Illegitimate Borders: Jus Sanguinis Citizenship and the Legal Construction of Family, Race, and Nation
abstract. The citizenship status of children born to American parents outside the United States is governed by a complex set of statutes. When the parents of such children are not married, these statutes encumber the transmission of citizenship between father and child while readily recognizing the child of an American mother as a citizen. Much of the debate concerning the propriety and constitutionality of those laws has centered on the extent to which they reflect gender-traditional understandings of fathers’ and mothers’ respective parental roles, or instead reflect “real difference.” Based on extensive archival research, this Article demonstrates that an important yet overlooked reason for the development of gender- and marriage-based derivative citizenship law—jus sanguinis citizenship—was officials’ felt need to enforce the racially nativist policies that were a core component of American nationality law for over 150 years. The complex interaction of gender, race, family law, and nationality law charted here demonstrates that gender-based jus sanguinis citizenship is not a biologically inevitable feature of American nationality law, as has been argued, but is in important respects the product of choices made by officials engaged in a racially nativist nation-building project. This history also suggests that what is at stake in modern challenges to gender-based citizenship laws is not only the constitutionality of those statutes, but a mode of reasoning about citizenship, family, gender, and race that continues to shape the practice and politics of citizenship in ways that are often obscured in modern citizenship debates.
author. Professor of Law, Boston University School of Law; Sidley Austin-Robert D. McLean ’70 Visiting Professor of Law, Yale Law School, 2013-2014. Earlier versions of this Article were presented at Yale Law School, the University of Minnesota, the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Boston University, Iowa University, the University of California at Irvine, Chicago-Kent, and the annual meetings of the American Society for Legal History and the American Association of Law Schools. I am grateful for the thoughtful comments I received during those presentations, as well as input from numerous colleagues, including Kerry Abrams, Kathy Baker, Angela Banks, Susanna Blumenthal, Khiara Bridges, Janet Calvo, Sam Erman, Bill Eskridge, Ariela Gross, Harold Koh, Gary Lawson, Carol Lee, Stephen Lee, Gerry Leonard, Serena Mayeri, Hiroshi Motomura, Melissa Murray, Claire Priest, Judith Resnik, Cristina Rodríguez, David Seipp, Dan Sharfstein, Reva Siegel, Norman Spaulding, Emma Teng, Patrick Weil, Barbara Welke, John Witt, and especially Linda Kerber. Archivists William Creech, David Langbart, and Rodney Ross, of the National Archives, and Zachary Wilske, of the Historical Research Branch of the U.S. Citizen and Immigration Services, provided expert assistance during my research trips to Washington and went beyond the call of duty on several occasions. Fabulous research assistants helped at different stages of this project: Allison Gorsuch, Jessica Marsden, and Rebecca Counts of Yale Law School, and Stephanie Hoffman, Jarrod Schaeffer, and Jessica Wall of Boston University School of Law. Law librarians at Boston University and Yale Law School deserve special commendations for their able and diligent assistance procuring sources. Finally, my thanks to the editors of the Yale Law Journal, and especially to Alex Hemmer, for superb and thoughtful editorial assistance.
Introduction
[I]t seems clear that illegitimate half-castes born in semi-barbarous countries of American fathers and native women are not American citizens.
–Edwin Borchard,The Diplomatic Protection of Citizens Abroad (1915)
Children born in the United States are citizens by virtue of the Fourteenth Amendment’s Citizenship Clause, but the citizenship status of children born to Americans living outside the United States is governed by a complex set of statutes.1 When the parents of such children are unmarried, those laws encumber citizenship transmission between the father and his child, while providing nearly automatic citizenship transmission between an American mother and her child.2 In three constitutional challenges to the gender-based regulation of parent-child citizenship transmission—Miller v. Albright, Nguyen v. INS, and Flores-Villar v. United States—the Supreme Court upheld these distinctions while laboring to explain why Congress has drawn such sharp lines between the nonmarital children of American mothers and fathers.3 Historians and legal scholars have also addressed this issue, and the resulting scholarship has largely focused on the origin of the gender-based regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship in the traditional cultural and legal norms that governed mothers’ and fathers’ respective parental rights and responsibilities outside marriage, and the perpetuation of those norms in what is now called derivative citizenship law.4
In this Article, I argue that a primary and overlooked explanation for the development and durability of gender-asymmetrical jus sanguinis citizenship law was the felt need of judges, administrators, and legislators to further the racially nativist policies5 that were central to American nationality law until 1965.6 At formative moments in the development of American nationality law, gender- and marriage-based domestic relations laws7 were enlisted by administrators, judges, and legislators to deny the citizenship claims of nonwhite children, especially those who were excludable under the race-based immigration and naturalization laws.
