes. Indeed, the reasons for thinking that Congress lacks capacity and incentive to consider the severability of statutes are, interestingly, reasons to think that agencies have such capacity and incentive. We consider three such reasons below.
1. Attention Paid to Severability Clauses
Some commentators have argued that members of Congress and their staff do not pay much attention to severability clauses. Instead, legislative counsel throw them “unthinkingly . . . into a statute without considering whether [they] really want[] each provision of [their] handiwork to stand independently.”149 Because Congress uses severability clauses so “indiscriminately,” a reviewing court could reasonably conclude that, if taken literally, severability clauses would “cover situations which they were never intended to reach.”150
The process by which administrative agencies decide to include severability clauses in rules, however, is vastly different from this supposed congressional process. Agencies do not just throw severability clauses into their regulations. As we explained in Part II.B, even the most active user of severability clauses—the FTC—has included a severability clause in only 6.3% of its rules from 2000 to 2014.151 Moreover, unlike Congress, agencies may not include severability clauses in their rules unthinkingly because the APA’s rulemaking procedures require agencies to respond to public input about their rules. To be sure, congressional committees do hold regular hearings on proposed legislation that would in theory permit the public to provide input about severability clauses. Administrative agencies, however, are required to respond in a rational way to public comments; otherwise, their rules can be set aside as arbitrary and capricious.152 Moreover, our research suggests that agencies tend to respond with care to comments suggesting the inclusion or removal of severability clauses. For example, in response to one set of comments, the Fish and Wildlife Service explained: “We recognize that severability clauses are frequently used in legislation but have decided that such a clause would not be useful in the current rule.”153 Similarly, in the statement of basis and purpose for one of its rules, the National Indian Gaming Commission wrote:
[S]ome commenters advocated for the inclusion of a severability clause . . . . [T]he Commission declines to include a severability clause in this regulation because it believes that the regulations are not so intertwined that striking one provision would necessarily always require invalidation of the entire part, and the lack of a severability clause will not compel a court’s finding on the issue.154
In short, there is no evidence that administrative agencies throw severability clauses unreflectively into their rules.
2. Time Pressure
Even if members of Congress and their staffs were inclined to reflect on the manifold potential ramifications of a statutory severability clause, they often lack the time to do so. Congressional staffs work under tremendous time pressure, making it less likely that they will have had the opportunity to consider the implications of a complex, probabilistic, and procedural instrument like a severability clause.155 Nourse and Schacter’s study of legislative drafting in Congress indirectly supports this hypothesis by finding that:
Several staff members complained about the dangers of drafting bills on the floor, as this increased the risks of the process becoming “ugly,” haphazard, and driven by political imperative. Staffers expressed concern about last-minute drafting without a lot of public scrutiny. Specific fears included provisions being “slipped in,” people losing track of whether one provision squares with another, or a provision being added to satisfy the needs of a senator in trouble for re-election.156
Similarly, in Gluck and Bressman’s more recent study of congressional legislative staff, respondents reported that time pressures often made it impossible to comply with their goal of making the usage of terms consistent across a statute.157 Neither Nourse and Schacter nor Gluck and Bressman surveyed staffers on their use of severability clauses, but we suspect that time pressures also inhibit staffers from meaningfully considering these clauses’ potential ramifications.
It is true that agencies labor under their own time pressures.158 Congress can impose deadlines on agency action,159 the public can petition agencies to initiate rulemaking,160 and, like Congress, agencies are not immune from the pressures of election cycles. Still, various statutory and executive controls require agencies to take care in promulgating rules. As noted, the APA, certain agency organic acts, and various other statutes impose procedural requirements on rulemaking that require deliberation and reasoned responses to comments by a promulgating agency. Review by OIRA typically requires agencies to justify major proposed rulemakings on the basis of sophisticated economic analysis. These various procedural mechanisms require an agency to be careful about each aspect of a proposed rule.161 Indeed, much of the literature on agency ossification maintains that many of these controls on agency action require agencies to use scarce resources inefficiently in order to explain their reasons for promulgating rules.162 We think it is fair to conclude that agencies promulgate rules in a more deliberate and deliberative way than Congress enacts statutes, which in part suggests that there should be less concern about deference to administrative severability clauses than about deference to statutory severability clauses.
