Governance Reform and the Judicial Role in Municipal Bankruptcy
abstract. Recent proceedings involving large municipalities such as Detroit, Stockton, and Vallejo illustrate both the utility and limitations of using the Bankruptcy Code to adjust municipal debt. In this Article, we contend that, to resolve fully the distress of a substantial city, municipal bankruptcy needs to provide more than simple debt reduction. Debt adjustment alone does nothing to remedy the fragmented decision making and incentives for expanding municipal budgets that are ingrained in municipal governance structures and that often underlie municipal distress. Unless bankruptcy also addresses governance dysfunction, the city faces a return to financial distress. Indeed, this Article demonstrates that governance restructuring has long been an essential element of corporate bankruptcy and that, given the monopoly position of local governments as providers of local public goods, it is even more important in the municipal bankruptcy context.
Some might argue that reducing a city’s debt is the best that bankruptcy courts can offer, due to concerns that a more comprehensive approach would, among other things, interfere with state sovereignty and exceed the statutory authority that the Bankruptcy Code grants to courts. In our view, these concerns do not withstand scrutiny. Based on a careful analysis of the origins of the current municipal bankruptcy provisions, as well as an assessment of recent Supreme Court jurisprudence, we argue that governance reform is permitted even under existing law, and point out that minor adjustments to municipal bankruptcy law would make this conclusion even clearer. To be sure, the states themselves, rather than a bankruptcy court, ideally should be the ones to effect municipal governance reform. But political factors and the imperatives of the immediate fiscal crisis make state intervention unlikely, thus underscoring the need for a more comprehensive approach to municipal bankruptcy.
authors.Clayton P. Gillette is the Max E. Greenberg Professor of Contract Law, New York University School of Law. David A. Skeel, Jr. is the S. Samuel Arsht Professor of Corporate Law, University of Pennsylvania Law School. We are grateful to Mehrsa Baradaran, Oren Bar-Gill, Kent Barnett, Randy Beck, Mitchell Berman, Martin Bienenstock, Vincent Buccola, Nathan Chapman, Andrew Crespo, Jaime Dodge, Gerald Frug, Brian Galle, Howell Jackson, Melissa Jacoby, Seth Kreimer, Bruce Mann, Martha Minow, Mark Ramseyer, Eric Rasmusen, Lori Ringhand, Usha Rodrigues, Mark Roe, Bo Rutledge, Darien Shanske, James Sprayregen, Paul Stephan, Adrian Vermeule, Steven Walt, and participants at faculty workshops at Harvard Law School; the University of Virginia School of Law; the University of California, Davis School of Law; the University of Texas School of Law; the University of Georgia School of Law; and the “Creditors and Corporate Governance in Bankruptcy” Conference at the University of Chicago Law School for helpful comments. We are also grateful to Kyle Lachmund, Nonny Onyekweli, and Antonio Pietrantoni for invaluable research assistance.
As an increasing number of municipalities take advantage of
the ability to adjust their debts under Chapter 9 of the Bankruptcy Code, the
utility and efficiency of that scheme has become more apparent.1 Fears that Chapter 9 would be
incapable of handling the fiscal distress of large cities have dissipated as
bankruptcy courts have deftly managed the bankruptcies of Vallejo, San
Bernardino, and Stockton, California; Jefferson County, Alabama; and Detroit,
Michigan.2 These episodes have revealed that
bankruptcy courts can balance the interests of the various
stakeholders—creditors, pensioners, the state, and
residents—involved when municipalities face fiscal distress. Less clear is whether the dexterity that bankruptcy courts
display in adjusting municipal debts has lasting effects on municipal fiscal
health. Courts tend to focus almost exclusively on the debt overhang
problem—that is, on reducing the municipality’s debt burden to a level
that permits a city to devote scarce resources to providing services rather
than solely to paying creditors. To the extent that municipal distress results
from a debt burden that stifles investment and diverts municipal budgets to
legacy costs rather than future productivity, the ability to pare down a
municipality’s debt may be sufficient. But municipal distress—especially the distress of a
substantial city—rarely is simply a matter of too much debt. Failed
budget policies do not arise autonomously, disaggregated from the political
environment in which they are devised. Rather, with the exception of cases in
which municipalities face some exogenous shock, such as a crippling tort suit
or natural disaster, or in which local governments suffer from broad economic
disruptions beyond their control, local fiscal crises usually are caused by a
governance structure that tolerates financial decisions in which the benefits
and costs of public expenditures are misaligned. The disparity may be temporal.
Local political officials concerned about electoral success or opportunities
for higher office may favor programs that promise short-term benefits paid for
through long-term costs. Alternatively, the mismatch may be spatial. Programs
that produce highly concentrated benefits in some districts within the locality
may be financed by imposing costs on neighboring districts, with the result
that the commons of the municipal budget faces overuse.3
Or, officials may adopt policies that confer inefficient benefits on small,
concentrated groups and discourage electoral redress by spreading the costs
among the diffuse electorate.4 The institutions of local governance that permit these
misalignments tend to be entrenched in city charters or bureaucratic regimes,
and left unchallenged, they survive even after bankruptcy proceedings adjust
the debts to which they have given rise. According to the conventional wisdom,
Chapter 9 has little to say about these issues other than to preclude the
bankruptcy court from usurping the political or governmental powers of the
municipal debtor.5
If the conventional wisdom is correct, Chapter 9 cannot meaningfully reduce the
risk of recidivism for a financially distressed municipality. The debt
adjustment provided by Chapter 9 offers temporary relief before the next
crisis, not a thoroughgoing remedy aimed at the root causes of municipal
distress. This Article challenges the traditional account. We contend
that municipal bankruptcy can and should address governance failures where they
contribute to financial failures. We argue that this conclusion follows from an
appreciation of the similarities between municipal corporations and the
for-profit corporations that are reorganized in Chapter 11 of the Bankruptcy
Code. Where governance failures contribute to corporate financial distress, no
one would treat governance reform as irrelevant to the reorganization of a
corporation. Carefully crafted governance rules were a central feature of the
Chrysler bankruptcy,6 and governance
rules figure prominently in most other substantial Chapter 11 cases as well.
From a purely functional perspective, governance reform is even more essential
to an effective Chapter 9 municipal bankruptcy than it is in Chapter 11, since
at least some stakeholders in insolvent municipalities are more dependent on
those entities than are stakeholders in insolvent firms. Municipal bankruptcy does not just facilitate governance
reform: in many cases, the logic of the municipal bankruptcy process requires governance reform. The
public—and inherently political—nature of municipal debtors has
traditionally been seen to preclude the use of Chapter 9 for anything other
than reducing a municipality’s debt.7
Our position is that the political nature of municipal fiscal distress has precisely
the opposite implication. The financial distress of a substantial municipality
nearly always signals that its politics are dysfunctional. The same entrenched
political environment that exacerbates fiscal instability may also frustrate
efforts to initiate reforms necessary to escape a cycle of financial
irresponsibility. That entrenchment can be overcome only by the inducement or
imposition of structural reforms from outside the municipality. Ideally, the outside catalyst would be the state, which retains
substantial authority over its political subdivisions. But political
entrenchment may also constrain the state from inducing or imposing structural
reforms that are needed for fiscal stability. Where that is the case, and where
the state accedes to a municipality’s use of the federal bankruptcy courts, we
conclude that the bankruptcy judge should and does have leeway to induce
necessary reforms. Yet discussions of Chapter 9 consistently ignore the
possibility of governance reform, even where it is essential to revive a
financially failed municipality. Although conventional wisdom suggests that
governance reform in bankruptcy infringes on state sovereignty, which perhaps
explains its neglect, we contend that governance restructuring in Chapter 9 passes
constitutional muster. Two decades ago, Michael McConnell and Randal Picker made the
most comprehensive argument to date for moving beyond the debt-adjustment model
of municipal bankruptcy.8 They contended that municipal
bankruptcy should permit reorganization of municipal structures in ways that
were analogous to the reorganization of firms in Chapter 11. For McConnell and
Picker, the expanded powers of the court would include authority to mandate
“politically unpopular reforms,”9 such as
authority to collect taxes to pay preexisting debt; to order reductions in
expenditures; to sell municipal assets; and perhaps even to reorganize the
boundaries of or to dissolve the debtor municipality based on applicable state-law
principles.10
McConnell and Picker advocated that these reforms take place in state
bankruptcy proceedings rather than in federal bankruptcy court.11
Implicit in McConnell and Picker’s recommendations is an optimistic story of a
benign state willing and able to enact reforms that facilitate municipal fiscal
discipline. We share McConnell and Picker’s intuition that relief for
fiscally distressed municipalities necessarily entails more than debt
reduction. We focus, however, on the design of municipal decision-making
institutions rather than boundaries or tax decisions, and look to the federal
bankruptcy court as the catalyst for reform. Where the state intervenes to
redress structural difficulties that cause fiscal distress, there may be little
need for bankruptcy court intervention. But where the state fails to do so because
of its own political constraints, rather than as a consequence of a deliberate
decision, we find fewer reasons to preclude bankruptcy courts from filling the
gap. While state political inertia has always been a concern, its salience has
increased considerably in the two decades since McConnell and Picker wrote
their classic article. In short, we view bankruptcy court intervention into
municipal governance as an option, not a requirement. It is warranted by the
same entrenchment problem that has led commentators to advocate for more
intensive judicial intervention in other public arenas, such as voting rights
or prison reform, where political incentives inhibit changes that one might
otherwise prefer be made through the political process.12
Indeed, we anticipate that the very presence of the option will make its
exercise less necessary, as states otherwise politically constrained from
enacting necessary reforms for distressed municipalities may prefer to do so
themselves, rather than leave the task to bankruptcy courts. The Article proceeds as follows. Part I explores the
similarities between the roles of municipalities and private corporations as
providers of services, but emphasizes that the monopoly position of the former
justifies a greater concern for protecting municipalities’ ongoing viability,
rather than simply maximizing the recoveries of creditors. This distinction,
which seems to be reflected in the greater emphasis on a fresh start in
municipal bankruptcy than in Chapter 11, underscores the need to address a
municipal debtor’s underlying problems, rather than solely reduce the amount of
its debt. Even if governance reform was unheard of in Chapter 11, there would
be a powerful case for attending to governance concerns in Chapter 9. In fact,
governance reform is not rare in Chapter 11; it is ubiquitous. Part II raises the question of why, if governance reform is
so common in Chapter 11, such reform does not currently occur in Chapter 9
cases. An obvious answer might be that state sovereignty precludes governance
reform. However, based on a careful analysis of the history of municipal
bankruptcy, starting with the first municipal bankruptcy law in 1934, we offer
an alternative explanation: historical path dependence is at least as important
as constitutional concerns. At key junctures, lawmakers seriously considered
explicitly incorporating governance reform into Chapter 9, but the proposals
were overtaken by events such as the need for immediate resolution of New York
City’s fiscal crisis in the 1970s. Part III develops our affirmative case that governance reform
is essential to the effective restructuring of a substantial municipality. This
Part argues not only that governance reform is permissible, but that bankruptcy
courts should refuse—on
feasibility grounds—to confirm a restructuring plan that fails to reform
municipal governance structures responsible for the distress that generated the
Chapter 9 proceeding.13 Part IV
considers potential objections to our vision for Chapter 9, including the
limited scope of municipal bankruptcy proceedings and constitutional concerns
such as the Supreme Court’s commandeering cases. In our view, none of these
objections preclude governance reform in Chapter 9. Part V takes up an equally substantial objection: that the
state, not a bankruptcy court, should be the entity implementing governance
reform. Although we fully endorse state intervention and agree that state
reform is the optimal solution for a municipality’s governance dysfunction, we
argue that doctrinal constraints limit states’ effectiveness to some extent and
that political constraints are an even more serious obstacle to state reform.
These impediments confirm the need for thoroughgoing reform in municipal
bankruptcy. In this Part, we lay the initial groundwork for our claims
about the proper scope of municipal bankruptcy by considering the similarities
and differences between municipalities and private corporations. If we
conceptualize municipalities and private corporations as alternative vehicles for
providing goods and services and consider the role of bankruptcy from this
perspective, the need to include governance reform as part of the toolkit for
addressing the financial distress of a substantial municipality becomes clear.