Although the statutes governing parent-child citizenship transmission were facially race neutral, the practices and legal regulation of family formation and recognition were not. Once incorporated into jus sanguinis citizenship law by judges, administrators, and legislators these racialized domestic relations law principles could be, and regularly were, used to exclude nonwhite children from citizenship. In some instances, these racialized practices were explicit as administrators and legislators incorporated race-based domestic relations laws governing marriage and legitimacy into jus sanguinis citizenship law.8 In other instances the practices were race salient, in that officials used restrictive conceptions of marriage and legitimacy in cases involving jus sanguinis citizenship claims of nonwhite children.9 Regardless of the particular means by which citizenship transmission between American fathers and their nonmarital foreign-born children was restricted, it is clear that gender-based domestic relations law principles incorporated into jus sanguinis citizenship law served a larger racially nativist nation-building project.10 And they did so in a very literal way: by determining which citizens’ children would be recognized as citizens, they helped regulate the actual reproduction11—and racial composition—of the citizenry. By focusing on the citizenship status of children,12 this history makes visible, in granular detail, the means by which laws regulating birth status—long used to create and maintain racial social and legal hierarchies within the American polity13—were regularly used to shape the racial composition of the polity as well.
My account begins in Part I with a little-studied but influential case decided by the Maryland Court of Appeals in 1864, Guyer v. Smith.14 In Guyer the court denied the citizenship claims of two brothers born in St. Barthélemy. The Guyer brothers’ American father was white, but their mother was reportedly “of African descent.” The jus sanguinis citizenship statute then in effect recognized as citizens foreign-born “children of persons who . . . are . . . citizens of the United States.”15 The statute was silent regarding the marital status of the parents, but the Guyer court declared that foreign-born illegitimate children of American fathers were not citizens under the statute. The Guyer court said very little about race, but even as the legal substructure of slavery was crumbling, it silently incorporated into citizenship law a set of domestic relations law principles that had been instrumental to the maintenance of slavery and the denial of citizenship for persons of African descent: laws that recognized the unmarried mother as the source of status for her children, including slave status.16
The Guyer case is a crucial starting point for any thorough examination of the evolution of jus sanguinis principles as applied to the citizenship claims of nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers.17 As shown in Part II, Guyer’slegacy was long and impressive, as the opinion became part of the legal lexicon of American citizenship and empire over the course of the nineteenth and into the early twentieth century. The interpretive rule that nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers were not citizens figured prominently in administrative decisions concerning the citizenship status of Samoan-born children of American fathers18 and was also deployed in efforts to enforce race-based exclusion statutes—the laws that barred the entry of Chinese, and eventually all Asians, into the United States.19 The Guyer rule20 thus served as an important resource for judges and administrators, who were regularly called on to interpret the jus sanguinis citizenship statute in the course of administering racially restrictive immigration laws.
The jus sanguinis citizenship statute, although modified several times, remained silent on the question of nonmarital children’s citizenship21 until 1940, when Congress codified a modernized version of the Guyer rule by continuing the default exclusion of nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers.22 Part III tells the story of how and why pre-1940 judicial and administrative rulings concerning the citizenship of nonmarital children became the basis of the Nationality Act’s jus sanguinis provision—a provision that, in its basic contours, survives to this day. It then turns to the implementation of the jus sanguinis statute during the U.S. military’s multi-decade tour of duty in Europe and Asia. In these theaters of war, the jus sanguinis citizenship laws operated in tandem with race-based immigration laws and race-based military marriage policies to exclude Amerasian children from citizenship.23 In sum, well into the twentieth century, officials charged with policing membership in the American polity consistently relied on the gender- and marriage-based regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship to help enforce racially nativist nationality policies.