3. Centralization
The Nourse-Schacter and Gluck-Bressman surveys have shed light on the variability, complexity, and polycentricity of statutory drafting in Congress. Statutes are regularly the result of many legislative bargains and are drafted by multiple committees over multiple iterations. In their study of staffers on the Senate Judiciary Committee, for example, Nourse and Schacter found broad consensus on the proposition that “[t]he [legislative] drafting process . . . is better understood as multiple drafting processes, varying along many axes,”163 reinforcing the aphorism that Congress is a “they,” not an “it.”164 Nourse and Schacter continue:
[R]esponsibility for drafting a bill often is diffused among many people and groups, chief among them staffers from different offices, Legislative Counsel drafters, and lobbyists. This dispersal of responsibility makes it problematic for a court to try to isolate any single moment, actor, or event that decisively conferred meaning on a contested provision.165
Moreover, respondents in Gluck and Bressman’s study emphasized that committees often operate as drafting “islands,” unconnected from the business of the other committees.166
The messy reality of the statutory drafting process has several implications for the plausibility of ascribing to Congress a specific intention to draft and pass workable severability clauses. First, the committee drafting model creates incentives for individual members to include severability clauses in statutes; members want to ensure that the portions of bills they have drafted will remain in effect even if portions drafted by members of other committees eventually fail. The larger and more complex a bill, the more likely it contains an unconstitutional provision, and thus the stronger the incentive to include a severability clause. The practice of legislating by means of omnibus bills strengthens incentives to include severability clauses, but not always in situations in which they would be advisable. Second, the isolation of congressional committees suggests that blanket severability clauses may be inserted into portions of bills drafted by one committee that were not intended to apply to other portions of the bill. This suggests that a statutory severability clause, drafted and passed by a committee without reference to other parts of the bill, does not provide an informed opinion on the larger body’s intent or on the workability of the statutory remainder. Third, traditional forms of democratic accountability likely do not chasten the temptation to include a far-reaching severability clause in a statute merely to protect a limited set of provisions. In Congress, responsibility for a severability clause gone wrong would be diffused across all members, diminishing any particular member’s concerns that she will be held unaccountable for inserting an ill-advised severability clause into a statute. This point also suggests that these clauses do not contain an informed opinion on the statutory remainder’s workability. In short, Congress arguably has too many cooks in the kitchen for a severability clause meaningfully to reflect the legislative will.
Not so for the administrative agencies. Instead of multiple committees working in multiple drafting stages, agencies draft rules in a more concerted fashion.167 There is no such thing as a “Christmas tree” rule.168 Rules are typically drafted by a single team of drafters, representing different offices, whose draft work product is reviewed multiple times — at least in general terms, if not word by word — by agency general counsels and often by the agency head or her deputies. Agency proposed rules are also subject to OIRA review, which puts them through a rigorous economic analysis. Furthermore, the temptation to include a severability clause in a rule in the hope of preserving important substantive provisions is reduced by the fact that responsibility for an unworkable regulatory remainder will fall squarely upon the agency (or, more realistically, the agency head). Thus, administrative severability clauses are more likely than statutory severability clauses to reflect the actual intent of their drafters.
Regardless of the merits of arguments discrediting statutory severability clauses, the case for not deferring to administrative severability clauses is based on an inapt analogy between the agencies and Congress. Having made the case that courts should defer to administrative severability clauses in Part I.B and having debunked the analogy between legislative and administrative severability clauses in this section, we next lay out a deference framework for administrative severability clauses.
B. A Chevron-Style Framework for Severability Clauses
We propose a two-step deference framework for administrative severability clauses, similar in some respects to Chevron deference. The Chevron framework addresses how a federal court should treat an agency’s interpretation of a federal statute that it administers. The framework proceeds in two steps. At Step One, the court asks whether “the intent of Congress is clear” after employing traditional canons of statutory construction; if so, “that is the end of the matter . . . the court . . . must give effect to the unambiguously expressed intent of Congress.”169 Step One launches a purely legal inquiry. Employing interpretive techniques in which they are skilled, courts ask whether the agency has stepped beyond the boundaries of its statutory authority. If, after employing these techniques, a reviewing court determines that the statute is silent or ambiguous on the relevant issue, then the court proceeds to Step Two. At Step Two, the court again undertakes a purely legal inquiry and asks whether the agency’s interpretation is “based on a permissible construction of the statute.”170 If so, then the court defers to the agency’s interpretation because “a court may not substitute its own construction of a statutory provision for a reasonable interpretation made by the administrator of an agency.”171
Chevron acknowledges that within a certain “zone of reasonableness”172 statutory interpretation is closer to creating policy than it is to discerning legal norms, and that it is better to allow the more expert and accountable agency to create policy. As the Supreme Court explained in 2005:
In Chevron, this Court held that ambiguities in statutes within an agency’s jurisdiction to administer are delegations of authority to the agency to fill the statutory gap in reasonable fashion. Filling these gaps, the Court explained, involves difficult policy choices that agencies are better equipped to make than courts. If a statute is ambiguous, and if the implementing agency’s construction is reasonable, Chevron requires a federal court to accept the agency’s construction of the statute, even if the agency’s reading differs from what the court believes is the best statutory interpretation.173
Thus, both courts and agencies have roles to play under Chevron—roles delimited by their institutional capacities. Using traditional interpretation methods, courts police the clear statutory boundaries, while agencies, employing their own expertise, may create reasonable policies within those boundaries.