Governance reform is not a new concept in bankruptcy; rather, it is already
central to many Chapter 11 cases. A key objective of Chapter 11 reorganization is to restore
the fiscal stability of a potentially viable firm so that it can efficiently
provide valuable goods and services. Much of the corporate-bankruptcy
literature focuses entirely on the benefits to creditors of this restored
productivity. If creditors would be better off maintaining the firm as a going
concern, according to this reasoning, then reorganization is appropriate. But
if dissolving the firm maximizes the payout to creditors, then selling the
assets and distributing the proceeds to creditors should be followed—even
if reorganization might seem to serve the interests of current employees,
equity holders, or other third parties.14
Conventional literature views corporate bankruptcy solely as a mechanism for
the efficient collection and payment of debts; rehabilitation of the firm for
its own sake at best risks inefficiencies and at worst is “nonsense.”15 The creditor collection—or
creditors’ bargain, as it is usually known—conception of bankruptcy is
contested,16
but we take it as a given here, in order to highlight a key difference between
private corporations and municipalities. Even if compelling in the corporate context, the creditors’
bargain conception is an awkward fit for municipalities. Like private
corporations, municipalities provide goods and services for which there is
substantial demand. And financial failure ensues when a municipality is unable
to provide those goods and services at a price (the taxes imposed by the
municipality) that residents are willing to pay. At that point, much like the firm
that is unable to generate sufficient revenues to pay its debts, the
municipality suffers insolvency as residents (the municipal equivalent of both
customers and equity holders) with sufficient means emigrate to other
jurisdictions, and those residents who remain are unable to make the higher tax
payments necessary to service existing indebtedness.17
As in the case of the insolvent firm, restructuring can be justified if it will
enable creditors to recover more than they would receive if the municipality
tried to pay all of its obligations in full. Municipal corporations, however, possess other
characteristics that make the case for a more extensive
restructuring—restructuring that includes governance reform as well as
debt adjustment—stronger than under the parsimonious view of corporate
reorganization. The conception of corporate bankruptcy as a pure collection
device is premised on the assumption that the troubled firm is one of numerous
firms that are competing in an active marketplace. The failure of one firm in
an active market does not substantially disadvantage customers, since they can
purchase similar goods from competitors; nor does a firm’s failure reduce
overall employment if employees can migrate to other jobs where they can be
more productive.18
These assumptions may reflect a somewhat romantic vision of consumer and labor
mobility, but for ordinary corporations, they often are close enough to reality
to justify the conclusion that rehabilitating a failed firm for its own sake is
unlikely to maximize social welfare under ordinary circumstances. Those same assumptions, however, are less plausible in the
municipal context. The goods and services that municipalities provide tend to
be public goods—goods that are nonrival or nonexcludable—or goods
subject to a natural monopoly.19 A private
provider is unlikely to produce these goods, notwithstanding substantial demand
for them, due to uncertainty about the ability to recover the costs of
production.20 If goods with these characteristics
are to be efficiently provided, governmental participation—either by
direct provision or by contracting for them to be provided by third
parties—is necessary, or at least appropriate.21
Local governments, rather than more centralized political
entities, properly play this role when the goods at issue have a limited
geographic scope (such as policing, firefighting, or street lighting) or take
the form of club goods that are preferred by a limited group of residents who
also are willing to pay for them (such as municipal golf courses or public
playgrounds for children).22 By offering
distinct bundles of goods and services, local governments allow prospective
residents to sort themselves according to their preferences for public goods,
just as market transactions permit consumers to sort themselves by preferences
in the characteristics of private goods. For example, those who prefer
proximity to their workplace may live in the central city, while those who
prefer low-density living may migrate to the suburbs, just as those who like
whole-wheat bread can sort themselves from those who prefer sourdough by making
appropriate market purchases.23 When municipalities petition for relief under Chapter 9, they
do so primarily because fiscal distress precludes the delivery of the very services
that municipalities were created to provide and of which they are monopoly
providers. Recognizing the distinctive nature of municipalities, several
bankruptcy courts recently have focused on service delivery, not debt service
alone, as a measure of whether a municipal debtor is “insolvent”24
and thus eligible for municipal bankruptcy.25
Similarly, a municipality that desires to exit Chapter 9 must submit to the
court a plan that is “feasible,” which courts increasingly have interpreted to
mean that “the debtor can accomplish what the plan proposes and provide
governmental services.”26 It is presumably to address the
service function of municipalities that the entire structure of Chapter 9 is
commonly described as providing a municipality with a fresh start as in the
case of an individual bankruptcy, rather than a mechanism purely for the
collection of assets to maximize the payout for creditors as in the case of
corporate bankruptcy.27 The increasing emphasis on service
delivery suggests that bankruptcy courts recognize that failing to restore
local public goods induces flight by those who pay taxes in excess of the
benefits they receive from the locality, followed by the imposition of even
higher taxes and fees on the remaining residents in order to pay fixed
municipal costs, and followed by additional exodus.28
From this perspective, Chapter 9’s restrictive scope of
restructuring seems anomalous. The fact that local governments provide public
goods otherwise undersupplied due to market failures means that market
solutions cannot remedy government failures. As a result, if the locality fails
to provide desired services, immobile residents will likely be unable to obtain
them. Relatively wealthy firms and individuals may be able to privatize
inadequate public services; firms and some individuals may substitute private
security, private education, private garbage collection, or private parks (such
as country clubs) for municipal services.29 But even these residents will be
exposed to the consequences of service-delivery insolvency when they venture
beyond their homes and places of business. For example, during Bridgeport’s
insolvency proceedings, the Chief of Police and the Director of Public Works
testified that budget cuts to their departments would destroy Bridgeport’s
ability to investigate property crime, collect residential garbage, or plow
snow-filled streets, creating a health and public-service emergency.30
As public services deteriorate, those with the means to flee insolvent
localities frequently do so.31 But many residents who suffer the
effects of service-delivery insolvency will be unable to migrate to an
alternative jurisdiction, and the residents who remain are likely to be those least
able to replace the services with even imperfect substitutes from private
providers. Given the logic of municipal decline, one might assume that
municipal bankruptcy would give a municipal debtor at least as many tools,
including governance restructuring, as are available to reorganize private
corporations. Alas, that supposition is not borne out by municipal bankruptcy
as currently conceived. Chapter 9 borrows numerous provisions from Chapter 11,32
and a Chapter 9 case proceeds very much like a traditional Chapter 11 case. In
Chapter 9, as in Chapter 11, the debtor negotiates with the creditors’
committee33
and other constituencies over the terms of a restructuring plan;34
the debtor submits the plan to its creditors for a vote;35
and, if each class votes in favor and the plan satisfies a list of other
confirmation requirements, the bankruptcy court confirms the plan.36
Despite these similarities, Chapter 9 has a much narrower scope than Chapter
11. The latter permits governance restructuring where mismanagement is viewed
as a cause of the firm’s failure.37 Not so in
Chapter 9, at least according to the conventional wisdom treating debt
reduction as the sole purpose of municipal bankruptcy. Chapter 9’s system of
debt adjustment addresses the immediate fiscal crisis but, as currently
applied, does not address the governance structure that may have generated
oppressive debt in the first instance. That is the case even though addressing
underlying governance issues is more important for troubled municipalities than
for private corporations. The discussion thus far suggests that, even if governance
reform were absent from Chapter 11, it would be an essential feature of
municipal bankruptcy, given the distinctive nature of the goods and services
that municipalities produce. But governance reform is not absent from Chapter
11 at all. It is ubiquitous. Corporate debtors regularly take advantage of the
reorganization process to reshape their governance as well as to restructure
their debt. The attention given to governance issues in Chapter 11 underscores
the incongruity of omitting governance reform from municipal bankruptcy. In recent years, lenders increasingly have forced certain
kinds of governance change, such as the hiring of a chief restructuring officer
even before a troubled company files for bankruptcy.38 But more pervasive reform usually
takes place only in Chapter 11 bankruptcy proceedings. Lenders may prefer that
governance be addressed in bankruptcy rather than through contract alone
because they fear the risk of potential liability if they are later deemed to
have overreached.39 Moreover, substantial governance
restructuring may be nearly impossible to achieve outside of bankruptcy.
Reorganization of the debtor’s board or alteration of shareholder-voting rules
usually requires approval of both the board of directors and the firm’s
shareholders.40
If either constituency will be disadvantaged by the changes, as quite often
will be the case, they are well positioned to thwart reform outside of
bankruptcy. Even companies whose governance is relatively effective when
they file for bankruptcy may need to make significant governance adjustments as
part of their restructuring process. Chapter 11 shifts control from the
debtor’s shareholders to its creditors, and usually transfers ownership rights
to creditors as well.41 These
transitions create the potential for significant conflict that is best managed
through carefully crafted governance rules.42 In the Chrysler bankruptcy, for
instance, Fiat, Chrysler retirees, and the U.S. and Canadian governments
received large ownership interests as a result of the restructuring.43
To protect each of these constituencies, Chrysler’s new organizational
documents specified that Fiat would designate three of Chrysler’s nine
directors, the retirees would designate one, the Canadian government one, and
the U.S. government three.44 Although
Chrysler’s reforms were especially elaborate, governance reforms that allocate
board seats to specified constituencies, create voting trusts, or make other
adjustments are a standard feature of substantial Chapter 11 cases.45 Courts do not necessarily intervene in Chapter 11 proceedings
by proposing specific structural changes. More often, bankruptcy judges confirm
plans that contain restructuring provisions provided by others since bankruptcy
judges are responsible for approving or rejecting reorganization plans but are
not permitted to propose a plan.46 The negative
implication of that process is that a court could
refuse to confirm a Chapter 11 plan that did not contain structural reform. But
creditors can insert themselves directly into the debtor’s governance in
Chapter 11 and have a strong incentive to do so. Because some creditors’ claims
are likely to be converted into equity in the reorganized debtor, creditors
often receive a governance role to protect their interest and to reduce the
risk of renewed financial distress.47 In the municipal environment, by contrast, creditors who
suffer reduced entitlements in bankruptcy proceedings are not granted any
decision-making role in postbankruptcy municipal governance. Even if creditors
in a Chapter 9 proceeding receive modified obligations, such as bonds payable
in ten years to displace existing bonds due immediately, no plan of adjustment
has ever granted the creditors a seat on the city council while the
restructured debt was outstanding.48 But the fact that creditors do not participate directly in
postbankruptcy municipal governance does not make restructuring inappropriate
or unnecessary. It means only that governance reform may need to occur by other
means. Creditors’ inability to dislodge the current governance structure
increases the need for third-party intervention to ensure that Chapter 9 fully addresses
the underlying causes of municipal financial distress. In the last Part, we considered how corporate-bankruptcy
proceedings commonly include governance reform as a means of increasing the
likelihood that the firm will operate successfully once it exits Chapter 11. To
our knowledge, there are no analogous cases of governance reform in Chapter 9.
The primary reason for the discrepancy lies in § 904 of the Bankruptcy Code.49
That provision precludes the court from interfering with any of the political
or governmental powers of the debtor. But the prohibition does not apply if
“the debtor consents or the plan so provides,”50
suggesting a broader scope for restructuring with debtor approval.51 One might think that in at least
some cases, local officials would benefit from restructuring and thus would
consent to its use in Chapter 9. Section 903, however, implies an additional
limitation on restructuring. That provision confirms the state’s power to
control a municipality in the exercise of political or governmental powers and
thus could be construed to disable a court from engaging in activities that
affect local institutional design.52
Together, these provisions suggest congressional concern with
constitutional limitations on federal diminution of state sovereignty in
Chapter 9 proceedings. Any such concerns might seem to preclude the exercise of
independent restructuring authority by a federal bankruptcy court.53
Some courts have stated explicitly that § 903 and § 904 are necessary to ensure
the constitutionality of Chapter 9.54
While these provisions may support the idea that Congress designed Chapter 9 to
avoid interference with state sovereignty, in Section IV.C we explain why
municipal restructuring does not run afoul of constitutional principles. Before engaging in that debate, however, we revisit the
history of municipal bankruptcy reform and show that constitutional concerns
are not nearly as complete an explanation for the absence of governance reform in
Chapter 9 as one might think. The municipal bankruptcies that gave rise to
Chapter 9 and its predecessors were due either to circumstances that governance
reform would not have addressed or to fiscal crises that superseded any
aspirations for governance reform. During the debates on the earliest
municipal bankruptcy laws, lawmakers were preoccupied with municipalities’
inability to restructure debts rendered unaffordable by the Depression, and
sought to enact legislation that would reduce the immediate problem. They were
not, by contrast, attempting to provide a comprehensive solution. When
municipal bankruptcy returned to legislative attention four decades later,
witnesses offered proposals that would have incorporated governance reform
directly and explicitly into municipal bankruptcy. These proposals fell by the
wayside, not because of any perceived constitutional infirmity, but because
Congress chose a different, nonbankruptcy solution to the most pressing crisis
of the time—New York City’s financial distress. Thus, path dependence has
played a more pivotal role in defining the scope of municipal bankruptcy law
than investigation of constitutional principles. The original municipal bankruptcy law was enacted in 1934 as
part of the New Deal response to the wreckage of the Great Depression. In the
early 1930s, thousands of municipalities defaulted as real-estate values
collapsed and taxpayers were unable to pay assessed property taxes.55
Although municipalities theoretically could have restructured their obligations
outside of bankruptcy, holdouts often stymied these efforts. “In every instance
where a governmental unit finds itself in financial difficulty and is able to
make some satisfactory agreement of adjustment with a majority of its
creditors,” as Congressman Mark Wilcox, the author of and leading advocate for
a municipal bankruptcy law,56 put it, “there is always a small
minority who hold out and demand preferential treatment.”57 State efforts to compel adjustment
of municipal debts would founder on the shoals of the Contracts Clause of the
U.S. Constitution.58 But because the
Contracts Clause does not bind the federal government,59
federal bankruptcy law provided a plausible solution to the problem of debt
overhang. The original municipal bankruptcy law sought to solve the
holdout problem by binding all bondholders, even the dissenters, if a majority
voted to restructure the bonds.60 The proponents of the law thought
that a more comprehensive framework was unnecessary. They also were well aware
that their proposal was constitutionally uncertain, since Congress had never
previously enacted a bankruptcy law for public entities like municipalities.61 And they needed to allay the
concerns of bondholders, who worried that municipal debtors would
opportunistically walk away from their debt. As a result, the original 1934 law
called for the equivalent of what we now refer to as a prepackaged
bankruptcy—a case in which the debtor has secured the approval of its key
creditors before filing for bankruptcy and files a proposed reorganization plan
at the same time or shortly thereafter.62
The 1934 law required the municipality to secure approval by creditors holding
fifty-one percent of the municipality’s debt—except with drainage
districts and the like, for which the requirement was thirty percent—before
filing its petition, and to file a proposed plan of adjustment with the
petition.63
As amended in 1937, after the Supreme Court struck down the original law,64
the municipal bankruptcy provisions imposed the fifty-one percent creditor
approval requirement in all cases.65
Throughout the process, Congress simply assumed, rather than
analyzed, the constitutional scope of federal judicial intervention into
municipal affairs. For the most part, statements made during the legislative
process in defense of the bill’s constitutionality were directed at complaints
that any law authorizing municipal bankruptcy necessarily infringed unconstitutionally
on state sovereignty.66 Little
evidence suggests that Congress was attempting to define the limits of federal
bankruptcy authority. Congressman Wilcox expressed confidence that the bill as
proposed protected the sovereignty of states and did not permit the federal
government “to interfere in any degree with any of the governmental or
political subdivisions of the local municipalities.”67
David M. Wood, a lawyer representing the creditors of fifty troubled
municipalities, contended that the bill had been carefully crafted to avoid the
constitutional questions that would arise if municipalities were subject to
involuntary bankruptcy.68 During the
debate on the original Act, Wilcox similarly highlighted the voluntary nature
of the filing and the plan of adjustment as the hallmark of constitutionality.69
Lawmakers did emphasize that judges would play a minimal role and that state
authorization was necessary.70 But in doing
so, they were responding to specific objections that, if Congress enacted the
law, cities would rush into bankruptcy to repudiate debts.71
Proponents of the bill were suggesting that courts and states would serve as
constraints on permissive debt avoidance. The lawmakers did not appear to be
exploring the constitutional limits of federal bankruptcy jurisdiction. True, a memorandum submitted by the Department of Justice
concluded that states may not abdicate or delegate essential powers of
government, and that state authorization for municipalities to file petitions
under a federal bankruptcy law that “does not permit interference with the
municipalities’ governmental functions would not constitute such an abdication
or delegation.”72
However, nothing in that memorandum explained what an unconstitutional “interference”
would look like. The memorandum referred to Congress’s inability “to regulate,
directly or indirectly, the fiscal policies of the States or their governmental
agencies,”73
perhaps because that issue arose in the congressional debates. Wilcox noted
that no one would want to surrender to any court the power of levying taxes,
“even if it could constitutionally be done.”74
Wilcox later dropped this agnosticism about the constitutional limits of
municipal bankruptcy, stating that an 1883 Supreme Court decision held that [n]o court has the right . . . to interfere with the
discretion of municipal officials as to the amount of money which they shall
pay to the police department, or the fire department, or the sanitary
department, or as to the ratio among the three, or as to any other government
function.75
But even that statement appears to have been intended to
provide assurances concerning the limits of the present bill, rather than a
discourse on constitutional constraints. Indeed, it appears that Wilcox’s
reference was to the 1880 case of Meriwether
v. Garrett.76
If so, his statement of the case substantially overstates the relevant holding:
that case held little more than that courts may not directly impose taxes to
pay a valid claim against a municipality, but instead must, by writ of
mandamus, require the officials properly designated by the legislature to levy
and collect any tax available.77 While the
Court revealed an aversion to any “invasion by the judiciary of the Federal
government of the legislative functions of the State government,”78
it is less clear that a federal court exercising authority under the Bankruptcy
Clause to approve restructuring of a municipality’s governance would constitute
such an incursion. Wilcox insisted that the bankruptcy court could require the
municipality to levy taxes to repay bondholders. Although a bankruptcy court
would not be able to determine the priority of municipal expenditures as
between, for example, paying police or fire fighters,79
he argued, “[S]o far as contracts or debts are concerned, the municipality
having contracted a debt, or a promise to pay, that permits them to levy taxes
. . . the court can itself enforce that contract by requiring the levying of
whatever taxes are necessary to meet that debt.”80
Wilcox envisioned, in effect, that the bankruptcy court would exercise all of
the powers that are theoretically available to a court pursuant to a mandamus
action outside of bankruptcy.81 Lawmakers were trying to solve a more limited problem,
however, in a context where the scope of their powers under the Bankruptcy
Clause of the Constitution was unclear. The statute they enacted sought to
achieve a single objective—preventing holdouts from scuttling a
restructuring that most creditors had approved.82
Governance reform was not on their agenda. Perhaps the reason for this was that the distress that
affected municipalities during the Depression was thought to have been caused
by the general economic conditions of the time, rather than by poor decision
making or dysfunctional municipal governance. This view may have oversimplified
the source of municipal distress. Politically opportune decisions to incur debt
do seem to have been on the rise during the period immediately preceding the
Depression. Total municipal debt (less sinking-fund assets) grew from just
under $3.5 billion in 1912 to over $15 billion in 1932.83 Between 1922 and 1931, the net
municipal debts of seventeen states more than doubled.84
Only in frugal Minnesota and North Dakota did debt levels decline during this
period.85
Yet the 1934 legislation was premised on the view that even for Detroit, the
city whose financial plight was most serious, the Depression was the problem,
not municipal governance.86 Even those commentators who concluded that municipalities had
taken on too much debt did not identify flawed governance as the explanation.