The fact that, during significant periods of American history, nationality law was designed and implemented in ways that served racially nativist objectives is not news, nor is the fact that many of the laws used to achieve those objectives were facially race neutral.24 What is distinctive about the account of jus sanguinis citizenship provided here is the particular legal technology that was enlisted in the service of a nativist agenda: durable but pliable gender-based domestic relations law principles.25 In this regard, this detailed history of jus sanguinis citizenship contributes to a growing body of literature that examines the important roles nationality law played in nation-building and in the development of the administrative state by examining the central role that family law played in those processes. As others have demonstrated, much of the administrative apparatus developed to implement the increasingly elaborate body of federal nationality law in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century was built up in the service of a nativist agenda.26 The history of jus sanguinis citizenship law demonstrates that laws governing marriage and birth status served this agenda as well, and they did so by providing officials with an exclusionary tool that appeared both natural and race neutral in the lines it drew between citizen and noncitizen.27
For some students of American nationality law, the importance of this account lies not in its historiographical significance, but in what it may mean for how we reason about the continued vitality of gender-asymmetrical jus sanguinis citizenship law today. Standing alone, history cannot resolve modern citizenship debates, but it can provide critical perspective on those debates, a project I undertake in Part IV. It can do so, first, by alerting us to the ways that gender- and marriage-based jus sanguinis principles continue to function in a race-salient manner in the practice and politics of American citizenship law.28 Second, it challenges the view that gender-asymmetrical jus sanguinis citizenship laws reflect natural and “biologically inevitable”29 means of regulating parent-child derivative citizenship—an understanding that has been developed and embraced by government attorneys and the Supreme Court in litigation challenging the constitutionality of gender-based regulation of derivative citizenship today.30 The genealogy of jus sanguinis citizenship provided here reveals, instead, that those laws are the product of choices made by legal actors at formative moments in the development of American nationality law, and acting under various institutional and ideological pressures. Far from “inevitable,” those choices were shaped by contemporary norms and mores concerning gender, parental roles, sexuality, and—as I demonstrate in great detail—the official imperative to enforce race-based nationality laws. To speak of these laws as inevitable thus obscures their origins and elides the ways that they continue to play an illiberal role in the practices and politics of citizenship today.
I. personal status laws, citizenship, and the civil war
The Nationality Act of 1940 was the first statute to explicitly regulate the citizenship of nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers or fathers. But the differential treatment of foreign-born children based on the gender of their citizen-parent predated the Nationality Act by at least a century and a half.31 For children born outside of marriage, that gender-asymmetrical system can be traced to Guyer v. Smith, an 1864 Maryland Court of Appeals decision.32 Guyer established the centrality of marriage as a requirement for patrilineal citizenship transmission. But the Guyer case was also about racial limitations on father-child citizenship transmission. The Guyer opinion—written during the Civil War by judges sitting in Maryland, the “middle ground” of slavery—incorporated a set of gendered and racialized domestic relations law principles concerning the status of nonmarital children. The Guyer opinion then served as an important and long-lasting resource for jurists, administrators, and lawmakers who interpreted, enforced, and enacted America’s racially nativist nationality laws.
A. Guyer v. Smith
At first blush, Guyer appears to be an unlikely precedent for the interpretation of federal citizenship law, as it was a state court case and did not involve anyone’s right to enter or remain in the United States. Rather, Guyer was a legal dispute over the ownership of a fifty-acre parcel of property in Allegany County, Maryland. John Guyer, an American citizen, had purchased the property in 1792. Approximately eight years later Guyer left Maryland and the United States, and eventually took up residence in St. Barthélemy.33 John Guyer died in 1841, devising the property to his two sons, Benjamin and James.34 In the 1850s, the sons’ ownership was called into question in an ejectment proceeding: George Smith and Israel Thompson asserted ownership over the parcel after they secured an escheat patent—a legal document that allowed Maryland to expropriate the property and sell it, in this case to Smith and Thompson.35
The problem, as Guyer’s lessee either knew or soon learned, and as Smith and Thompson may very well have known, was that John Guyer’s sons had fragile claims to American citizenship and hence to the property itself. In the nineteenth century, in many states—including Maryland—one’s property rights were partially contingent on one’s citizenship status.36 Under Maryland law, non-citizens could own land, but they could take land only as “purchasers,” a term of art that meant that their land was always subject to escheat.37
Thus, a central question in Guyer v. Smith was whether the Guyer brothers were American citizens. They were born in St. Barthélemy, at the time a Swedish colony; hence, no argument was made that they were citizens via the doctrine of jus soli. No one suggested that they had been naturalized.38 Rather, they claimed to be citizens by virtue of an 1802 federal statute that provided that