The deference framework for administrative severability clauses that we propose is similar. At Step One, a reviewing court should determine whether the regulatory remainder is lawful. Michael Dorf has called this the “taint problem” for severability analysis because the remainder of a statute or rule may be “tainted” by residual legal defects when a court invalidates a certain provision.174 This inquiry is analytically prior to the two questions of the Alaska Airlines severability test.
If the remainder is lawful, then at Step Two a court should determine what the severability clause requires and defer to it. Like Chevron Step Two, the courts’ review at this stage should be highly deferential because, as we explained in Part I.B, agencies are better than courts at determining when a regulatory remainder will be workable.175 Like Chevron, our deference framework assigns to the courts and agencies roles delimited by each institution’s capacities.
The deference framework we propose would break the vicious cycle in which courts, rather than agencies, make the severability decision. By giving agencies deference at Step Two, it would (1) allow agencies to answer the intent and workability questions and (2) provide agencies with incentives to include severability clauses in more rules when appropriate.
Before expounding further upon the mechanics of our proposed deference framework, we should note that administrative law already has the conceptual resources to implement the framework. Under the Seminole Rock doctrine,176 which predates Chevron by nearly forty years, federal courts give what is essentially Chevron deference to an agency’s interpretation of its own rules.177 Like Chevron, the contemporary statement of the Seminole Rock doctrine involves a two-step analysis. First, a reviewing court asks whether the agency’s interpretation steps outside the boundaries established by the agency’s original rule—that is, whether the agency’s interpretation is “inconsistent” with the regulation.178 If not, the court asks whether the agency’s interpretation is “plainly erroneous.”179
Two rationales support the doctrine. First, an originalist rationale180 posits that agencies, as the drafters of administrative rules, have special insight into their intent when promulgating those rules.181 Second, a functionalist rationale emphasizes the agencies’ specialized expertise in administering their “‘complex and highly technical regulatory program[s].’”182
Seminole Rock is related to severability because questions of severability are fundamentally questions of interpretation.183 Just as archetypal questions of statutory interpretation oblige the court to examine the legislative authorities (for example, text, structure, and legislative history) to determine the legislature’s intent, so too does severability analysis oblige the court to examine the regulation in search of the agency’s intent. If severability is fundamentally a question of interpretation, then an agency’s opinion on the severability of its rule is an interpretation of that rule deserving Seminole Rock deference. Small wonder, then, that the rationales underlying the Seminole Rock doctrine dovetail with the two questions of the Alaska Airlines test. The “touchstone” of severability analysis is the lawmakers’ intent. And since agencies have special insight into their intent when enacting administrative rules, they are best equipped to opine on that intent. Further, severability analysis requires a determination of whether the remainder of a regulation is workable. Since agencies have special expertise in the “complex and highly technical regulatory program[s]” they administer, they are best equipped to opine on the workability of regulatory remainders.184 Thus, although neither the Supreme Court nor the D.C. Circuit have applied the Seminole Rock doctrine to administrative severability clauses, accommodating the deference framework we propose would not require a seismic shift in the current doctrine. We now discuss each step of our proposed deference framework in more detail.
1. Step One: Address Legal Defects
At Severability Step One, a reviewing court must determine whether the regulatory remainder is lawful or “tainted” by residual legal defects.185 The Alaska Airlines severability test does not require this inquiry, largely because the Alaska Airlines test assumes that the reviewing court will not leave in place a remainder that is unlawful. In any case, a reviewing court has a duty to determine whether the regulatory remainder is lawful.