For example, writing in 1936, Albert Miller Hillhouse, the Director of Research
of the Municipal Finance Officers’ Association,87
criticized the fiscal overextension of many municipalities, but attributed it
to an overly optimistic view that the real-estate boom of the prior decade
would continue, rather than to the politics behind those miscalculations.88
Yet Hillhouse’s analysis suggests that political arrangements were an important
causal element. He noted that “[b]oth civic-minded and non-civic-minded
pressure groups sponsor new or expanded services in prosperous times, many of
which are very necessary. . . . The combined pressure of these groups
constitutes a real driving force. No increase in government service is
advisable, however, if the community cannot afford it.”89 Hillhouse therefore revealed a sentiment that today might
be cast in more concrete public-choice terms concerning the relationship
between “pressure groups” and the size of government. Focus on that
relationship might have allowed more direct attention to solutions that could
forestall municipal distress, even in times of widespread economic crisis. But
there appears to have been little consideration of the possibility that the
design of governmental decision making could reduce recidivism, much less that
the bankruptcy process should be the means for accomplishing that objective. In Ashton v. Cameron
County Water Improvement District No. 1,90
the Supreme Court invalidated the 1934 municipal bankruptcy law, based on an
extraordinarily broad interpretation of the Tenth Amendment as precluding any
federal authority over municipalities, and on the grounds that the Act violated
the Contracts Clause.91 The opinion
has largely been discredited.92 The statute
provided that only voluntary petitions by the distressed municipality were
cognizable in bankruptcy.93 Moreover, the
statute rejected any federal intent to limit or impair the power of states,
including “the power to require the approval by any governmental agency of the
State of the filing of any petition hereunder and of any plan of readjustment,”
and denied the right to file a bankruptcy petition to any political subdivision
over which the state had assumed supervision or control.94
These provisions led Justice Cardozo to conclude in his dissent in Ashton that the statute “has been framed
with sedulous regard to the structure of the federal system.”95
Nevertheless, the Ashton majority
opinion endorsed a view of federalism so strict that Congress could not enact a
bankruptcy law that covered municipalities even with the consent of the state.96
That position was taken on the non sequitur that such consent would constitute
a violation of state sovereignty and an unlawful enlargement of the powers of
Congress, notwithstanding that states “may voluntarily consent to be sued;
[and] may permit actions against [their] political subdivisions to enforce
their obligations” without violating that same principle.97
To permit Congress to legislate bankruptcy proceedings for a political
subdivision of the state would be tantamount, the Court concluded, to
permitting Congress to tax states or their political subdivisions, an activity
that all understood as violating constitutional principles of federalism. Congress responded by essentially reenacting the law that the
Supreme Court had invalidated. The revised statute itself changed little, other
than to exclude counties and to include a legislative history that acknowledged
the “sweeping character” of the holding in Ashton
and effectively rejected it.98 Nevertheless, Congressman Wilcox
went to lengths to indicate the narrow scope of the legislation, its limited
impact on the states, and the voluntary nature of the municipal bankruptcies it
authorized.99
Given the continued requirement that a majority of creditors agree to a
composition in order to obtain relief, Wilcox indicated that the bill constituted
“purely and simply a composition, acceptable to the petitioning district and
the majority creditors, and that no governmental function is involved.”100
Wilcox stressed that “this is not a bill designed to superimpose the will of
Congress onto the will of the municipality or the district.”101
Nor was it a bill “to dictate to a municipality or taxing unit how it should
operate its business.”102 Wilcox
emphasized the composition aspect because, as he read Ashton, the decision was predicated on a mistaken belief that
Congress was “imposing its will on a municipality.”103
The new bill, in Wilcox’s view, made it plain
enough that neither the Court nor the Congress nor anybody has any right or
power to say to any municipality, after it goes into court, “We will order you
to do thus and so”, [sic] or “We are going to change your method of payment, or
your system of taxation,” or anything else.104 Thus, Wilcox
was concerned about meeting the Ashton opinion
on its own terms, not arguing that it was wrong as a constitutional matter. Only two years after the Court decided Ashton,it upheld the
“new” law in United States v. Bekins.105
State consent, which had been deemed insufficient in the 1934 law, formed the
primary basis on which the Supreme Court upheld the revised version of the
legislation.106
Wilcox’s effort at clarification obviously was successful, as the Court
concluded that the new law expressly avoids any restriction on the powers of the
States or their arms of government in the exercise of their sovereign rights
and duties. No interference with the fiscal or governmental affairs of a
political subdivision is permitted. The taxing agency itself is the only
instrumentality which can seek the benefits of the proposed legislation. No
involuntary proceedings are allowable, and no control or jurisdiction over that
property and those revenues of the petitioning agency necessary for essential
governmental purposes is conferred by the bill.107 Virtually all commentators have concluded that the
differences in the two statutes were solely cosmetic, and that
politics—the Supreme Court’s famous “switch-in-time”—rather than
changes in legislative language explains the shift from Ashton to Bekins.108The availability of a federal forum for
debt adjustment to overcome the Contracts Clause obstacle for states was
represented as an example of federal-state cooperation rather than one of
conflict.109
But even Bekins said little about the
constitutional scope of municipal bankruptcy. While the Court emphasized that
the law did not “impinge on the sovereignty of the State” and allowed the state
to maintain control of “its fiscal affairs,” the opinion also stressed that
sovereignty includes the capacity to make contracts in which the states “give
consents upon which the other contracting party may rely with respect to a
particular use of governmental authority.”110 Of course, even more has changed in
the balance struck by principles of federalism since Bekins. While direct taxation of states remains outside the
congressional purview, congressional regulation and taxation of state fiscal
activities have been upheld.111 Though the parameters of congressional
authority to regulate state policies through the Commerce Clause remain murky,112 the more specific nature of the Bankruptcy
Clause has systematically been held to grant Congress substantial authority
over the scope of bankruptcy proceedings, even where the results of those
proceedings affect states or their subdivisions.113 The next major period of municipal bankruptcy reform came
four decades later.114 Whereas the distress that prompted
the original municipal bankruptcy law was nationwide, the 1970s crisis centered
on a single city: New York City. Inefficient and interest-group-dominated
municipal governance was widely recognized as a root cause of New York City’s
financial distress.115 New York City had long lived beyond
its means, in large part to cement political support by traditional politically
influential groups. Fiscal distress increased as the civil-rights movement
empowered new groups to demand a share of municipal resources that they had
previously been denied and to which city officials acceded without reducing
other expenditures. Total city spending rose forty-seven percent in a two-year
period in the mid-1960s, largely as a consequence of previously negotiated
settlements with public labor unions.116
Spending on welfare doubled in the same period, and Medicaid spending
quadrupled.117
While spending stabilized in subsequent years and new revenue
sources—including additional state grants—brought some budgetary
stability, by the end of the decade, recession made spending levels unsustainable.
The city’s response, however, was not to attempt to undo obligations but to
obfuscate their costs, which were “pasted over with new taxes, gimmicks, and
wishful thinking.”118 At bottom,
New York City’s predicament stemmed from a governance structure that tolerated
or encouraged generous expenditures to politically influential groups, fostered
by a politically entrenched budgetary system. The New York City crisis of the
1970s raised the issue of governance reform much more directly than the 1930s
deliberations had. Starting in 1974, state and local officials in New York
actively intervened, ultimately establishing several different oversight boards
and providing $2.3 billion in rescue financing.119 New York Governor Hugh Carey, who
had previously been a congressman for many years, made several trips to
Washington to lobby for federal assistance for New York City.120 President Ford balked, insisting in
remarks at the National Press Club on October 29, 1975 that the real
responsibility for New York City’s crisis lay with the city itself and
grumbling that responsibility was being dumped on the federal government.121
Rather than a federal bailout, Ford concluded, New York City should consider
filing for municipal bankruptcy.122
The New York Daily News summed up his
remarks with the now famous headline: “FORD TO CITY: DROP DEAD.”123 Several weeks before Ford’s remarks, the House Judiciary
Committee held the first of a series of hearings on proposed amendments to the
municipal bankruptcy provisions in the bankruptcy laws. Although a major
bankruptcy reform effort that would culminate in overhaul of the entire
bankruptcy statute in 1978 was well underway, the impetus for the October 1975
hearings was the New York City crisis. A recurring question was whether New
York City could plausibly use the existing municipal bankruptcy laws to
restructure its obligations. Every witness who raised the question agreed that
it would be impossible for New York City to obtain the approval of fifty-one
percent of its creditors in time for a bankruptcy filing, as required by the
then-current municipal bankruptcy provisions.124 Two developments in the hearings are particularly revealing
of the relationship between bankruptcy and municipal governance. First, several
weeks after the initial hearing, the Ford Administration proposed that Congress
enact a new, separate Chapter XVI designed solely for major cities like New York.125 The new chapter, which was
considered in a hearing two days after Ford’s National Press Club remarks,
would have applied only to cities with at least one million residents.126
It also would have eliminated the fifty-one percent creditor-approval prerequisite
for eligibility, while retaining the requirement that the city file a
preliminary restructuring proposal with its bankruptcy petition.127
Finally, the new chapter would have required the municipality to show
explicitly how it would balance its revenues and costs going forward.128 Then-Assistant Attorney General Antonin Scalia, who testified
on behalf of the proposal, emphasized that the new chapter would ensure “more
substantial use of Federal judicial authority in overseeing reestablishment of
the fiscal integrity of the petitioning city.”129
Scalia contended that active judicial intervention was essential for an
effective financial restructuring of a substantial city and that enacting a
separate chapter for big cities would minimize the risk of constitutional
objections. Because the default of a large city “might seriously disrupt
banking, financial and commercial activities nationwide,” Scalia reasoned,
Congress could draw on the Commerce Clause as well as the Bankruptcy Clause for
authority.130 The second relevant feature of the hearings was a repeated
emphasis on the need for municipal bankruptcy to facilitate governance reform.
The most interesting proposal in this regard came from Judge Patchan, a
bankruptcy judge in Cleveland. Patchan’s proposal had two parts. The first was
greater flexibility for courts to shape the restructuring process. “With due
regard for state sovereignty,” he said, “the federal courts should be granted a
more active role within the design of the municipal bankruptcy chapter of the
Act presently contemplated by Congress.”131 Patchan maintained that “where the
debtor alone cannot design a workable plan or where functional restructuring is
needed, the court should serve as a catalyst to bring necessary parties
together to produce such a plan.”132
He advocated that the court be given continuing jurisdiction to ensure that the
municipality carried out its restructuring plan.133 Patchan’s second proposal sought to facilitate governance
reform that a municipal debtor might not be able to carry out on its own. “I
would suggest,” Patchan told the lawmakers, “that consideration be given to a
means by which State officials, or local officials outside the debtors’
administration, can be brought into the formulation of a plan and given
standing in court. In that way the city may gain necessary State house support
for possible restructuring of local government functions.”134
Patchan proposed that the bankruptcy judge be authorized to form a committee of
relevant officials and to give the committee the power to propose a
restructuring plan.135 Another witness, representing the then-new municipal bond
insurance business, offered a less fully developed proposal for governance
reform. Referring explicitly to the New York City crisis, he argued that the
“bankruptcy judge should have the benefit of the expertise of an advisory board
similar to the ‘Big Mac’ board to assist him in evaluating the likelihood of
success of a [restructuring] plan.”136 Neither lawmakers nor the witnesses in the hearings seemed to
doubt that Congress had the authority to include provisions like these in its
municipal bankruptcy amendments. Then-Assistant Attorney General Scalia, who
extolled the proposed Chapter XVI as assuring federal judicial oversight, as
noted earlier, was confident that the new chapter would be constitutionally
sound.137
Harvard Law professor Vern Countryman, who dismissed the proposed Chapter XVI
as pointless “shadow-boxing” between President Ford and New York officials, was
especially insistent that any state sovereignty concerns were overstated.138 But the focus quickly shifted away from New York and its
governance issues. The New York City crisis was moving too fast to be resolved
by a hastily drafted new bankruptcy chapter, and it was far from clear that the
proposed Chapter XVI would have been adequate in any event. Persuaded that the
enactment of a moratorium law by the state of New York reflected an
acknowledgment by New York City that it was in default, President Ford
announced his support for more than two billion dollars in federal loan
guarantees for New York several weeks later.139
Congress enacted the necessary legislation shortly thereafter, and the
President signed it on December 15, 1975.140 With New York’s immediate cash crunch
averted, lawmakers scrapped the proposal for a new Chapter XVI and set aside
the more ambitious governance-oriented proposals. Congress did, however, enact
the most extensive reforms to the existing municipal bankruptcy laws since the
1930s. The signature change was the removal of the requirement that a
municipality secure the approval of fifty-one percent of its creditors to an
initial restructuring proposal before filing.141 Congress made a number of other important
changes as well, one of which explicitly authorized municipal debtors to assume
or reject collective bargaining agreements and other executory contracts.142 In one sense, the historical evidence described in Section
II.B and Section II.C only deepens the mystery we are trying to solve: if
lawmakers understood the importance of governance reform, and assumed that
municipal bankruptcy could be used for this purpose, why do we see so little of
it in actual Chapter 9 cases? Lingering concerns about constitutionality no
doubt played some role, but we think the heart of the explanation lies
elsewhere. The first thing to note is that significant obstacles
remained, even after 1976, for a municipality that wished to file for Chapter
9. Federal bankruptcy courts were available only to those municipalities whose
states authorized a Chapter 9 petition, and even today, only half the states
have granted the requisite permission.143 Although they no longer were
required to secure fifty-one percent approval before filing for bankruptcy,
municipal debtors still had to demonstrate, among other things, that they were
insolvent, which is uniquely defined for Chapter 9 purposes to mean failure to
pay debts as they become due or inability to pay debts as they become due.144
Since municipalities have access to tax revenues, the insolvency requirement
can be very difficult to meet, even for a municipality in dire financial
straits. For example, Bridgeport, Connecticut’s effort to adjust debts in
bankruptcy during a period of extreme fiscal distress foundered on the court’s
determination that the city was not insolvent because it was still capable of
borrowing and had not yet run out of cash.145
The stigma of a bankruptcy filing also has a chilling effect, especially for
large and complex municipalities. No mayor wants to be the one who has put his
or her city in bankruptcy. Due to these obstacles, together with states’ ability to
intervene in a variety of ways, there has long been a striking (and oft-noted)
selection bias in actual municipal bankruptcy cases. Until recently,
financially distressed sewer and water districts filed for Chapter 9, but
substantial cities simply did not.146
Of the 650 or so municipalities that filed for bankruptcy between 1997 and
2009, the vast majority have been special districts, such as irrigation
districts that failed to attract expected development or small towns crippled
by a lawsuit or unexpected catastrophe.147
Thus, financial infeasibility, rather than dysfunctional governance, motivated
these bankruptcy petitions. Until the recent spate of municipal bankruptcies,
the only large jurisdiction other than Bridgeport that had sought the
protection of Chapter 9 was Orange County, California, which suffered from its treasurer’s
losing bets on derivatives contracts.148 Much more than constitutional concerns, this selection bias
explains why governance has figured more prominently in legislative debates
than in actual cases. To return to our Chapter 11 analogy, the parallel
situation would arise in the corporate context if the only firms that filed for
Chapter 11 were small restaurants and other closely held corporations, not
large businesses like Chrysler or United Airlines. When a closely held
corporation files for Chapter 11, it ordinarily is either reorganized with its
existing owners intact, or liquidated.149
Governance reform plays little or no role. It is only with more complex
businesses that we see the carefully calibrated governance reforms described in
Part I. The same logic applies in Chapter 9. Because the
municipalities that filed for bankruptcy before 2008 tended to be special
districts, it is hardly surprising that we do not find efforts to use Chapter 9
to effect governance reform. While filings by substantial municipalities still
make up a small fraction of Chapter 9 petitions,150 the frequency of filings by such
entities has increased.151 Because the
financial distress of many municipalities stems in large part from obligations
such as pensions that cannot easily be restructured outside of bankruptcy,
additional filings can reasonably be anticipated.152 We draw two conclusions, one descriptive and one normative,
from Chapter 9’s new prominence as a restructuring option for substantial
cities. First, we predict that, as more cities make use of Chapter 9, there
will be increased pressure to include substantial governance reform as part of
the reorganization process. Second, we believe that governance reform should be—indeed,
must be—incorporated into Chapter 9. We take up the latter point in Part
III. As discussed in Part II, problems
with the city’s governance are nearly always a major factor when a substantial
city falls into financial distress. In this Part, we take a closer look at some
of the governance tendencies that can exacerbate a city’s financial
difficulties and stymie efforts to reverse a downward spiral. Not only can
Chapter 9 governance reform counteract these tendencies, but a restructuring
plan that does not address the governance dysfunction may be destined to fail.