the children of persons who now are, or have been citizens of the United States, shall, though born out of the limits and jurisdiction of the United States, be considered as citizens of the United States: Provided, that the right of citizenship shall not descend to persons whose fathers have never resided within the United States.39
On the face of it, the assertion that the Guyer brothers were American citizens looked probable. After all, their father, John Guyer, had been a citizen and had, in fact, resided in the United States, as required by the 1802 Act. No one denied that James and Benjamin were his children. Thus, the attorney for the Guyer brothers’ lessee, Thomas McKaig—a respected Maryland attorney and former state senator—argued that the Guyer brothers were citizens under the 1802 statute, and that the state had no right to escheat their property, by then called Yamland.40 But McKaig did not argue the point forcefully, perhaps for good reason. Testimony offered into evidence revealed that Benjamin’s and James’s mother, Margaret, was of “African descent.”41
With this fact in mind, it is notable that the Guyer brothers or their lessee chose to pursue the matter for six years and bear the expense of an appeal. After all, in Dred Scott v. Sandford, decided just one year before the Guyer case was filed, Chief Justice Taney made clear that persons of African descent could not be citizens of the national polity by any means.42 Dred Scott had not been overruled by 1864, when the Maryland Court of Appeals decided Guyer, and it would seem that the appellees had a strong argument thatthe Guyer brothers were ineligible for citizenship simply because of their race. That argument was undoubtedly cognizable, as other officials confronted with similar claims around the same time had reasoned along similar lines when interpreting the jus sanguinis statute. For example, in the 1860s, an American consul in China had relied on Dred Scott to resolve the citizenship claim of the son of an American “negro” father. The son was born in Amoy, China before the Civil War. When the American consul was asked to determine the son’s citizenship, he concluded that “as the Dred Scott decision before the war had deprived negroes of their rights as citizens, . . . the ban of that decree” barred the son’s claim to American citizenship under the jus sanguinis statute.43 But in the Guyer appeal, that argument was not made.
Even more curious than the plaintiffs’ persistence in pursuing Yamland is the relatively minor role that race played in the defendants’ arguments. Attorneys for Smith and Thompson—Oliver Miller and Thomas Devecmon—certainly did not hesitate to bring the matter to the attention of the Court of Appeals, noting that “[s]he, (their mother[]) . . . is not of pure white blood, but partly of African blood or descent.”44 They also contended that under Maryland property law, the Guyer brothers’ racial status should have weighed in the defendants’ favor:
These plaintiffs are not only aliens, but are proved to be of African descent, and it is against the policy of our laws that such persons should hold real estate in Maryland, and the rule, therefore, that an alien cannot bring an action to recover this land, should be rigidly enforced against these parties.45
But the available documents suggest that Miller and Devecmon did not argue that the Guyer brothers’ claim to citizenship under the federal statute was categorically barred because of their race.46 They also said nothing about Dred Scott, which was still technically good law, even though it would seem to have provided extremely powerful precedent, and a possibly winning argument.
Court of Appeals Judge James Bartol, the author of the opinion, appears to have been equally hesitant to make much of the Guyer brothers’ race. He does not mention Dred Scott in the opinion, even though he might have been able to resolve the entire case in short order by doing so. Instead, in dealing with the question of the Guyer brothers’ citizenship, he simply declared that illegitimatechildren did not have the benefit of the 1802 federal law:
These appellants claim the benefit of that section, as the children of John Guyer, who was a citizen of the United States. But the proof shows that they were not born in lawful wedlock, they are therefore illegitimate; under our law nullius filii, and clearly therefore not within the provisions of the Act of 1802.47
The “proof” to which Judge Bartol referred was the sole witness’s statement that “[h]e cannot say whether the father and mother of the plaintiffs were lawfully man and wife, or whether the said children were born in lawful wedlock. To the best of my belief it was not so.”48
It is impossible to establish with certainty why the Maryland Court of Appeals did not also, or simply, rely on Dred Scott to determine the Guyer brothers’ citizenship, but one can engage in informed speculation based on the specific circumstances surrounding the Guyer litigation. Dred Scott was not formally overruled until the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified in 1868. But in November 1864, fifteen days before the court issued its opinion in Guyer, Maryland adopted a new state constitution that abolished slavery and declared that “all men are created equally free”49—a proclamation that may have offered a symbolic challenge to the validity of the Dred Scott opinion.50 This is not to suggest that the many questions regarding black people’s status in the United States—or in Maryland—had been resolved by the time Guyer was decided; far from it. The Civil War was not yet over, and even if Union forces prevailed it was not clear what that victory would mean for black people. However, it is quite possible that, because of these uncertainties and the violent, nation-rending upheaval that questions concerning black people’s citizenship had precipitated, the Guyer court turned to domestic relations laws—laws that were facially race neutral but palpably race salient in their operation—to determine the Guyer brothers’ claims to citizenship.