The proper scope of a court’s review for residual legal defects will inherently be somewhat open-ended. On one hand, a court may not leave in place legal defects that are apparent from its review of the provision challenged in litigation. On the other hand, the duty to determine the existence of residual defects does not require the court to comb the entire rule in search of problems. Indeed, such a requirement would, in some cases, be far too onerous for a court to perform and would arguably violate the Constitution’s case-or-controversy jurisdictional requirement by giving a court license to rule on the legality of any aspect of a rule, even if not challenged by the parties.186 Thus, a reviewing court is obliged to determine whether the remainder contains residual legal defects that are substantially related to the challenged provision. We now explain how a court should undertake that task.
a. Identifying Defects
A reviewing court considering whether to leave a regulatory remainder in place must determine whether the remainder suffers from any of several types of legal defects, including whether the remainder is unconstitutional, ultra vires, or arbitrary and capricious.187
First, a regulatory remainder may be unconstitutional. Suppose the Department of Homeland Security promulgates a rule containing a severability clause and two substantive provisions: first, the rule bans all “First Amendment activities” in domestic commercial airports, and second, the rule contains a fallback provision stating that, “In the event that a court sets this rule aside, all expressive activities that, consistent with the First Amendment, can be banned in an airport, shall be banned.”188 If a plaintiff challenges the first provision in court, the remainder clearly would contain a residual constitutional defect. While the reviewing court would set the first provision aside as unconstitutionally overbroad,189 the remainder would be unconstitutionally vague.190
Second, a regulatory remainder may also be ultra vires, even if the original rule was not. Suppose a federal statute directs the Federal Reserve Board to promulgate two types of regulations.191 First, the Board must establish procedures to be used in an administrative hearing to determine whether a particular financial institution that does not fall under the statutory definition of a “bank” nevertheless offers many of the services that banks offer (banking services). Second, after those procedures are established, the Board must promulgate regulations to monitor and control the activities of institutions found to offer banking services to ensure that consumers are adequately protected. Now suppose the Board promulgates a rule that establishes both the procedures to be used in hearings and the substantive regulations governing institutions that offer banking services. Finally, suppose the hearing procedures are unconstitutional. In this example, if a plaintiff successfully challenges the hearing procedures, the regulatory remainder would suffer from a residual ultra vires defect because the statute directs the Board to promulgate substantive regulations only after promulgating procedures to be used in hearings.
Finally, the regulatory remainder might be legally defective because it is arbitrary and capricious. This defect is most common when a reviewing court renders the remainder inconsistent with the rule’s statement of basis and purpose.192 To illustrate, consider the D.C. Circuit’s decision in MD/DC/DE Broadcasters Association II.193 In MD/DC/DE Broadcasters I, the court considered the constitutionality of an FCC rule regarding the equal employment opportunity policies of broadcasters.194 To ensure that minority and women candidates knew about available job opportunities with broadcast stations, the FCC rule required broadcasters that sought licenses from the FCC to make “a good faith effort to disseminate widely any information about job openings.”195 To “afford[] broadcasters flexibility in designing their EEO programs,” the rule allowed broadcasters to select one of two options for accomplishing that goal.196 Under Option A, licensees had to “undertake four approved recruitment initiatives in each two-year period.”197 The FCC did not require licensees who selected Option A to report the race and gender of job applicants.198 Under Option B, licensees could design their own outreach programs but had to report the race and gender of each job applicant and how the applicant was referred to the station.199 The D.C. Circuit held that Option B required race-based discrimination and was accordingly subject to strict scrutiny.200 The court then held that Option B was unconstitutional because it was not narrowly tailored to any ostensibly compelling interest that the Commission might have had.201 Finally, the court found that the unconstitutional provision was inseverable from the remainder of the rule and set aside the entire rule.202
In its petition for rehearing in MD/DC/DE Broadcasters Association II, the FCC asked the court to reinstate the remainder of its rule.203 Writing for the court, Judge Douglas Ginsburg observed that the FCC had two goals in promulgating the rule, but that Options A and B would each achieve only one of those goals.204 As the court observed, the FCC’s statement of basis and purpose stated “that Option A could satisfy the goal of achieving broad outreach” and “that Option B was added in order to afford broadcasters flexibility.”205 The court accordingly concluded that severing the invalid part of the rule “would leave in force a rule that, in view of the Commission’s own stated goals, would be arbitrary and capricious”206 because the remainder would achieve only one of the stated goals. The majority plainly thought they had confronted a taint problem. After setting aside the unconstitutional part of the FCC’s rule, the rule’s remainder became, in the majority’s view, arbitrary and capricious. Thus, the court set aside the entire rule.