Indeed, to put the point more strongly, if a city’s governance dysfunctions are
severe, a bankruptcy judge should not confirm a restructuring plan that leaves
the governance crisis unaddressed. The most common governance problem—our principal focus
in the discussion that follows—is a fragmented local decision-making
structure.153 One of us has recently considered
the fragmentation issue in a related context.154 We therefore only summarize the
issue here. We begin by briefly describing four general patterns of municipal
governance fragmentation, then consider how a bankruptcy court could counteract
the fragmentation. In a fragmented budgetary system, fiscal policy is
decentralized in a manner that allows decision makers to determine expenditures
without simultaneously internalizing their costs.155
As a result, the municipal budget takes on the characteristics of a common pool
from which various actors can obtain benefits, while sharing the costs with
other participants. Because those who utilize the common resource fail to
internalize the full costs of their activity, there is a tendency for overuse.156 In the municipal context, the
misalignment between costs and benefits through fragmentation could arise from
any of numerous sources. First, different branches of the municipal bureaucracy could
have authority over spending and be inattentive to the manner in which their
spending decisions affect the overall budget. The mayor, for instance, may wish
to concentrate spending on a small number of projects each of which, as a
consequence of scale, has a high expected value for the municipality. City-council
members may prefer to spend the same amount of money on numerous small
projects, each of which has a positive, but relatively low expected value
within a member’s district, and the aggregate of which does not equal the
expected value of the smaller number of large projects favored by the mayor.
Departments within the municipality may have interests in maximizing their
share of the municipal budget rather than providing efficient service. If their
costs are opaque to legislators, bureaus may obtain a level of funding in
excess of that preferred by the median legislator or the median voter.157 Second, different individuals within a governmental branch could have authority over spending and
engage in negative-sum logrolling to support each other’s favored projects,
notwithstanding that those projects do not return net local fiscal benefits.
Trades among city-council members in order to favor projects for the districts
from which they are elected may take this form. The desire of city-council
members to appeal to constituents within their respective districts and the
subsequent tendency for logrolling suggests that city expenditures per capita
will increase with the number of districts. Barry Weingast, Kenneth Shepsle,
and Christopher Johnsen formalized this effect with the law of 1/n, which assumes that a citywide tax is
used to finance a project in a specific district.158
As the share of the project’s cost in the district decreases, the law of 1/n predicts that the number and cost of
projects will increase.159 Subsequent
empirical work by Reza Baqir;160 Laura Langbein, Philip Crewson, and
Charles Brasher;161 and John Charles Bradbury and E.
Frank Stephenson162 supported
the existence of a positive relationship between council size and expenditures.
More recently, however, Lynn MacDonald has attempted to control for the
possibility that the relationship between council size and spending is
endogenous, and has concluded that the relationship is “not definitively
positive.”163 Of course, even empirical work that
does not support the law of 1/n does
not necessarily indicate the absence of adverse effects from decentralized
districts. Within a fixed budget, if expenditures are used for projects that do
not have positive citywide effects, fiscal stability could suffer. New York
City’s fiscal crisis, for example, was not simply a function of high
expenditures, but also of the use of expenditures for groups that had
substantial political power and did not necessarily represent the interests of
the city at large.164 In addition,
the empirical work also does not distinguish between healthy and distressed
localities; it is plausible that the effects of the law of 1/n are more pronounced in distressed
cities than in the average city within the studies. Third, bureaucrats with expenditure authority who do not
coordinate may make budgetary decisions that either duplicate efforts or
conflict with each other. If both the city council and the mayor’s office form
subdivisions for tasks such as city planning or environmental review, the different
constituencies of those offices could generate more redundancy and conflict
than collaboration. The consequences for the fiscal condition of municipalities
have been captured in accounts of cities such as New York and Chicago.165 Fragmentation in budget making and
expenditures in those cities tends to generate redistribution of wealth to
groups that are able to influence the entity with expenditure authority, and
the plethora of such authorities leads to increases in the size of government.166
Even after its bankruptcy, Detroit’s governance appears to
reflect the third type of fragmentation, burdening the city’s decision making
with costly redundancies. Although the causes of Detroit’s decline over the
second half of the twentieth century are multifaceted, fragmented governance
and reduced budgetary flexibility may have diluted the city’s capacity to
adjust to the decline of the auto industry, white flight, and other challenges.167
For example, Detroit’s separate planning departments report separately to the
mayor’s office and to the city council. This arrangement invites review of
plans both by the mayor, who is responsible to the city as a whole, and by
individual city-council members, who consider the interests of particular
electoral districts. Similarly, while Detroit’s City Charter provides for an
office of corporation counsel, the charter also authorizes the city to obtain
the opinion or advice of an attorney in any matter pending before it, and to
retain an attorney to represent the council in a matter where there exists a
conflict of interest with another branch of government.168
Although the charter seems to envision that additional legal assistance will be
obtained only in special circumstances, the city council created a permanent
legal division that frequently conflicts with the Office of Corporation Counsel.169 The process for selecting Detroit’s police chief reflects a
fourth form of fragmentation in that it decentralizes appointive authority over
city officials, with equally dire implications for Detroit’s financial health.
The empirical literature on business mobility reveals that crime rates figure
prominently in firms’ decisions to move or expand their business, though they lag
behind cost factors in significance.170
This evidence suggests that low crime rates contribute to municipal fiscal
health.171
Courts are well aware of the link between effective policing and municipal
financial health. In both the Detroit and Stockton bankruptcy cases, for
instance, the bankruptcy judge pointed to cutbacks of police services as
evidence of municipal crisis.172 Thus, one
might conclude that the selection of the person charged with choosing among
plausible policing strategies (e.g., aggressive quality-of-life enforcement,
community policing, or increasing police presence) could significantly affect a
municipality’s fiscal stability. Perhaps for this reason, city charters in
major cities tend to confer on the mayor the exclusive authority to appoint or
to nominate the chief of police.173
Detroit’s City Charter, by contrast, substantially constrains the selection of
that official. Detroit’s charter provides for a Board of Police Commissioners
consisting of eleven members, seven of whom are elected from the City’s council
districts.174
The Board’s responsibilities include establishing policies, rules, and
regulations for the police department and approving the departmental budget.175
Perhaps most importantly, the Board identifies candidates for the city’s chief
of police, and the mayor may only select the chief from the list that the board
submits.176
Even in the abstract, this arrangement suggests that the
mayor has limited control over the selection of policing strategies. In
practice, the fragmentation is even more severe, because the Board has
traditionally been heavily populated by commissioners who are themselves former
police officers.177 While the
experience that they bring to the office may sometimes ensure greater
understanding of the competing policies, there is also some risk that
commissioners whose background involves policing will identify with the
preferences of police officers rather than with the policies that would best serve
the municipality. It is unlikely that internal politics would generate reform
of any of these structural inducements to fiscal excess. Bureaus that benefit
from serving client groups can be expected to resist centralization of budgets
that would limit their discretion or their funding.178
City-council members will rarely abandon practices that allow them to provide
services to constituents who maximize electoral chances or post-public service
opportunities. Mayors are not inclined to welcome oversight of their decisions.
For example, even when the New York City Charter was amended after the fiscal
crisis of the 1970s to create the Independent Budget Office (IBO), successive
mayors sought to defund it179 and provided funding only after
losing court battles over withheld funding.180 Entrenched political authority that
favors fragmented decision making means that any reforms would have to emerge
from some third party that has the authority to restructure governing
institutions. Under the approach we advocate, a bankruptcy judge could play
this role when the consequences of fragmentation have become sufficiently
severe that a municipality files for bankruptcy. A bankruptcy judge who
construed Chapter 9 as including governance reform could induce revision of the
city charter in a manner that defragmented municipal decision making by, for
example, placing appointive power over the police department exclusively within
the mayor’s jurisdiction. Alternatively, assume fiscal distress has been generated by
negative-sum logrolling among city-council members, each of whom has secured
funding for projects within his or her district at the expense of overall local
welfare. At least three changes in institutional design could reduce the
problem. First, the city council could be elected on an at-large basis rather
than by district. Second, the number of city-council members could be reduced.
Third, the mayor could be given a strong veto power that would permit her to
deny funding to a project that appeared inconsistent with municipal welfare.
Entrenchment could frustrate intramural efforts to enact any of these (or other
meaningful) antilogrolling reforms. Again, a bankruptcy judge could spur
redesign of municipal governance by encouraging one of these (or some other)
reforms.181 More radically, a court could encourage a more thorough
alteration of the existing form of government. Cities in the United States
typically take either a council-manager form of government or a mayor-council
form of government.182 The former
involves an elected council that hires a professional city manager. The city
may have a mayor, but the council retains authority over policy and budget.183 In the mayor-council form of
government, both the mayor and council are elected. The mayor serves as chief
executive and may have substantial administrative, budgetary, and appointive
authority, as well as veto power over legislative enactments.184
The literature concerning the comparative fiscal performance
of these forms of government is equivocal. It is not clear whether different
methodologies, the different time periods in the studies, or some other
variable explains these differences. There is theoretical support for each of
the findings.185
Stephen Coate and Brian Knight find that mayor-council forms of government have
approximately nine percent lower per capita spending, and that spending falls
following switches from council manager to mayor council and rises following
switches in the other direction.186 Lynn MacDonald concluded from a twenty-year
study of political structure and fiscal-policy outcomes that council-manager
cities had lower spending in the 1980s, but the effect disappeared in later
years.187
Earlier studies ran the gamut from showing higher spending under mayor-council
forms of government,188 to lower spending
under that structure,189 to the
absence of any effect.190 Mayors who are elected citywide and have veto power may
resist expenditures that only benefit a specific district. Managers may better
control spending because they are not subject to political pressures from
interest groups. But managers may spend as much as or more than mayors because
managers are accountable to council members who may be subject to pressures
from those same groups.191 The variations in these studies,
however, should not preclude judicial consideration of a switch in government
in a particular bankruptcy case. The studies consider cities generally, and it
remains plausible that more systematic differences between forms of government
exist for cities that are fiscally distressed. Given the theoretical
explanations for why one form of government may be more fiscally stable than
another, a court that concluded that the variables that generate high
expenditures were present in a distressed city with one form of government
could reasonably contemplate inducing a switch to the alternative. For example,
a court that concluded that a manager exercised little discretion over
implementation of council policies, and that those policies reflected
disproportionate expenditures to groups that provided electoral support to
legislators, might exert pressure for adoption of a strong mayor-council
structure that permitted centralized budgeting and executive vetoes.192 In other contexts, a bankruptcy court might be convinced that
the locality has too few, rather than too many, mechanisms for constraining
fiscal profligacy. A bankruptcy judge could condition plan confirmation on the
appointment of a financial control board that provided expertise in reviewing
(and perhaps approving) city budgets and that increased the transparency of the
budgetary process. Puerto Rico’s recent proposal for restructuring the debt of
the commonwealth and some of its public corporations included creation of a
control board that would oversee the budgetary process and be authorized to
levy sanctions for noncompliance with approved budgets.193 As we have noted, New York City
revised its City Charter to create the IBO.194
That nonpartisan agency issues a forecast of revenue and spending for the
coming year, performs a comprehensive review of the mayor’s preliminary budget,
and creates an analysis of the executive budget that focuses on changes from
the preliminary budget. The IBO also issues detailed fiscal briefs on critical
issues facing the city, prepares technical background papers, and outlines
annual budget options for increasing revenue and saving costs.195
The objectivity of the Office is enhanced by a complicated process for
appointment of a director that inhibits capture by any particular group within
the city.196
In addition, the independence and professionalism of the IBO are secured by a
requirement that it receive funding in proportion to the budget office of the mayor.197
While the success of the New York City IBO may be a function of its capacity to
draw from a substantial talent pool of individuals with expertise in public
finance, a bankruptcy judge plausibly could conclude that another municipality
had sufficient access to human capital to make a similar body an effective
agent for analyzing and publicizing budgetary issues as a municipality seeks to
escape fiscal distress postbankruptcy. To the extent that municipal distress is attributable to a
temporal misalignment of costs and benefits of municipal expenditures, a
bankruptcy court could demand structural reforms of institutions that
exacerbate the externalization of costs to future residents. For example,
several commentators have suggested that municipal difficulties arise from the
use of defined benefit pension plans, rather than defined contribution plans,
for municipal employees.198 If elected
officials can obtain electoral support by offering substantial pension benefits
to public-sector unions, while deferring the related costs to a later time,
they may resist reform.199 A bankruptcy
court that concluded that these incentives substantially contributed to the
fiscal distress of an insolvent municipality might condition confirmation on
the adoption of a local ordinance to require that future contracts with public
sector unions permit only defined contribution plans. The State of Michigan
imposed a similar requirement on the City of Detroit when it agreed to provide
state funding in return for the creation of a state advisory board prior to the
City’s filing for bankruptcy.200 One term of
that agreement was that any future collective-bargaining agreement would
provide that newly hired employees of the city would have “a defined
contribution retirement health care benefit.”201 Although the bankruptcy court has less authority over a
city’s relationship with the surrounding communities, a judge also could spur
regional reform in some contexts, such as sewer and water services that
encompass the city and nearby counties.202
A regional water arrangement was one of the few structural governance reforms
that was in fact achieved in the Detroit bankruptcy case.203 Finally, one could also imagine a
bankruptcy court encouraging more creative reform. For example, some
municipalities have permitted groups within the locality to form business
improvement districts (BIDs) or neighborhood improvement districts that allow
firms or neighbors to fund a higher level of public services than the
municipality provides generally and to impose assessments on recalcitrant
members if a majority or supermajority approves.204 These districts are controversial,205 but there is at least some evidence that
they reduce crime206 and, at least for well-funded BIDs,
increase commercial property values.207 They plausibly discourage exit, because
they ensure that members can use fees for services from which they benefit
directly in the same way that they would if they emigrated to less
redistributive suburbs. A bankruptcy court might conclude that such efforts are
worth undertaking in an effort to revitalize a city and, where that is the
case, could expect the municipality to enact the legislation necessary to
establish the districts. In this Section, we propose that the current Bankruptcy Code,
and in particular, the requirement that a plan of adjustment be “feasible,”208
provides the doctrinal basis for a bankruptcy court serving as a catalyst for
governance reform. Before explaining that issue more fully, we note that
bankruptcy filings may alter political dynamics that frustrate reform, even
without judicial prodding for specific organizational structures. First, although a city’s leadership may be reluctant to
endorse reform under ordinary conditions, given the political costs of
challenging beneficiaries of the existing system, fiscal distress that is
severe enough to require a bankruptcy filing is likely to diminish the leverage