B. Domestic Relations Law and the Legal Construction of Race
Judge Bartol’s reference to the domestic relations law principles governing the status and rights of nonmarital children was summary in nature, possibly because his readers would have been familiar with the rudimentary legal principles on which he relied. In the nineteenth century, the common law of domestic relations differentiated sharply between marital and nonmarital children. Within marriage, the father had custodial rights over his children, as well as rights to their labor. In return, so to speak, the father was required to support his marital children, and they inherited his name, status, property, and domicile.51 Mothers had no, or very few, legal rights vis-à-vis their marital children.52 But outside marriage, the opposite pattern prevailed. The putative father’s estate and status did not pass to his “natural child” unless he adopted the child as his own—a measure that was left to the father’s discretion and in the nineteenth century was generally limited to situations where the father married the child’s mother after the birth of the child.53 By contrast, although the strict common law originally prevented the nonmarital child from inheriting property or status from or through his mother, by the early nineteenth century many states had moderated this rule by statute, so that nonmarital children could often inherit from their mothers, and mothers had a duty to support such children.54 As it developed in America, then, domestic relations law established default rules that enabled patrilineal property and status transmission in marriage and matrilineal property and status transmission outside marriage. The Guyer court incorporated these well-known principles of nineteenth-century domestic relations law into federal citizenship law.
The system of sexual ethics and racial status that these domestic relations law principles reproduced was also well known. Under these principles, women of all races bore responsibility for, and the social stigma of, children born out of wedlock.55 In addition—and crucial to understanding the Guyer case—the gender-based bastardy laws on which Judge Bartol drew had long shaped and sustained the practice of slavery in slave states like Maryland. Although the line between slavery and freedom was demarcated in different ways at different times, the principle that the bastard child’s status was determined by the condition of the mother frequently functioned to differentiate blacks from whites and free blacks from slaves, and it effectively ensured that the children of slave mothers and white fathers (often masters) were slaves.56 Moreover, given the prohibitions—both legal and social—on slave marriage,57 a rule that recognized the maternal line as the source of personal status for nonmarital children meant that children of female slaves were almost always born slaves, regardless of their father’s status, and, in most cases, his race. Even in states that determined racial status based on a drop or percentage of “African blood,” that rule was often based on the maternal line.