In dissent, Judge David Tatel criticized the majority for not deferring to the agency’s litigation position. He maintained that the court should defer to the agency’s opinion on severability because the agency had the statutory authority to promulgate Option A and expressed its position in the briefs that Option B was severable.207 Regardless of whether the regulatory remainder was arbitrary and capricious under the case’s facts, we agree with the majority’s endorsement of the following principle: a court may not leave in place a regulatory remainder that is inadequately supported by the original rule’s statement of basis and purpose.208 While courts should defer to an agency’s opinion whether a rule’s remainder will be workable (a claim we defended in Part I), courts should not defer to the agency’s position on whether the rule’s statement of basis and purpose adequately supports the remainder. An agency’s statement of basis and purpose need not persuade the reviewing court that the regulatory remainder is a good idea; indeed, from the court’s perspective the remainder may seem like a disaster. However, for the court to satisfy its obligations under the APA, it must be persuaded that the regulatory remainder has adequate support in the agency’s statement of basis and purpose—that is, that the agency has provided reasons for the regulatory provisions that remain.
Residual arbitrary and capricious review accommodates the sensible idea that the larger the portion of an administrative rule that a court invalidates, the less willing a court should be to enforce the remainder. Generally speaking, for example, the larger the portion of a rule that a court invalidates, the more likely that the remainder will also be set aside because it is more likely to be arbitrary and capricious under the rule’s statement of basis and purpose. We do not advocate that courts use the extent of invalidation as a factor when determining whether to sever invalid provisions of rules, but the extent of invalidation may be helpful in predicting what a court will do with a regulatory remainder.
b. Remedying Defects
When a reviewing court identifies residual legal defects in a rule containing a severability clause, it should first determine whether it could invalidate the remaining infirmities without causing additional taint problems. If invalidating additional provisions would remove the residual defects, then the court should generally use its equitable discretion to invalidate those additional provisions and uphold the remainder.
But if the court cannot eventually rid the remainder of taint problems, then the remedy should depend on the type of legal defect tainting the remainder. Consider the three types of legal defects discussed above. Neither courts nor agencies can fix rules that are ultra vires or constitutional. In our hypothetical example of the Federal Reserve Board’s banking regulations, neither the reviewing court nor the Board can change the fact that the remainder of the Board’s rule is ultra vires in the absence of pre-established administrative procedures for determining whether a financial institution offers banking services. The same is true for constitutional violations. Thus, if a rule inextricably violates an agency’s congressional mandate or the Constitution, the court should invalidate the entire rule.
By contrast, courts should often use the remand-without-vacatur remedy when a court finds a regulatory remainder to be arbitrary or capricious. Ordinarily, courts “set aside” unlawful agency actions by vacating them, which nullifies the action and requires the agency to initiate new procedures.209 Courts sometimes, however, remand the rule without vacating it,210 which leaves a rule in force while the agency works to cure its defects.211 Remand without vacatur eliminates some of the costs of the remand-and-repromulgation cycle because regulated entities do not have to adjust to a regulatory vacuum during the time that the agency works to fix its original rule’s defects. Of course, if the agency does not eventually revise a remanded rule to the court’s satisfaction, then the court will vacate the rule in its entirety. But while the rule is on remand, regulated entities must still comply with the regulatory remainder.212
Remand without vacatur will often be the appropriate remedy for a rule containing a severability clause whose remainder is arbitrary or capricious. Courts have typically used remand without vacatur in two sets of circumstances: where the court determines (1) that the agency can likely cure a rule’s defects and (2) that vacatur would have disruptive consequences for a regulatory regime.213 With respect to the first circumstance, the promulgating agency can usually fix a regulatory remainder containing a severability clause that a court finds arbitrary and capricious by providing additional reasons for the remainder in the rule’s statement of basis and purpose. With respect to the second circumstance, because agencies do not frequently include severability clauses in their rules, when an agency does so, this provides strong circumstantial evidence that the agency believes that vacatur would have disruptive consequences for its regulatory scheme.