of proponents of the status quo; and a mayor who files for bankruptcy may feel
that there is little more to lose, given the political costs she will already
have incurred by declaring the need for bankruptcy. If the state has special
provisions for distressed cities and local officials have been replaced by an
emergency manager, as in Detroit,209
the willingness to pursue structural reform may be even greater. Bankruptcy may
thus create political opportunities that did not previously exist. Indeed, one
benefit of permitting structural reform in bankruptcy may be that the existence
of the option makes its exercise unnecessary since the locality may prefer to
restructure on its own rather than risk external imposition.210
Second, and relatedly, bankruptcy can centralize
decision-making authority and diffuse opposition. Outside of bankruptcy, a
proposal to change governance arrangements would need to be vetted with the
city’s voters and with the officials that would be affected, even if neither
had formal veto power over reform. From their perspective, reform may have
significant downsides and little immediate upside. In bankruptcy, the reforms
can be included as part of a single package that also includes a substantial
reduction of the city’s debt load. For voters especially, reform may be more
palatable as part of the combined proposal. Overall, incorporation of
governance into municipal bankruptcy would considerably strengthen the hand of
city leaders who wish to effect reform (and weaken the hand of leaders who are
themselves an impediment to reform), since city leaders could rightly say that
they have no choice but to include governance reform in their restructuring
proposal.211 Suppose, however, that the municipal decisionmakers are
reluctant to pursue reform, even after the municipality has filed for
bankruptcy. How can the bankruptcy court intervene? Chapter 9 makes clear that
the debtor alone has authority to file a plan of adjustment.212
Thus, under current law, the bankruptcy court would not be entitled to dictate
the terms of structural reform. Nevertheless, the bankruptcy court is permitted
to confirm the plan only if it satisfies certain criteria, and courts can use
those criteria to induce—or effectively compel—debtors to propose
desirable reforms.213 Some legislative history suggests
that plan-confirmation standards would incorporate the principles of cases in
which courts considered whether the debtor was making full use of its taxing
powers.214
While isolated statements in the legislative history of what is now Chapter 9
are not by themselves strong evidence that courts can mandate municipal tax
increases,215 both the logic and language of
Chapter 9 suggest that a bankruptcy judge can reject a plan that fails to
address obvious governance dysfunction. McConnell and Picker concluded that the requirement that a
plan be “in the ‘best interests of the creditors’” provides the most obvious
basis for judicial leverage but were skeptical that the clause was intended to
give the court broad discretion to second-guess the city’s financial
arrangements.216 We focus instead on the requirement
that a proposed restructuring plan cannot be approved unless it is “feasible.”217 If fragmented governance has
contributed to fiscal irresponsibility in the first instance, then a bankruptcy
judge cannot properly conclude that the debtor’s restructuring plan is feasible
if it leaves in place a political structure that threatens to return the
municipality to insolvency. Even if the municipality adjusts its balance sheet
dramatically, dysfunctional governance will encourage a prompt return to fiscal
profligacy. Indeed, this very risk became an issue in the Detroit bankruptcy
proceedings. The bankruptcy judge appointed an independent expert to assess the
feasibility of Detroit’s restructuring proposal. The expert defined feasibility
in terms of the following question: Is it likely that the City of Detroit, after the
confirmation of the Plan of Adjustment, will be able to sustainably provide
basic municipal services to the citizens of Detroit and to meet the obligations
contemplated in the Plan without the significant probability of a default?218 Although the feasibility expert concluded that
Detroit’s plan met this standard, she raised concerns about Detroit’s failures
to incorporate governance reform into the restructuring. “This bankruptcy has
been largely focused on deleveraging the City,” she noted, “often to the
exclusion of fixing the City’s broken operations.”219
As a result, she concluded, “[T]he operational restructuring that often occurs
with commercial reorganizations will be left largely to Mayor Duggan and his
managers for the post confirmation period.”220
Implicit in that statement was a view that, absent additional governance reform,
there remained serious questions about the feasibility of Detroit’s
restructuring. A perceived lack of authority to address those issues, rather
than their irrelevance, perhaps explains why the independent expert and
ultimately the bankruptcy judge deferred to local officials to redress some of
the core causes of Detroit’s distress. At first glance, there may seem to be a temporal mismatch
between the feasibility requirement and concerns about the consequences of poor
governance. “Feasibility,” on this understanding, would be concerned only with
short-term financial viability; while the effects of poor governance are likely
to fester over multiple years of deficits, mismanagement, and inappropriate
expenditures before crisis reemerges.221
Thus, governance reforms that are intended to forestall long-term distress
might seem to be a poor fit for a test that focuses on the near future. Indeed,
even the parties themselves may not seem to have incentives to respond to
judicial recommendations of long-term governance restructuring because they
receive no benefit from the effort.222 But feasibility for a municipality inherently requires
attention to long-term financial solvency. The need to consider the long term
is most obvious where restructuring existing obligations entails deferring
payments rather than simply eliminating them. New York State’s efforts to
restructure New York City debt, for example, included an exchange of short-term
notes for bonds with a maturity of up to twenty years.223
Detroit issued $1.28 billion of new bonds, with maturities ranging from eight
to thirty years, as part of its plan of adjustment.224
Confirmation of a plan that restructures existing debt or requires the issuance
of new long-term debt implies that the debtor will be able to make debt service
payments when due. A plan cannot be considered genuinely feasible if it extends
maturities but does nothing to increase the probability that payments will be
forthcoming at the new maturity date. Creditors who accept extended maturities
will expect the municipality to take measures to avoid the need for additional
adjustment during the period when their bonds are outstanding. The same is true
of other stakeholders, such as pensioners, whose obligations may have been
adjusted in bankruptcy, but who remain entitled to postbankruptcy payments into
the long-term future for services already rendered.225
Given their long-term stake, creditors who are the beneficiaries of
restructured obligations have good reason to respond to judicial suggestions or
even to offer recommendations for restructuring without judicial prompting once
it becomes apparent that there is legal authority for incorporating such
measures into a plan. Once we recognize that municipal bankruptcy is not solely
intended to restructure debt but to permit revival of municipal services,226
the case for a long-term view of feasibility becomes even stronger. As the
court in the Detroit bankruptcy noted, “feasibility” in the municipal context
includes not simply avoiding default but also the ability “to sustainably
provide basic municipal services to the citizens of Detroit . . . .”227
Just as degradation of services from poor governance is likely to occur slowly,
emergence from service-delivery insolvency also takes time. Reestablishing a
tax base after a long period of depopulation, rebuilding dilapidated
infrastructure, and scaling up a municipal workforce that may have been
decimated during a period of fiscal distress require long-term arrangements.228 As in
the case of extended-debt obligations, if feasibility involves obligations that
can only be satisfied in the long term, it is appropriate to include within the
remedial scheme measures that themselves will return benefits on a similarly
extended time horizon. While we recognize that our proposal varies significantly
from the common understanding of the pure debt adjustment function of Chapter 9
and could conflict with a broad interpretation of § 904’s prohibition of
nonconsensual judicial interference with any of the debtor’s political or governmental
powers, our proposal is less radical than it initially appears. First, as we
have noted, it is commonly recognized that bankruptcy courts have the capacity
to do indirectly what they cannot do directly by refusing to confirm plans that
do not include details such as tax increases that the municipality might
otherwise reject.229 Second, as discussed more fully in Part IV, the structural
interventions that we propose reflect a difficult but manageable balance
between state and federal law.230 Chapter 9 itself
imposes a limitation on the ability of federal bankruptcy law to trump state
law. Section 943(b)(4) allows confirmation of a plan only if, among other
things, “the debtor is not prohibited by law from taking any action necessary
to carry out the plan.”231 Thus, without amendment of that
provision, a court could not, for example, require a municipality to adopt an
at-large election system for the local legislature if state statutes require
such elections to occur by districts. But assume that the locality’s decision to use district
elections were embodied in the city charter rather than in a state statute.
Would § 943(b)(4) also prevent judicial modification of that document as a
condition of plan confirmation? Here, a municipal debtor appears to have more
flexibility, especially if the restructuring plan requires that governance
reforms will only be implemented if the city charter is amended through the
ordinary charter amendment process.232
Of course, that course of action, which may include a voter referendum,233
provides opportunities for those who benefit from the status quo to oppose
reforms. But they may have difficulty doing so without revealing their
self-interested positions and without at least providing opportunities for
proponents of reform to explain why proposed amendments were included in the
Chapter 9 plan. Third, structural requirements imposed by the bankruptcy
court need not be permanent. That is because municipal governance structures,
at least for home-rule municipalities, tend to be imposed through the same city
charters that may have to be amended in order to implement proposed reforms.
While charters essentially form the constitution for the municipality, they are
typically subject to amendment far more readily than are constitutions of more
centralized governments. Thus, what is accomplished through the bankruptcy
process can be undone if opponents of reform are able to gather sufficient
support for the pre-bankruptcy regime. To be sure, as we have just noted, state
law frequently requires substantial effort, including voter approval, in order
to amend a city charter.234 Some
charters also contain temporal limitations on amendment or revision.235
The result is that structural reforms imposed by the bankruptcy court could not
be undone without difficulty but would also be subject to their own reform
should they prove to be less desirable than anticipated. They would however be
subject to amendment and revision just as any other matter addressed within the
city charter.236 We have outlined what we think is a compelling case that
governance reform needs to be added to the Chapter 9 menu, and indeed, that a
substantial municipality often will not be able to propose a feasible
reorganization plan in the absence of governance reform. In this Part, we
address potential objections to such a major shift from the conventional
understanding of municipal bankruptcy. We focus first in this Part on the
structure of Chapter 9 itself. Several key provisions in Chapter 9 seem to
limit its scope to financial restructuring. We take up each of these
provisions, concluding that they reflect the conventional wisdom but do not
preclude governance reform. We also address a weighty constitutional objection
to our proposal: the argument that governance reform would violate the
unconstitutional conditions doctrine, even if Chapter 9 purported to allow it.
The final two Sections consider two important practical objections: (1) the
question whether bankruptcy judges are competent to induce or oversee governance
reform; and (2) the possibility that the prospect of governance reform will
discourage Chapter 9 filings. When the original municipal bankruptcy laws were challenged
in the 1930s, much of the discussion centered on claims of impermissible
interference with the prerogatives of the states as protected by the Tenth
Amendment.237
(The other principal concern, the constitutional prohibition against impairment
of contracts, is implicated by a city’s restructuring of its debt but not by
the governance reforms we advocate here.) Three different provisions of Chapter
9 are designed to assuage these concerns.238
The first prohibits a municipality from filing for bankruptcy unless its state
explicitly authorizes it or municipalities like it to do so.239
The second prohibits the use of Chapter 9 to limit or impair a state’s control
over its municipalities.240 And the
third prohibits the bankruptcy court from interfering with a municipality’s
political or governmental powers, property or revenues, or use of income
producing property “unless the debtor consents or the plan so provides.”241
Our proposal implicates only the third of these protections. On first glance, the restriction on bankruptcy court
authority over the municipality’s political or governmental powers seems to
preclude precisely the kinds of reforms we have advocated. But there are
several responses to that criticism. First, as Steven Walt and Richard Hynes
have demonstrated, the constraint that § 904 imposes is less absolute than it
initially appears.242 For example, notwithstanding § 904,
the court is still entitled “to appoint a trustee to exercise . . . avoidance
powers if the municipality refuses to do so”243
and to determine whether the debtor is permitted to secure “post-petition
financing with collateral,”244 each of
which interferes with the debtor’s property and powers. Although those
exceptions exist pursuant to explicitly delineated authority in the Bankruptcy
Code, they at least dilute any claim that the constitutional principles
embodied in § 904 mandate a strict separation of bankruptcy powers and state
sovereignty. Second, and much more importantly, the noninterference
provision includes a large escape hatch that could make major governance
reforms possible in many cases. If the “debtor consents” to the interference or
if “the plan so provides,” the prohibition does not apply.245 The first term—debtor
consent—seems to contemplate consent by the debtor at any point in the
bankruptcy case. For example, shortly after Detroit filed for bankruptcy, the
bankruptcy court appointed a fee examiner to oversee Detroit’s bankruptcy
lawyers’ fees. Detroit consented to this oversight that might otherwise have
been deemed to interfere with Detroit’s political or governmental powers.246
Because only the debtor itself can propose a restructuring plan,247 the debtor’s consent also is a
prerequisite to the use of the plan to effect changes that might otherwise be
viewed as interference with political or municipal powers. The escape hatch
thus gives the bankruptcy court the power to implement governance reforms so
long as the debtor agrees to the changes. In the bankruptcy context, debtor consent has multiple
features. We first address the question of who among various elected officials
has the authority to speak on behalf of the debtor. We then turn to the
possibility that broader popular consent would be required to enact particular
reforms. The issue of which elected officials speak for the debtor may seem
superfluous. If elected officials have resisted efforts to restructure their
government prior to bankruptcy, it is unlikely that they would consent to a
procedure that allowed the bankruptcy court to motivate the same results that
those officials have eschewed. Nevertheless, there may be circumstances in
which the resistance of local officials matters less. Where, prior to
bankruptcy, governance of the municipality has been turned over to a
state-appointed financial control board, entrenchment will serve as less of a
constraint. For instance, under Michigan law, Detroit’s emergency manager had
sweeping, unilateral authority that displaced both the mayor and city council.248
As a result, neither fractured authority nor entrenchment was a concern in
Detroit’s bankruptcy. Similarly, under New York law, an emergency control board
that has been appointed to oversee a municipality can file a petition under
Chapter 9.249 One could also imagine that a mayor who both had unequivocal
authority to give the requisite consent under § 904 and believed that
bankruptcy courts would use that provision to strengthen mayoral authority
would consent to judicial intervention. But if a municipal debtor has both a
mayor and a city council, the question of which one can provide the necessary
“consent” for purposes of § 904 may depend on state law that dictates the
division of local powers between local executives and legislatures. To answer
the related question of whether the proper city officials had filed a
bankruptcy petition in the case involving Harrisburg, Pennsylvania, for
example, the court relied on state law and the local city charter to conclude
that only the mayor had authority to file the petition.250 Consent is less likely to be
forthcoming where the proposed “interference” affects the incumbents themselves
in ways that they perceive as threatening their authority. As we have suggested above, where structural reforms affect
city charter provisions, the issue of consent becomes more complicated, not
necessarily because of entrenchment but because consent under state law could
be interpreted to require the same charter commission and electoral process
that is necessary to amend or revise a charter outside of bankruptcy. Indeed,
even if the official who speaks for the municipality in bankruptcy agreed to
include charter reform in the plan, it is not clear that such consent would
bind the municipality, since that official would have had no authority to
restructure the municipality’s governance structure outside of bankruptcy. One plausible technical solution to the obstacle of popular
consent may exist in current law. Among the provisions of Chapter 11
incorporated into Chapter 9 is § 1123(a)(5).251
That provision authorizes the debtor to make charter amendments in its
reorganization plan, subject only to bankruptcy’s plan confirmation process.
One could, therefore, interpret the reference to “charter” to apply to
municipal as well as corporate organic documents and allow bankruptcy law to
circumvent state law restrictions on charter revision. We recognize, however,
that this interpretation is aggressive (and perhaps normatively objectionable).
Chapter 9 also contains a democracy-preserving provision that allows a plan to
be confirmed only if “regulatory or electoral approval necessary under
applicable nonbankruptcy law in order to carry out any provision of the plan
has been obtained, or such a provision is expressly conditioned on such
approval . . . .”252
Presumably that provision requires that any restructuring proposal in a reorganization
plan must be approved through a local referendum when the same proposal would
have required a referendum outside the bankruptcy context. Alternatively, the
potential for impasse may suggest the need for more explicit avenues for
reform. These could include express amendment of Chapter 9 to trump city
charter amendment provisions, or, perhaps more palatably, to require submission
of governance reform proposals to the normal charter revision process. Perhaps the more important constraint on § 904 is the
capacity of the bankruptcy judge to withhold confirmation of a plan that fails
to incorporate certain measures that the court deems necessary for fiscal
success. As we have already noted, the authority to withhold confirmation
permits a bankruptcy court to do indirectly what § 904 prohibits being done
directly.253
A court required to consider the feasibility of a plan and the best interests
of creditors prior to confirmation254
could conclude that continuing the existing municipal governance structure
substantially increased the probability of recidivism or impeded the delivery
of services. The court could therefore deny confirmation of a plan that failed
to restructure. This veto power increases the likelihood that each of the
relevant decision makers will consent to needed reforms. The second statute-based objection to governance reform is
semantic but equally serious. Unlike Chapter 11, which explicitly contemplates
governance reform, one might contend that Chapter 9 only provides for financial
restructuring. Whereas Chapter 11’s title is “Reorganization,” Chapter 9 is
called “Adjustment of Debts of a Municipality.” Similarly, Chapter 11 says
simply that the debtor may file a “plan,”255
whereas Chapter 9 states that “[t]he debtor shall file a plan for the
adjustment of the debtor’s debts.”256
This language seems to envision that a Chapter 9 debtor will restructure only
its balance sheet, not its governance. Although balance sheet restructuring has traditionally been
Chapter 9’s focus, which is reflected in the references to “adjustment of
debts,” these labels do not preclude governance reform. The first thing to note
is that the “adjustment of debts” language is a legacy of the concerns that
shaped the original municipal bankruptcy laws. As discussed earlier,257
the drafters’ principal concern in the 1930s was enabling stressed
municipalities to restructure their bond debt, at a time when it was unclear
whether Congress’s bankruptcy powers extended at all to public entities such as
a municipality. It is therefore unsurprising that the principal provision of
the earliest act referred to “municipal-debt readjustments.”258
Lawmakers were reluctant to use the word “bankruptcy” or words such as
“reorganization” that connoted bankruptcy, and they wanted the new law to seem
as narrow as possible. With only minor modifications,259 this label has been retained, even
as the key concerns in municipal bankruptcy have evolved. The historical origins of the term do not justify a
conclusion that Chapter 9 permits governance reform, of course. But they
provide a context for thinking about several other considerations that do seem
to make that case. First, as we have been emphasizing throughout this Article,
effective, long-term fiscal rehabilitation of the municipality, for the benefit
of both residents and creditors, may not be possible unless it includes
governance reform as well as adjustment of current debts. Debt adjustment and
governance reform may go hand-in-hand. The adjustment of a municipality’s debts
may in this sense imply governance reform as well. The second consideration is the noninterference provision we
considered in the prior Section.260
As we have seen, even if construed broadly, the provision does not forbid a
bankruptcy court from “interfering” with a municipal debtor’s political or
governmental powers under all circumstances.261
It only precludes interference to which the debtor has not consented and that
is not contained in the restructuring plan. This suggests that, notwithstanding
the ostensibly restrictive language in the title, the technical language of
Chapter 9 does not foreclose efforts to address the debtor’s municipal
political or governmental structure through the plan for adjustment. Even if §
904 is read to limit the conditions under which courts may “interfere,” the
fact that some such conditions exist belies the notion that the language of
“debt adjustment” alone restricts the court or the plan to fiscal issues,
narrowly defined. The Chapter 9 provisions that have occupied our attention in
the last two Sections were designed to ensure that Chapter 9 does not interfere
with state sovereignty under the Tenth Amendment and related constitutional
protections. But perhaps the provisions do not go far enough. Even if permitted
by Chapter 9, governance reform could be challenged as commandeering or as
imposing unconstitutional conditions on state and local decisionmakers, under a
line of Supreme Court cases that have taken on heightened significance after
the first major Affordable Care Act case, National
Federation of Independent Business v. Sebelius (NFIB).262 The concern
that governance reform would violate the Constitution, even if Chapter 9
permits it, is the most serious obstacle to our proposed rethinking of
municipal bankruptcy. Eighty years ago, state sovereignty questions cast a cloud
over all of Chapter 9. Elements of that claim remain. Objectors to Detroit’s
eligibility for municipal bankruptcy, for example, contended that Chapter 9
violated the requirement of the Bankruptcy Clause that bankruptcy laws be
“uniform.”263
Even if Chapter 9 itself is no longer in jeopardy, the prospect that it might
be used to reform municipal governance introduces a new complication. In New York v. United
States,264
Justice O’Connor identified two general principles that run through this line
of cases. First, Congress can attach conditions when it directs funds to the
states under its Spending Clause powers, so long as the conditions are
sufficiently related to the purposes of the funding.265
Second, Congress also can give states the option either to regulate in
accordance with federal standards or to face preemption.266
In each case, federal influence on state decision making is permissible if “the
residents of the State retain the ultimate decision as to whether or not the
State will comply.”267 Prior to NFIB, the
Court routinely upheld federal legislation that imposed conditions on state
decisionmakers when it involved federal spending, since “Congress has no obligation
to use its Spending Clause power to disburse funds to the States,”268
while casting a colder eye on federal intervention in other contexts.269
In NFIB, Chief Justice Roberts made
clear that the anti-commandeering principle imposes limits—in practice,
not just in theory—even on Congress’s power to attach strings to its
funding programs: “The legitimacy of Congress’s exercise of the spending power
. . . rests on whether the State voluntarily and knowingly accepts the terms of
the ‘contract.’”270 The Court
concluded that the healthcare law’s extension of Medicaid benefits to new
recipients, which gave states the option either to carry out the extension or
to forfeit all of their federal funding under the existing Medicaid program,
did not meet this standard. “In this case,” the Chief Justice wrote, “the
financial ‘inducement’ Congress has chosen is much more than ‘relatively mild
encouragement’—it is a gun to the head.”271 If we are reading the implications of NFIB correctly,272 the same
general principles apply in Spending Clause and other commandeering cases,
although the Court presumably will continue to apply them more forcefully
outside of the Spending Clause context. Since Congress enacted Chapter 9 under
the Bankruptcy Clause, not the Spending Clause, governance reform could be
subject to particularly skeptical review. Yet in many respects, Chapter 9
functions quite similarly to federal spending, and congressional conduct
pursuant to the Spending Clause therefore provides the best analogy to
Congress’s authority under the Bankruptcy Clause. Although Congress does not
disburse funds from the federal treasury under Chapter 9, discharge from debt
gives municipalities financial resources they could not obtain outside of
bankruptcy. The discharge therefore provides municipalities with the functional
equivalent of a direct grant that the federal government is not obligated to
provide to distressed municipalities.273
Assume, for example, that Congress offered a financially distressed
municipality a grant sufficient to pay its outstanding debts, but the grant was
contingent on the municipality’s adoption of a form of government that was
understood to reduce the risk of fiscal profligacy. If the Supreme Court
precedents suggest that such a conditional grant would fall outside the realm
of commandeering, then adjustments in bankruptcy that had the same effect
should be treated no differently.274
In both the spending and the general commandeering contexts,
the Court seems most concerned that states have a genuine option whether or not
to accept the incursion on their lawmaking authority. The Court’s principal
objection to the Medicaid extension was the severe penalty it exacted on states
that declined to embrace the extension.275
Included in the Court’s distinction between coercion and legitimate consent is
a concern (much criticized by commentators but oft-repeated by the Court) that
the absence of genuine consent also could undermine political accountability by
making it difficult to determine whether state or federal decision makers are
responsible.276 “[W]here the Federal Government
directs the States to regulate, it may be state officials who will bear the
brunt of public disapproval, while the federal officials who devised the
regulatory program may remain insulated from the electoral ramifications of
their decision.”277 With Chapter 9 governance reform, state and local officials
have far more authority–a more legitimate choice–than with the
federal initiatives the Court has struck down as commandeering. Most obviously,
a municipality cannot even file for Chapter 9 unless authorized to do so by
state law.278
Once a state does authorize its municipalities to file, only a municipality
itself can invoke Chapter 9; creditors are prohibited from throwing a city into
Chapter 9 involuntarily.279 States’
actual behavior underscores the absence of any federally-imposed obligation
that states feel to confer the requisite authority. Only half of the states
have enacted the requisite authorization, and of those, more than half have
imposed conditions on a municipality’s right to file for Chapter 9.280
Only after its state has authorized
municipal bankruptcy, and after a
city voluntarily files for bankruptcy, would the city face a more constrained
choice: either reform its governance or run the risk that the bankruptcy judge
will decline to approve the city’s debt adjustment plan. Even this choice is
more meaningful than the state’s options under the Medicaid extension in NFIB, since a municipality that declined
to implement governance reform would not be forced to give up federal benefits
it had previously enjoyed. Under nearly any ordinary understanding of coercion and
consent, the governance reform proposals we have advocated neither coerce nor
compel state and local decision makers.281 Even if one accepted the proposition
that federal taxation for federal programs could impose the same constraints on
states as direct commandeering by crowding out the states’ capacity to raise
their own taxes for their own purposes,282 conditions imposed on a debt adjustment
plan in bankruptcy do not entail any federal taxation. Governance reform, at
least where related to the risk of profligacy, also is directly related to
Chapter 9’s financial objectives and thus does not raise germaneness concerns.283
Finally, by their very nature, conditions created by a federal judge on a
case-by-case basis to fit the circumstances of an individual municipality in a
Chapter 9 proceeding (itself an infrequent phenomenon) impose a much lower
threat to federalism principles than congressional action that simultaneously
applies to all states and their political subdivisions. To the extent that the
value of federalism lies in experimentation and variety in the provision of
goods, services, or government institutions,284
or in the capacity of those with different preferences to sort themselves into
hospitable jurisdictions,285 little is
lost should federal action induce a single municipality to alter its governance
structure. Nevertheless, and notwithstanding our analogy to the Spending
Clause, there are dissimilarities between federal grants and federally approved
debt adjustment, and these dissimilarities point in different directions with
respect to the legitimacy of federal intervention in restructuring local
governments. As commentators have argued, spending from a federal treasury
subject to a budget constraint assumes a zero-sum quality that requires
legislators to internalize the costs of their decisions because they must pay
for even conditional spending by either sacrificing other budget items or
raising taxes.286 In theory,
spending from a fixed budget also induces potential recipients to monitor
overall spending to ensure that they obtain a fair share of expenditures.
Either argument indicates that there are political limits to the federal government’s
capacity to pursue its own policies at the expense of the states. Federal
bankruptcy control over municipalities, however, does not have the same
zero-sum quality. Thus, there is greater risk of federal overstepping of
boundaries. On the other hand, the availability to states of alternatives to
federal bankruptcy dilutes the claim that the federal government is
commandeering an operation in which states could not otherwise engage on their
own terms. States remain free to deal with municipal insolvency by negotiating
with creditors for consensual adjustments or providing assistance, perhaps
accompanied by financial control boards or other arrangements that address the
problem of moral hazard that might otherwise imperil bailouts. These mechanisms
may be less efficient and more costly than federal bankruptcy law. But the
experiences of municipalities that resolved substantial financial distress
without bankruptcy—such as New York City, Philadelphia, and
Cleveland—demonstrate that viable, if less desirable, alternatives to
federal involvement exist.287 We acknowledge, however, that two additional considerations
could make our case a closer call. The first is political accountability.
Suppose a bankruptcy judge threatened to deny confirmation unless a city
reformed its governance, but did not provide any specific guidance. If the city
proposed, for example, to privatize its sanitation department by contracting
with private providers as part of its debt adjustment plan, city voters might
not know for sure whether to treat city officials or the federal bankruptcy
judge as responsible for the new governance framework. Interestingly, these
accountability concerns counsel in favor of giving bankruptcy judges authority
to mandate governance reform directly, rather than relying on their indirect
power under current law to veto a plan that lacks governance reform as
infeasible.288
Either way, so long as bankruptcy judges are explicit about their expectations
for governance reform, the lines of accountability seem sufficiently clear to
assuage concerns about blurred responsibility. Moreover, Chapter 9 governance
reform is subject to an important check that is entirely absent under true
commandeering: as noted earlier, if municipal voters do not like the governance
reform, they could remove it after the bankruptcy case. Any reforms would be
fully reversible, subject only to the constraints that state law or the city
charter put on governance change. We anticipate that such reversals would be
infrequent, both because of the stickiness of the new status quo and because,
if the governance reform does translate into fiscal responsibility, residents
will prefer it to the prior government structure. But the possibility of
reversal does retain some autonomy for the municipality, which is lacking in
the commandeering decisions. Despite these protections, one might still worry that the
rights bankruptcy interferes with are so important that even meaningful state
and local consent to the reforms are not sufficient. “Where Congress exceeds
its authority relative to the States,” Justice O’Connor explained in New York v. United States, “the
departure from the constitutional plan cannot be ratified by the ‘consent’ of
state officials.”289 Indeed, Ashton was predicated in part on the proposition
that “[n]either consent nor submission by the States can enlarge the powers of
Congress.”290
The right of the state to determine the governance structure of its cities
could be seen, in a sense, as inalienable.291 In our view, this final objection is the most serious concern
with our governance proposal. The first thing to note in response is that
courts have traditionally been less deferential to local governments than state
governments. The Supreme Court has long construed the Eleventh Amendment as prohibiting
lawsuits against states and state officials, for instance, but not against
local officials.292 In other
areas as well, the Court has adopted a less deferential approach to local
government. Municipalities are “persons” for purposes of civil rights liability
under 42 U.S.C. § 1983;293 states are
not.294
Further, states enjoy broader antitrust immunity than their political
subdivisions.295
It is also important to point out once again that deep financial distress is
emblematic of the failure of a city’s democratic processes. Displacement of
those processes in an effort to restore the financial stability that a
well-functioning democracy would pursue arguably is far less problematic than
it might be with a city that is already providing the local public goods that
localities are created to deliver.296 Even if governance reform is legally permissible under both
Chapter 9 and the Constitution, some might raise prudential objections, arguing
that bankruptcy court intervention could do more harm than good. The first
reason for skepticism concerns an empirical difficulty. Even if it is
appropriate to use Chapter 9 for structural reform where governance issues are
a cause of bankruptcy, are bankruptcy judges competent to distinguish cases in
which fiscal distress emerges from internal dysfunction rather than exogenous
circumstances? It is, for example, plausible that Detroit’s decline was caused
as much by the exit of the auto industry, an increase in energy prices that drove
industry to the Sun Belt, and high labor costs as by municipal policies.297
One might question whether courts can disaggregate the various causes of fiscal
distress or distinguish symptom from cause. Given that judicial intervention
would interfere with democratic governance, restructuring would be appropriate
only when political failure was clearly a major contributor to fiscal failure. Despite their limitations, bankruptcy judges will often be
able to determine whether fiscal instability is due to some exogenous event or
to political dysfunction. The bankruptcy filing in Harrisburg, Pennsylvania,
for example, was precipitated by an investment in a failed incinerator project
that did not necessarily reflect broad-based fiscal impropriety.298
But even municipalities that suffer exogenous shocks have opportunities to
recover or to adjust to new circumstances. Failure to do so may be a
consequence of entrenched decision-making structures rather than of the initial
event. Some evidence of political dysfunction may be inferred where
bankruptcy has been preceded by a period of decline in tax revenues and
population without offsetting reductions in expenditures and with heavy
reliance on borrowing. Some evidence suggests that high debt levels and high
spending levels are correlated with political relationships rather than with
structural factors outside the control of city officials.299
Therefore, increasing debt-to-revenue ratios or increasing deficits over a
period of years may demonstrate a lack of political will to confront long-term
distress in order to serve short-term interests. Increases in workforce or
expenditures to groups that have an advantage in organizing may also be indicia
that politics rather than resident demand has been driving unsustainable budgetary
decisions.300
For example, at the height of its fiscal crisis in 1976, New York City’s
municipal public employment levels and labor costs per capita were
significantly above those of virtually all other major municipalities (with the
exception of the District of Columbia), perhaps indicating the strength of
interest groups rather than service demand.301
Detroit’s decline was characterized by inefficiencies in the delivery of
municipal services—such as reduced collection rates of property taxes,
redundancy in municipal functions, mismanagement of grant funding, and public
employee work rules based on seniority—rather than simply insufficient
revenues.302 Therefore, it appears that,
notwithstanding frequent ambiguity about the causal relationship between
governance and fiscal distress, even a court wary of interfering with municipal
structures would be able to identify situations in which the link is
sufficiently clear to justify remedial efforts. Causation difficulties, however, do not exhaust the potential
objections to allocating the responsibility to bankruptcy courts. A second
difficulty involves the unintended consequences of any proposed governance
reform. In this version of the “grass is greener” fallacy, the court may
compare an existing, failed governance structure with an untried but romantic
one. It is plausible that courts desirous of doing something to address a distressed city’s political dysfunction
could advocate structural reform that is ill-suited to the situation. We have,
for example, indicated that the empirical literature on the relationship
between government structure and fiscal performance is not monolithic.303
Thus, it is plausible that a recommended reorganization will not have the
anticipated effects. The variety of governance structures in both private and
public realms suggests that no costless version of governance exists. Instead,
different structures generate different costs and benefits. As we have noted,
centralized governance promotes unified decision making in a manner that considers
the interests of all constituents and thus avoids the adverse effects of
fragmentation.304 But
centralization simultaneously creates a risk of political monopoly and
disenfranchisement of those with minority views, and those features can also lead
to problematic financial effects. Centralized local governments, for example,
can direct public expenditures to a political base even though the overall
effect is to dilute the financial stability of the locality as a whole.305
There is a risk that the institutions selected to address the governance
failures to which a bankruptcy judge attributes fiscal distress will simply
generate new difficulties that are different from, but not necessarily less
serious than, those that the court purports to remedy. Even institutional structures that increase financial
stability may generate offsetting costs in terms of democratic governance or
misallocation of resources to a new, but no more deserving, class of favored
beneficiaries. A strong mayor may have the capacity to eliminate expensive
projects that the majority of residents find too costly, but may also eliminate
projects that the majority supports.306
Some structural reforms could frustrate positive change by handing power to a
group disinclined to implement it, such as if at-large council members turned
out to favor the status quo more than those elected from districts. While we acknowledge the risk, it is also important to
recognize that similar uncertainties underlie restructuring of firms under
Chapter 11.307
Moreover, a court that induces consideration of structural reforms can hear
arguments and evidence about existing political dysfunction and the propriety
of reorganization in a particular case, shedding light on issues that Chapter 9
cases currently ignore, even in spite of their relevance to fiscal stability.