One D.C. Circuit opinion has already suggested this approach to severability. In Alliance for Community Media, a panel of the D.C. Circuit held that FCC regulations authorizing cable providers to ban indecent material on cable access channels violated the First Amendment.214 Consequently, the court had to determine whether to sever the unconstitutional provisions of the FCC’s rule from the regulatory remainder. The court observed that, were it to sever the invalid provisions, it would leave in place a regulatory scheme under which indecent material could be regulated only on cable channels for unaffiliated commercial programmers but not on cable channels set aside for public, educational, or governmental use.215 The FCC, however, had not provided a justification for this seemingly odd distinction between cable access channels. Accordingly, the court was concerned that leaving this scheme in place would be arbitrary and capricious. Rather than invalidate the entire rule, the court remanded it without vacatur.216 The court explained:
[W]here an agency is involved, a court need not strike down a regulation to effect a reconsideration by the issuing body. Thus, a court will issue a remand to the issuing agency if there is “substantial doubt” as to whether the agency intended its regulation to be severable. Such a remand is often in the best interest of justice in that it allows the agency to reconsider the residue of its original regulation and keeps judges out of the business of administrators.217
However, Alliance for Community Media was later vacated,218 and no subsequent cases have followed its approach of ordering remand without vacatur in these circumstances. We agree, however, with Alliance’s approach.
The foregoing discussion explains how courts should proceed at Severability Step One. A court should determine (1) whether invalidating a portion of a rule creates residual legal defects for the regulatory remainder that are substantially related to the challenged provision and (2) whether these defects can be removed. If the defects are inextricable, then the appropriate remedy will depend on the nature of the defect. When the defect is constitutional or ultra vires in nature, the court should set aside the entire rule. But when an inextricable defect renders the rule arbitrary and capricious, the court should generally remand the rule without vacating it. If, on the other hand, the regulatory remainder does not contain inextricable legal defects, the reviewing court should proceed to Severability Step Two, to which we now turn.
2. Step Two: Defer to the Agency
Part I.B showed that if courts deferred to administrative severability clauses, then regulatory schemes would promote expertise, accountability, the rule of law, and efficiency. In light of these potential benefits, we maintain that a court’s review at Severability Step Two should be highly deferential and relatively straightforward: determine what the severability clause requires and follow it.
This thesis requires a defense, of course. The fact that agency decision making on severability is typically better than judicial decision making does not necessarily entail that a reviewing court should always defer to an administrative severability clause. A reviewing court’s severability decision might be more prudent in some cases if it could draw upon an agency’s technical expertise. But not every severability decision will be highly technical. Similarly, the promulgation of some administrative severability clauses may not have involved participation by the public and may not have engendered any great reliance interests. This might lead some to conclude that the deference framework we propose is over-inclusive. One might argue that the fact that agencies are often superior decision makers about severability supports a deference framework more akin to the Skidmore regime, according to which the degree of deference that a severability clause receives should vary with a rule’s technical complexity; the extent to which the agency’s expertise and democratic accountability informed its adoption of the severability clause; and the extent to which the public has relied on the severability clause.219
We must therefore defend our choice of a more rule-like framework over a standard-like framework.220 An extensive literature addresses the considerations that should lead one to favor (or not favor) a rule over a standard.221 The primary drawback of rules is that they are usually over- or under-inclusive with respect to the rulemaker’s underlying policy goals.222 A rule-like framework may therefore lead a court to defer to an administrative severability clause that does not confer the benefits of administrative severability clauses discussed in Part I.B.
We believe, however, that rules have benefits that outweigh their drawbacks (vis-à-vis standards) in the case of deference to administrative severability clauses. First, a rule-like framework would better confine the discretion of lower courts, helping courts higher in the judicial hierarchy overcome principal-agent problems.223 A standard-like framework may influence lower courts to defer to administrative severability clauses not when those clauses, say, reflect the agency’s administrative expertise, but when the court approves of the regulatory scheme that would result from the rule’s remainder. Adopting a rule-like framework would help to curb this shirking tendency.
Second, a rule-like framework would be more predictable and thus would encourage the development of investment-backed expectations.224 As discussed in Part I.B.3, predictability in the law has a number of cost-saving advantages for agencies and regulated entities alike. Because agencies can better predict the effect of a severability clause, they can choose how to use their rulemaking resources most efficiently. If an agency is relatively certain that a court will defer to a severability clause, for example, it may choose to promulgate a set of substantive regulations as a single rule rather than divide the regulations across several rules. The agency might also devote fewer agency resources to explaining how the agency’s administrative expertise informs the adoption of the severability clause. Similarly, regulated entities would be better positioned to organize their affairs around a regulatory scheme because they could more easily predict what the law would be if a challenged provision were eventually set aside.225 Finally, both agencies and regulated entities can save costs associated with the additional expense of litigating the application of a standard as opposed to the application of a rule.226
We also doubt that the over-inclusiveness problem is very severe in the case of a rule-like deference framework for severability clauses. As we explained in Part III.A, agencies tend not to include severability clauses in their rules lightly. When they do include a severability clause, they do so only after deliberation. Moreover, the cost of including a severability clause in a rule, as opposed to opining on severability in litigation, suggests that agencies will include these clauses prudently when they elect to bear these comparatively higher costs.