Where a locality suffers political conditions sufficiently dysfunctional to
precipitate debt adjustment in bankruptcy and sufficiently entrenched to resist
internal reform, it may be desirable to accept the risk of unintended
consequences over the certainty of structurally induced fiscal distress. A final concern is that the prospect of governance reform
might have a chilling effect on municipal bankruptcy filings. Municipalities
may be more reluctant to file for Chapter 9 relief because those who are
currently charged with making that decision will be disinclined to initiate a
process that could dilute their authority. Relatedly, states, which have full
discretion to prevent their municipalities from filing for Chapter 9 relief,
could be reluctant to grant the requisite specific authority308
necessary to allow even a willing municipality to enter Chapter 9 because the
state prefers to maintain control over the governance of its political
subdivisions. In either case, the effect would be to deny a fiscally distressed
municipality the benefits from debt adjustment only available in Chapter 9.
Perhaps it would be preferable to permit the limited relief available under the
current regime and hope that recidivism will not occur rather than to risk
municipal or state avoidance of an imperfect, but useful, debt adjustment
process. Although these concerns are real, we doubt that the risk of
governance restructuring within bankruptcy would alter the calculus of either
municipal or state officials concerning the decision to enter or permit a
Chapter 9 filing. From the perspective of municipal officials, the possibility
of diminished power looms large. But the officials of a municipality that is on
the cusp of bankruptcy face a highly uncertain future; if debt adjustment is
necessary to avoid further deterioration of the local economy and subsequent
deterioration of officials’ political future, then even self-interested
officials may consider Chapter 9 to be the best alternative, notwithstanding
the possibility of restructuring. As we noted above with respect to the
possibility of obtaining consent under § 904, to the extent that the local
executive would be the beneficiary of centralized decision making that we have
associated with fiscal stability, a mayor is likely to prefer restructuring
that would permit consolidation of budgetary decisions under his or her
auspices to the status quo.309 City council
members, who are more likely to lose patronage and power under any movement
toward a strong mayor system, might be more likely to oppose a Chapter 9 filing
that risks restructuring.310 In at least
some cases, any objections of the city council will be irrelevant because other
parties have the relevant authority when the municipality faces sufficient
distress to warrant a Chapter 9 petition. New York, Michigan, and Rhode Island,
for example, may place fiscally distressed localities under the supervision of
a financial control board or emergency manager.311
Once appointed, those authorities may recommend to state officials that the
local government be authorized to file a Chapter 9 petition, as Detroit’s
emergency manager did,312 or may
directly file such a petition.313 Moreover, if governance restructuring were otherwise
considered an appropriate role for a federal bankruptcy court, the potential
tendency of city councils to avoid filings in order to retain authority could
be overcome by an amendment to the Bankruptcy Code that placed filing authority
in the hands of the local executive. To be sure, a state may consider such intervention to be an
intrusion on its own prerogative to determine the governance structure of its
political subdivisions and forbid its municipalities from filing for Chapter 9.
But the political economy of municipal fiscal distress is more complicated. The
experiences of Detroit and New York City reveal that state officials may be
reluctant to interfere with municipal political processes because local officials
and constituencies may blame state officials for the diminution of local
autonomy.314
State officials, therefore, may prefer that any such diminution be imposed by a
third party. The ability of state officials to “blame” a federal bankruptcy
judge for redesigning institutions that enhance local (and state) fiscal
stability may be sufficiently attractive to make Chapter 9 more appealing
rather than less.315 Moreover, the threat that municipal restructuring poses to
the state’s plenary authority over its political subdivisions is perhaps more
limited than initially appears to be the case. As we discuss below, the state
retains the capacity to impose governance structures that render bankruptcy
court intrusion unnecessary.316 Even within
bankruptcy, the state is likely to play a significant role in formulating the
plan that the debtor municipality submits for confirmation. In addition to its
other authority over a municipality, the state will typically be the source of
substantial capital infusions that will be necessary to make any plan feasible.317
Of course, the state’s plenary authority over its localities survives
bankruptcy so that the state presumably could also intervene subsequent to the
municipality’s exit from bankruptcy to readjust the local governance structure.
As a result, any action taken by the bankruptcy court that conflicted with
state preferences could be temporary. The state might not object for yet another reason as well.
The state could effectively pre-empt federal bankruptcy court intervention if
the state itself took action that addressed governance issues in fiscally
distressed localities. Indeed, one benefit of allowing a federal bankruptcy
court to restructure municipal governance is that the threat of judicial
intervention could induce states to act more expeditiously in addressing local
structural defects and thus avoid the need for a bankruptcy court to take any
measures. In short, the very presence of the power to restructure municipal
governance in bankruptcy could render its exercise superfluous. That possibility, however, raises a related question: If
states have the capacity to alter municipal governance structures, why not
leave that task to the state and limit the bankruptcy court to the traditional
role of adjusting debts? It is to that question that we next turn. In this Part, we address the capacity of states, rather than
bankruptcy courts, to restructure dysfunctional local governments. We begin by
acknowledging that states have political and institutional advantages over
courts for this purpose. But we contend that there will be occasions when the
state is disabled from exploiting those advantages. Restrictions on state
intervention result from two sources. First, legal doctrines that define the
relationship between the state and its political subdivisions may prevent state
interference with local governmental structures. Those doctrines typically
arise from principles of home rule that grant municipal governments immunity
from state interference with respect to local internal organization. Second,
the political economy of state intervention may render it difficult for states
to intervene in local institutional design, even when the state has the legal
authority to do so. If governance restructuring is vital to municipal fiscal
health, the natural question to ask is why the state, rather than a federal
bankruptcy court, is not the appropriate entity to impose governance
restructuring in the face of recalcitrant local officials. After all, standard
legal doctrine provides that states can exercise plenary power over their
political subdivisions, constrained only by federal or state constitutional
law.318
State legislatures, which deal with local governmental powers on a regular
basis, appear to have a comparative advantage over courts, including federal
bankruptcy courts, in designing institutions that affect the welfare of
municipal residents. As Omer Kimhi has argued, the state is well positioned to
deal with municipal fiscal distress because it has greater control over the
socioeconomic or political causes of crisis and has the capacity, by
conditional bailout, direct state takeovers, or the imposition of local
governance mechanisms, to resolve it.319
Moreover, to the extent that local fiscal distress threatens to spill over to
other jurisdictions in the state—either by reducing the faith of credit
markets in the fiscal health of neighboring jurisdictions or by threatening
consequences in the metropolitan economy—the state has the appropriate
motivation to intervene.320 Finally, it
is more consistent with principles of federalism to permit the state to dictate
forms of governance than to invite the intervention of a federal bankruptcy
court. For each of these reasons, it is preferable that the state
design and dictate structural change for municipalities. We are concerned,
however, with the very common case in which the state has not addressed the
question of institutional design in the face of fiscal distress.321
If inaction is the consequence of a deliberate decision that state intervention
would entail costs in excess of the benefits of enhanced fiscal stability,
there may be little reason for a federal bankruptcy court to revisit the
inquiry. If, however, the state’s inaction is motivated by factors unrelated to
questions of institutional design, then it may be desirable to have a third
party, such as a federal bankruptcy court, induce appropriate structural
change. Of course, ad hoc explanations for state inaction in a particular case
are difficult to discern and thus invite courts to engage in messy speculation
about state political processes. To determine whether or not bankruptcy courts
should abstain from municipal governance reform we therefore will need to
consider what, as a general matter, explains state inaction rather than what
occurred in a particular case. For two very different reasons, states may often fail to
impose appropriate governance structures on a fiscally distressed municipality.
The first, a relatively benign story, involves legal doctrines that dictate the
relationships between the state and its political subdivisions.322
These doctrines limit the state’s authority to intervene, although the
constraints are much weaker than might initially seem to be the case. The
second, perhaps a more complicated and malign explanation, involves the
political economy of those same relationships.323
The political impediments are much more significant, and confirm the need for
bankruptcy court intervention. Our discussion of state intervention focuses on the capacity of
state legislatures to restructure local government. In theory, state courts
with authority to resolve municipal distress could make restructuring part of a
state insolvency process and perhaps circumvent some of the political economy
obstacles that we attribute to legislatures. Indeed, McConnell and Picker
argued for displacement of federal municipal bankruptcy law with state
municipal bankruptcy law.324 We have
little disagreement about the institutional capacity of a state bankruptcy
regime to address matters of municipal governance. But, as McConnell and Picker
recognized, current law restricts that option since the Bankruptcy Code limits
states’ ability to enact laws that impose debt adjustments on unwilling
creditors.325
McConnell and Picker concluded that elimination of that provision would permit
states to enact their own adjustment laws.326
They rejected the obvious response that the Contracts Clause precludes states
from impairing the obligation of contract.327
We are less certain. McConnell and Picker relied on the Supreme Court’s
decision in Faitoute Iron & Steel v.
City of Asbury Park, which upheld a state municipal insolvency statute
against a Contracts Clause challenge on the grounds that the law created no
impairment if it allowed a creditor a greater probability of recovery than
would otherwise have been possible.328
A debt adjustment plan that promises a creditor of a bankrupt municipality
something rather than the nothing that would otherwise be forthcoming will
satisfy that standard. But subsequent Contracts Clause jurisprudence allows
such exceptions only in the face of a “broad, generalized economic or social
problem.”329
Certainly the Great Depression, during which Asbury Park fell into insolvency,
qualified. Fiscal distress that imperils the solvency of a major city and
threatens substantial national effects might similarly qualify. But it is less
certain that distress attributed to the profligate pension arrangements of a
city with less national importance would.330
In any event, the ad hoc determination that would be required concerning the
constitutionality of impairment in a particular situation makes a state
municipal restructuring law too uncertain to be a basis for reliance. McConnell and Picker may stand on stronger ground when they
contend that state insolvency laws in effect at the time municipal distress
materializes would not violate the Contracts Clause because those laws become
part of subsequently negotiated contracts.331
But that solution requires initial legislative intervention of the type that,
in this Part, we suggest has a low likelihood of materializing prior to the
fiscal crisis that it is intended to redress. Indeed, to the extent that state
legislatures have recently addressed the possibility of municipal insolvency,
they have demonstrated more sympathy for creditors than municipalities by
granting bondholders liens that would arguably withstand reduction even in
federal bankruptcy proceedings.332 We thus concentrate on the capacity
and incentives of legislators to require structural reform outside of municipal
debt adjustment. Notwithstanding the traditional view that a state can
exercise plenary power over its political subdivisions, state constitutional
doctrines place constraints on the state’s interference with local autonomy.333
A legislature that respected those constraints and thus refused to restructure
municipal institutions of governance may simply be adhering to a settled allocation
of responsibility between states and their political subdivisions. Violation of
those constraints by dictating forms of governance could be seen as imposing
costs on local autonomy in excess of the benefits of redressing even a serious
fiscal crisis. The most powerful limitation on state authority gives
municipalities the authority to exercise home rule in the design of their own
governance structures. Home rule, however, is not a monolithic concept. In some
jurisdictions, it provides a municipality only with initiative authority; the
municipality can legislate in an area designated as “local concern” or
“municipal affairs” even without prior legislative authorization.334
In other jurisdictions, home rule authority provides a broader level of local
autonomy by immunizing the locality from state intervention, again with respect
to matters denominated as involving purely “municipal affairs.”335
In the first set of jurisdictions, the exercise of home rule is always subject
to state intervention; there is no area in which the locality is entitled to
trump a conflicting state statute. In such a jurisdiction, the state could
always impose a form of government on one of its municipalities, even if the
municipality preferred an alternative. For example, Michigan’s Home Rule City
Act requires a city charter to contain provisions for the election of specified
officers for specified terms.336 A
municipality that preferred a different set of local officials, or different
terms for them, would be unable to trump the state, notwithstanding home rule
status. State inaction in such a jurisdiction cannot be explained as a function
of a doctrinal requirement that the state be excluded from designing municipal
institutions. In the second set of jurisdictions, there is a stronger claim
that home rule status precludes the state from intervening in matters that
involve an insufficient degree of statewide concern. If the structure of
municipal governance falls into that category, then municipal choices trump the
state’s, as several courts have held. The Arizona Supreme Court recently opined
that, notwithstanding general ambiguity about the dividing line between matters
of state concern and local concern, it “is absolutely clear that charter city
governments enjoy autonomy with respect to structuring their own governments.”337
Thus, a state statute that provided for partisan ballots did not displace a
municipal charter requirement of non-partisan elections;338
a state prohibition on partisan elections did not bar local partisan elections
for charter cities;339 and a local
residency requirement for political candidates trumped a more stringent state
statute.340
Other states have similarly concluded that the governance structures of home
rule municipalities, at least insofar as they involve elections, trump
conflicting state laws.341 The New
Mexico Supreme Court concluded that a state statute that dictated a set number
of city commissioners did not bind home rule municipalities.342 None of these decisions, however, have been rendered in the
face of an effort to impose institutions on a municipality that faces fiscal
distress. Distress could alter the calculus because home rule authority is
limited to matters of local concern, and fiscal distress may entail extramural
effects. At least in part for this reason, courts have permitted states to
alter the governance structure of home rule municipalities by appointing
receivers or financial control boards, although these courts have also
emphasized the temporary nature of the intervention.343 It is somewhat unclear whether a
state that otherwise grants localities full autonomy with respect to its local
affairs would be permitted to dictate institutional design of a more
longstanding nature for a municipality if the state made capital infusions or
if the municipality’s fiscal distress led to higher borrowing costs elsewhere
in the state. In addition to home rule limitations, constraints on special
legislation may seem to restrict a state’s authority. Most state constitutions
preclude the enactment of special legislation that imposes unique burdens
affecting only some of the state’s political subdivisions.344
The aversion to imposition of unique burdens is implicit in those constitutions
that permit special legislation to be enacted only if the affected locality
agrees. The Michigan Constitution, for example, only permits special
legislation if it has been approved by two-thirds of “members elected to and
serving in each house and by a majority of the electors voting thereon in the
district affected.”345 The consent
prerequisite in the Michigan constitutional clause, which has common analogues
in other state constitutions,346 effectively
precludes the legislature from enacting laws that will specially burden a
particular locality. The special legislation prohibition seems to limit the
capacity of the legislature to tailor a governance structure to those
municipalities that suffer fiscal distress. Nevertheless, like home rule, the special legislation
prohibition serves as a relatively weak constraint. Courts have systematically
allowed legislatures to enact legislation that affects only a subset of
municipalities as long as the classification is rationally related to a
permitted state purpose.347 In this
sense, special legislation analysis essentially follows equal protection analysis
under the federal Constitution. Thus, legislation that imposes government
structures on municipalities that have required state financial assistance,
that have been placed into receivership, or that fail to maintain a balanced
budget for a particular period of time could arguably avoid invalidation, even
though they apply only to a class of municipalities. Moreover, both courts and
state constitutions have occasionally allocated to the legislature itself the
capacity to determine whether proposed legislation is “special” within the
meaning of the prohibition.348 Thus, fear
of invalidation is unlikely to restrain a legislature otherwise convinced of
the propriety of intervention in the governance of a distressed municipality. The limited scope of the special legislation prohibition may
have conflicting implications for a state’s ability to require governance
reform in distressed municipalities. On the one hand, the state’s ability to
circumvent the constitutional limitation through creative classification
suggests that there is less need to rely on bankruptcy courts to reform
dysfunctional governance structures. On the other hand, statutory reforms that
appear directed at an individual locality necessarily raise questions about
legislative motivation and are more susceptible to judicial invalidation. A
recent example involves legislation enacted by the Michigan legislature in the
wake of Detroit’s efforts to exit bankruptcy proceedings. One of those laws
required a city with a population of six hundred thousand or more to establish
the position of chief financial officer, to be appointed by the mayor subject
to the approval of the governing body of the city, and if applicable, any
financial review commission that has authority over budgetary matters in the city.349
At the time that the legislation was enacted, Detroit’s population was just
under seven hundred thousand, but had been falling substantially in the four
years prior.350
The next largest city in Michigan has a population of less than two hundred
thousand.351
Thus the population figure appears to be a substitute for inserting into the
legislation the word “Detroit,” a measure that would likely have run afoul of
Michigan’s prohibition on special legislation where a general law is possible.352
Presumably, the legislature did not believe that it was appropriate to dictate
municipal officials for all cities or even for all large cities; perhaps more
realistically, localities would have resisted such intrusion into local
governance. While the Michigan legislature was willing to risk invalidation to
enact a statute that would impose governance constraints on Detroit, and only
Detroit, either less salient cases of fiscal imprudence or more aversion to
circumventing constitutional constraints could induce legislatures to take a
more conservative approach and avoid imposing governance reforms even on
distressed localities. The prior Section suggested that legal doctrine provides
some, albeit minor, constraints on the capacity of the legislature to dictate
forms of governance to the state’s municipalities. Where legal constraints
operate, bankruptcy court intervention to restructure municipal governance
might be seen as improper rebalancing of the priorities that the state had
struck between the interests in local autonomy and the risk that a municipality
or the state would suffer as a consequence of flaws in the design of municipal
governance. The limited scope of constitutional restrictions on state
legislatures during municipal fiscal crisis, however, indicates that those
doctrines do not substantially foreclose impinging on local decisions. The
explanation for legislative inertia must lie elsewhere. It is, of course, plausible that the state would have been
willing to intervene in municipal structure in an appropriate case, but that
the legislature made a considered determination that such drastic action was
undesirable in the specific case of the municipality that had entered Chapter
9. The case for restructuring depends on balancing the costs and benefits of
governance reform, and the legislature could have made a good faith
determination that the costs of restructuring were excessive. In that case,
judicial revisiting of the decision would appear inappropriate, given the legislature’s
comparative (if imperfect) advantage in defining the limits of municipal
authority and the proper allocation of state and local responsibilities. Thus,
the area in which judicial intervention would appear to be appropriate would be
those cases in which the legislature not only had failed to deploy measures
that would enhance fiscal stability for the municipality, but had failed to do
so for less benign reasons than a considered judgment of the value of
restructuring. It is, of course, difficult to the point of fruitless to
determine legislative intent in the case of legislative inaction. As William
Eskridge has demonstrated, legislative inertia may result from different
degrees of intensity in favor of acting as well as from insufficient support for
action.353
Assume, for example, that state legislators responded to fiscal instability in
a municipality in the following manner: forty percent of the legislators
desired no tampering with the municipality’s governance structure; forty
percent desired requiring the municipality to move to a strong mayor model; and
twenty percent favored disincorporating the city and merging it with the county
surrounding it. Assume further that each of these positions was resistant to
compromise. Under that scenario, there would be a solid majority for taking
action about municipal governance, but the result would be inaction. It would
be difficult to argue that a bankruptcy court should intervene to correct the
result, because the legislature had not failed to consider restructuring; it
simply failed to achieve consensus on the form restructuring should take. Nor
could the court assume that the existence of a majority for some form of
restructuring provided the court with authority to select a restructuring
option and impose it in the name of achieving majority will. Assume, for
example, that the forty percent that favored a strong mayor also favored no
action over disincorporation, and that the twenty percent that favored
disincorporation also favored no action over a strong mayor. Under those
circumstances, a court could not correctly conclude that any form of
restructuring was a majoritarian preference compared to no restructuring. Uncertainty about legislative process and intent does not,
however, necessarily leave a court helpless or mired in unfettered speculation.
Legislative history, although sparser in the state context than in the federal
one, should reveal whether any discussion of restructuring has occurred. Even
in the absence of legislative history, one might conclude that the state’s
failure to act is the result of considered judgment if inertia is inconsistent
with incentives that the state otherwise has to intervene. Given the structure
of the state government, the state legislature should be willing, if not anxious,
it might seem, to impose a governance structure on municipalities that are
experiencing fiscal distress. This is true for two reasons. First, as Roderick
Hills has argued, the state has incentives to expand the scope of its
jurisdiction and therefore to invade areas that might properly be allocated to
localities.354
If state legislatures desire to expand their jurisdiction, fiscal distress
provides an opportunity to act on “imperialist” tendencies. Second, as we have
suggested above,355 fiscal
distress could generate negative externalities sufficient to overcome
objections that principles of home rule preclude a state role in municipal
affairs. In addition, municipal fiscal distress that is sufficiently
severe to attract legislative attention traditionally involves major cities,
and the traditional story of state/local relationships suggests widespread
suburban and rural hostility to urban areas.356 Thus, one can infer that the
legislature will be more likely to exploit local fiscal distress to discipline or
embarrass a municipality that was often the target of statewide animosity.
Given these apparent incentives to intervene, a state’s failure to intervene
could, theoretically, reflect legislative judgments—to which bankruptcy
courts should defer—rather than inertia or a political impasse. In reality, however, inertia or impasse is more likely to be
the principal explanation for inaction. Begin with the contention that the
state legislature is likely to exploit opportunities to discipline or embarrass
the distressed municipality. Recent scholarship indicates that the relationship
between urban areas and the state legislature is more complicated than the
traditional story of hostility. Cities that desire additional authority from
the legislature often obtain it; indeed, empirically minded students of state
processes conclude, “State legislatures have routinely deferred to local
governments.”357 A recent paper by Gamm and Kousser
demonstrates that the failure of large cities to obtain legislative authority
is due less to hostility from other jurisdictions or to partisan politics than
to disagreement within the delegation from the affected locality.358
Legislators are willing to defer to the preferences of local legislators where
those preferences are clear. Where disunity within the local delegation in the
state legislature obfuscates the signal about city preferences, other
legislators have no one to defer to.359
If there is unified resistance to state intervention within the delegation from
the affected municipality, by contrast, that may be sufficient to quash any
effort to impose a government structure. Moreover, to the extent that
partisanship explains state interference in local government, it may also
explain state inaction. If the distressed municipality is dominated by the same
party that dominates the state legislature, the state legislature may be
reluctant to chastise local political leaders by imposing an unwanted
governance structure on them.360 These results suggest that a locality may have sufficient
influence in the legislature to forestall any efforts to impose structural
change, even when doing so would enhance fiscal stability. If that is the case,
then the argument for bankruptcy court to restructure municipal governance may
be stronger because legislative inaction about municipal structure would result
from the dominant position of the distressed municipality rather than from the
considered judgment of the legislature about the propriety of imposing
institutions that could provide fiscal stability. To be sure, the studies finding that legislatures defer to
municipal will may be skewed by their focus on bills introduced by delegates from
the affected localities.361 Legislators
from other jurisdictions may be indifferent about autonomous decision making by
the affected city, because exercise of the extended authority has few external
effects. But if the municipality has fallen into distress, and the distress
could have extramural consequences, state legislators’ deference could quickly
dissipate. In theory, this reasoning could explain states’ willingness to enact
legislation introduced by local officials under ordinary circumstances, while
also suggesting that a state’s failure to intervene when a municipality falls
into distress reflects considered judgment rather than a political failure that
warrants bankruptcy court intervention. Yet, even if state legislators can be expected to intervene
in the event of fiscal distress, they have little incentive to correct
dysfunctional governance arrangements. State intervention that reacts to
concerns about the external effects of fiscal distress tends to target the
immediate crisis. The principal concern is to reassure credit markets that the
municipality at issue and other municipalities will not default. Governance
reform, by contrast, is intended to generate long-term solutions by addressing
the causes of a crisis rather than the imminent consequences of inadequate
existing institutions. Centralized decision making, for example, may reduce the
size of budgets by eliminating logrolled deals in the future. It will not,
however, assure the current payment of debts or assist in the renegotiation of burdensome
executory contracts. Nor is restructuring likely to be salient to those who are
concerned about the immediate need to address budgetary deficits or to balance
the conflicting claims of creditors, public employees, and residents to an
insufficient local treasury. Thus, state legislative efforts to address a local
fiscal crisis have typically focused on some form of state takeover, either
through a receivership or through a control board.362
Each of these methods has the capacity to exercise substantial authority over
budgetary decision making of the distressed municipality. But these forms of
intervention are intended to be temporary, to dissolve at the end of the crisis
period, and to manage the current crisis rather than to impose longstanding
structural changes on the municipality. In the New York City fiscal crisis of
the 1970s, for example, Senate Republicans agreed to provide assistance
necessary to avoid a default, but the conditions focused on empowering the
Municipal Assistance Corporation for the City of New York as a supervisory
agency rather than revamping the internal governance of the city.363
There is another reason to suspect that a failure by the
state to intervene will usually reflect inertia, rather than a considered
judgment. We have hypothesized that restructuring often would move in the
direction of a more centralized municipal decision-making process. That means
that restructuring will confer more authority on mayors and detract from the
authority of city-council members. Assuming that mayors would prefer more
authority to less, one might initially imagine that the legislature would be
motivated to mandate centralization, because the mayor of a major city is
likely to have more influence with the state legislature than individual city-council
members.364
If that is true, then, again, one might conclude that the failure of the state
legislature to intervene is a consequence of a substantive judgment that such a
move is, on balance, undesirable, rather than a consequence of political alignments.
But a period of fiscal distress is not a propitious time for
the legislature to confer additional authority on the mayor of a municipality
that faces fiscal distress. The incumbent mayor is likely to have become a
focal point of blame for the very distress that additional centralization is
intended to alleviate. Even if the absence of centralized control is
responsible for the distress, the fact that the crisis materialized on the
incumbent’s watch makes that official less likely to receive sympathy from the
legislature. Instead, the legislature will likely question the competence of
the mayors whose cities face local distress, and those mayors are unlikely to
enjoy a promising political future, at least in the short term.365
Nor is the mayor, even one with influence, likely to advocate
any governance reforms, no matter how essential, that would detract from her
executive authority. For example, we noted above that the legislation enacted
by the government of Michigan required Detroit to appoint a chief financial
officer—a rare instance of legislative intervention in municipal
governance in the face of fiscal crisis. That requirement was presumably
intended to provide centralized decision making insofar as it created a single
umbrella for what had been a multi-faceted budgetary process.366
It is unlikely that a mayor would advocate such a reform in the state
legislature. Similarly, as we have indicated above, a requirement that a
municipality elect its city council through an at-large system rather than through
district elections could facilitate fiscal stability because it would reduce
the benefits of district-by-district logrolling. But a mayor may be agnostic
about or oppose such a change because it would undermine that official’s claim
to be the only representative elected by the electorate as a whole. In summary, the failure of the state to restructure municipal
governance in the face of fiscal crisis is not likely to be a consequence of
considered legislative judgment that should foreclose a bankruptcy court’s
visitation of the subject. Nor is it likely to emanate from respect for legal
doctrines that caution against interference with local autonomy. Instead,
legislative inertia is likely to result from political considerations that are
disembodied from the optimal allocation of authority between the state and its
localities or the optimal design of fiscally stable institutions within the
locality. Some political deviations from ideal institutional design must, of
course, be tolerated, if for no other reason than the low likelihood that
political actors, such as courts, will be able to improve on decisions made in
the political market. But where fiscal crisis translates into the inability of
the municipality to provide the basic services for which it has been created,
the failure of the state to address root causes signals a sufficient gap to
warrant some redress. Since bankruptcy courts have been assigned the
responsibility of supervising the restructuring of municipal debts and thus
addressing the symptoms of a failed system of governance, they seem relatively
well positioned to address the causes of that system, at least where the state
itself has demonstrated an incapacity to intervene. According to the conventional wisdom, municipal bankruptcy
can only be used to restructure a municipality’s debt. Attempting to reform a
city’s governance would purportedly violate state sovereignty, as well as
several key provisions of Chapter 9 that were drafted with state sovereignty in
mind. The Detroit bankruptcy largely reflected this conventional wisdom.
Although the court-appointed feasibility expert warned about the potential
consequences of failing to address Detroit’s operational problems, Detroit
restructured its debt without addressing the dysfunctional features of its
municipal governance. It would be unfortunate if Chapter 9 were as limited as the
conventional wisdom suggests. When a substantial city files for bankruptcy, its
excessive debt may only be the external manifestation of problems that run much
deeper. Fragmentation and related governance problems are nearly always a key
underlying cause of the city’s financial distress. If Chapter 9 cannot address
these deeper problems, its efficacy may be quite limited. In this Article, we have argued that Chapter 9 can and should
address these deeper problems. Governance reform is a common feature of
corporate reorganization in Chapter 11, and it is even more essential for the
restructuring of a troubled city, since a city, unlike a corporation, cannot be
liquidated or ownership rights transferred from one group of stakeholders to
another. Although we acknowledge that governance reform could be challenged on
constitutional grounds or as violating one or more provisions of Chapter 9 that
are designed to limit the scope of bankruptcy court intervention, we believe
that governance reform would ultimately withstand challenge. If it does,
Chapter 9 could prove to be a more effective tool for addressing the financial
distress of substantial cities than even its advocates have imagined. Introduction
I. municipal
reorganization and corporate reorganization
A. The
Need for Municipal Governance Reform
B. Governance
Reform in Chapter 11
II. why
hasn’t governance been a focus in chapter 9?
A. Municipal
Bankruptcy in the 1930s
B. Ashton to
Congress to Bekins
C. New
York City and the 1970s Amendments
D. Selection
Bias in Municipal Bankruptcy Filings
III. an affirmative case for governance
reform
A. Fragmented
Governance as a Source of Distress
B. Bankruptcy
as a Governance Corrective
IV. objections to governance reform in
chapter 9
A. Bankruptcy
Courts Cannot Interfere with Municipal Powers
B. Only
the “Adjustment of Debts” Is Permitted in Chapter 9
C. Commandeering
and Unconstitutional Conditions
D. Will
Bankruptcy Judges Make Matters Worse?
E. Will
Governance Reform Discourage Bankruptcy Filings?
V. why
not the state?
A. Doctrinal
Constraints on State Design of Municipal Governance
B. The
Political Economy of Structural Reform
Conclusion