If one accepts our defense of Chevron-style deference to administrative severability clauses, one might then ask why our proposal is even more deferential than Chevron. At Chevron Step Two, courts defer only to reasonableagency interpretations of ambiguous federal statutes. Why then do we not propose that courts defer only to reasonable administrative severability clauses?
Deference only to putatively reasonable administrative severability clauses, however, would invite courts to determine for themselves whether a regulatory remainder is workable, thereby defeating the very purpose of the deference framework. At Chevron Step Two, the question of reasonableness is a question of legal meaning—that is, whether the agency has adopted a permissible construction of the statutory text (interpreted in light of the traditional tools of statutory construction). That question of reasonableness is still one within the institutional competence of the courts and does not require the reviewing court to evaluate the validity of the agency’s underlying reasons for adopting its construction. By contrast, the question of reasonableness at Severability Step Two would require the reviewing court to determine whether it is permissible for the agency to maintain that the regulatory remainder is workable. This reasonableness question would inherently take the reviewing court outside of its institutional competence and collapse into an evaluation of the substantive regulatory merits of the agency’s decision.
Furthermore, concerns about the unreasonableness of a severability clause are mostly allayed by our proposed residual arbitrary and capricious review, which we outlined in the previous section. If the regulatory remainder lacks a legal defect, such as being ultra vires or inconsistent with the agency’s statement of basis and purpose, then the severability clause will likely not be unreasonable. Accordingly, the deference framework we propose can afford to be even more deferential than Chevron at Step Two without allowing unreasonable severability clauses to escape scrutiny.
3. Step Zero: The Limits of the Deference Framework
An agency may express its opinion on severability through agency actions other than including a severability clause in a rule. As we noted in Part II.B, ordinary agency practice is to opine on severability in trial and appellate briefs. An agency could also opine on severability by issuing any of a variety of informal agency documents, including interpretative rules and guidance manuals, which do not require notice and comment.227 We should therefore defend an underlying assumption of this Article—the assumption that the “domain”228 of a deference framework for severability should be limited to severability clauses. Put differently, we assume that courts should not give Chevron-style deference to other forms of agency action in which an agency might opine on severability.
Several Supreme Court cases might suggest that our deference regime should cast a wider net. The Supreme Court has addressed another “domain” question in the context of determining what agency actions should receive Chevron deference.229 In the leading case, United States v. Mead Corp., the Court considered whether tariff classification rulings by the Customs Service were entitled to Chevron deference.230 The Court held that the tariff classification rulings at issue should not receive Chevron deference because they were not promulgated in the exercise of delegated authority to make rules with the force of law. The Court stated that notice-and-comment rulemaking (and formal adjudication) would presumptively receive Chevron deference but that other agency actions might also qualify for deference when “it appears that Congress delegated authority to the agency generally to make rules carrying the force of law, and that the agency interpretation claiming deference was promulgated in the exercise of that authority.”231 Thus, Mead expressly declined sharply to delimit Chevron’s domain to legislative rules.232
The Supreme Court’s Seminole Rock doctrine requires deference to an even larger set of agency actions. Auer itself, for example, involved an agency interpretation expressed in an amicus brief.233 In MD/DC/DE Broadcasters II, three judges on the D.C. Circuit suggested that Seminole Rock/Auer deference should apply to agency opinions on severability expressed in litigation. In that case, Judge David Tatel dissented from the D.C. Circuit’s denial of rehearing en banc, in an opinion joined by then-Chief Judge Harry Edwards and Judge Judith Rogers. The FCC petitioned for rehearing, requesting that the court reinstate the remainder of a rule. Judge Tatel argued that the agency’s opinion on the severability of its rule was an interpretation of the rule warranting Seminole Rock deference.234 Thus, if judicial deference to an agency’s opinion on severability follows as a direct application of the Seminole Rock doctrine — that is, if courts should defer to administrative severability clauses pursuant to Seminole Rock — then perhaps the domain of our proposed deference framework should not be limited to severability clauses.
Although we agree that administrative severability clauses warrant deference under the Seminole Rock doctrine, we do not think that courts should give Chevron-style deference to agency opinions on severability other than severability clauses.235In large part, our view is based on misgivings we share with several Justices on the Supreme Court about Seminole Rock itself.236 Recently, several Justices have criticized the Seminole Rock doctrine’s tendency to encourage agencies to issue vague rules through notice-and-comment rulemaking and then clarify those rules through less formal, deliberative, and participatory procedures.237 Some Justices worry that the Seminole Rock doctrine creates incentives that ultimately undermine the accountability, transparency, and predictability of administrative rulemaking.238
There are similar concerns about incentives related to informal agency opinions on severability. Part II.B noted that the current severability doctrine does not create adequate incentives for agencies to promulgate severability clauses through notice-and-comment procedures. So giving the same Chevron-style deference to agency opinions on severability expressed through informal agency actions would seem to undermine an agency’s incentive to use more formal procedures.239
Chevron-style deference for informal agency opinions on severability would also generate uncertainty. A reviewing court cannot, as a practical matter, give Chevron-style deference to every agency informal opinion on severability because agency officials may express inconsistent opinions. Accordingly, a deference framework that would give Chevron-style deference to some informal agency actions would have to apply a meta-standard for determining which agency actions warrant deference.240 Such a meta-standard, however, would likely produce inefficient litigation over the proper application of the standard in individual cases. Chevron-style deference for agency opinions on severability should therefore be reserved for severability clauses.
Reserving Chevron-style deference for severability clauses does not mean, however, that a reviewing court should give no deference to an agency’s opinion on severability expressed in an informal agency action. We think informal agency opinions on severability should receive Skidmore deference.241 When notice-and-comment procedures are prohibitively time- and resource-consuming, informal agency opinions on severability can generate some of a severability clause’s benefits. For example, even if a court does not defer to an agency’s informal opinion on severability and strikes down a rule entirely, an informal opinion on severability could promote predictability because it could indicate how the agency is likely to proceed in the future. Suppose, for example, that an agency promulgates provisions A and B as part of regulation R and states in an informal agency opinion that provisions A and B are severable. Assume further that a court later rules that provision A is unlawful and inseverable from provision B. In this case, though the agency’s opinion was ineffective at preventing a court from striking down the rule, the opinion would still give regulated entities some evidence that the agency is likely, in the future, to re-promulgate provision B even in the absence of provision A.
Furthermore, since agencies do not use severability clauses frequently,242 agencies will likely clarify the severability of current regulations, if at all, through informal agency actions. Although we prefer that agencies opine on severability using severability clauses, amending existing rules that would benefit from an agency opinion on severability may be too cumbersome or costly.243 In these circumstances, we think an agency should be given incentives to opine on the severability of its rules, even if the agency does not express its opinion through a formal amendment to a rule. Accordingly, we think Skidmore deference is appropriate to encourage an agency to clarify its position on severability rather than remain silent.
Under this approach, the various tiers of deference would appropriately match the diligence the agency used in expressing its opinion on severability. A reviewing court would reward an agency for an informal opinion on severability with deference tailored to the degree of care and expertise that the agency employed in adopting that opinion. Further, if an agency chose to invest even greater resources by promulgating a severability clause through the rigors of notice and comment, then a reviewing court would give additional deference in recognition of the greater rulemaking benefits that those procedures entail.
Conclusion
The current doctrine and agency practice on administrative severability clauses is unfortunate. Administrative severability clauses allow agencies to express their expert and popularly informed opinion on the severability of their rules. And if courts routinely deferred to those opinions, they would promote expertise, accountability, the rule of law, and efficiency in regulatory schemes.
However, the federal courts have implicitly analogized administrative severability clauses to severability clauses contained in statutes. Based on this analogy, federal courts have developed a doctrine in which the severability decision “will rarely turn on the presence or absence of . . . a[n] [administrative severability] clause.”244 As a consequence, agencies have diminished incentives to promulgate their opinions on severability by means of notice-and-comment procedures. And the actual frequency with which agencies include severability clauses in their rules reflects these diminished incentives. Agencies have been content to leave the severability decision to the courts.
Current doctrine and agency practice suggest that courts need a deference framework for administrative severability clauses. Under this framework, courts should police the boundaries of the agency’s lawmaking authority by ensuring that regulatory remainders are lawful. But when a regulatory remainder is lawful, a reviewing court should follow the opinion an agency expressed in a severability clause.
For the Appendix, please see the PDF.