For example, in Daniel v. Guy, an Arkansas case, a woman sued for her freedom claiming that she was white, and hence not a slave. The Arkansas Supreme Court adopted a maternal descent rule for determining blackness: “a one-drop-of-blood rule,” as long as that drop passed through the maternal line.58 Similarly, in the canonical slave law case Hudgins v. Wrights, the Supreme Court of Appeals of Virginia explained that “by the uniform declaration of our laws, the descendants of the females remain slaves, to this day, unless they can prove a right to freedom, by actual emancipation, or by descent in the maternal line from an emancipated female.”59Maryland was no exception to this rule, which jurists traced to both common law and Roman law principles.60 Given the ubiquity of this rule, it is unsurprising that when son-of-Maryland Chief Justice Taney set out slavery’s long pedigree in his Dred Scott opinion, he explained that in the Roman Empire slave status “was decided by the condition of the mother,” and quoted the Institutes of Justinian to show that slaves had long been “born such of bondwomen.”61
These basic principles of domestic relations law—that within marriage the status of children followed that of the father, while outside marriage the status of children followed that of the mother—were deeply embedded in the logic and practice of slavery and were a fundamental component of the laws that constructed race as a sociolegal category in the antebellum South. They were frequently used to help determine the racial status of mixed-ancestry individuals—that is, whether that individual would be classified by law as black or white or some other race.62 Importantly for present purposes, these principles were also instrumental to how nineteenth-century jurists reasoned about black people’s exclusion from citizenship. When Chief Justice Taney wrote in Dred Scott that slave status was “decided by the condition of the mother,” he was explaining not only why black people were enslaved, but also why they were not citizens.63 And when the Maryland Court of Appeals was asked to determine the citizenship of Benjamin and James Guyer, it drew on the very same domestic relations law principles to provide an interpretation of the statute governing jus sanguinis citizenship, and to explain why the Guyer brothers were not citizens. Thus, although the opinion does not rely on the Guyerbrothers’ race as justification for their exclusion from citizenship, the laws governing racial identity and status operated just below the surface of the opinion. By turning to domestic relations laws, the Maryland Court of Appeals was able to determine the Guyer brothers’ citizenship without more than passing reference to their race, with no mention of Dred Scott, with no mention of the violent unwinding of slavery that served as the backdrop of the Guyer appeal, and with no mention of the promises of racial equality that Union victory would have signaled at least to some people. However present the race question—and, in particular, the question of black people’s citizenship—was in the everyday lives of those involved in the Guyer case, to those reading the opinion today, the racial content and context of the case barely register.
II. guyer’s legacy
But who reads Guyer v. Smith today? Who, other than the parties affected, ever read Guyer? After all, less than a year after the Maryland Court of Appeals decided Guyer, the Civil War was over, and in short order Congress enacted the 1866 Civil Rights Act, which provided that “all persons born in the United States and not subject to any foreign power, excluding Indians not taxed, are . . . citizens of the United States.”64 Two years after that, the Fourteenth Amendment constitutionalized jus soli citizenship (“the right of the place”), which largely put an end to the struggle over freedmen’s formal citizenship status—although contests over freedmen’s rights as citizens surely continued.65 And in 1870, Congress made naturalization available to people of “African nativity.”66 Seen in this light, Guyer would seem to be a relic of a bygone moment, and of a repudiated understanding of American citizenship.
But Guyer lived on and continued to function as a tool of racial exclusion in the practice of American jus sanguinis citizenship. The opinion was relied on by government attorneys, cited in judicial opinions, debated in intra- and inter-departmental administrative memoranda, and enforced by various government agencies.67 It was discussed in treaties, in articles, and in an important Attorney General Opinion issued in 1920.68 In these sundry sources and contexts, Guyer’sprimary holding—the interpretive rule that nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers were not citizens—was regularly given its strictest, most exclusionary application in cases involving nonwhite children, and therefore had the tendency to exclude such children from the American polity.69 However, the racialized origins and operation of the Guyer opinion were omitted from accounts of the case. In the hands of administrators, judges, and legal scholars who regularly worked with and interpreted American nationality laws, Guyer—and the ostensibly race-neutral domestic relations law principles for which it stood—thus provided a useful resource for those who sought to enforce racially nativist nationality policies. As I demonstrate in the Sections that follow, it was useful in part because its racialized operation was frequently obscured.
A. A Primer on Racially Nativist and Gender-Based Nationality Laws
Well into the twentieth century, the Fourteenth Amendment notwithstanding, other formal rules that governed membership in the American polity—such as immigration and naturalization laws—were shaped in significant ways by racial nativism.Perhaps the best known chapter in that story is the categorical exclusion of people of Asian descent, starting with the Chinese, from the late nineteenth through the mid-twentieth century. On the state level, efforts to expel and exclude people of Chinese descent began as early as the 1850s, when the California legislature began enacting laws intended to discourage the immigration—and encourage the emigration—of Chinese laborers who had flocked to California in search of work during the gold rush.70 Federal exclusion of Chinese people began in the late nineteenth century, first with the Page Law of 1875 and next with the Chinese Exclusion Act of 1882, which suspended immigration of Chinese laborers for a period of ten years and also declared that “no State Court or Court of the United States shall admit Chinese to Citizenship.”71
Exclusion laws barring the entry of Chinese and other Asian people were expanded over the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, culminating in the National Origins Act of 1924, which both re-codified the race-based exclusion laws and created a national origins quota system that would remain in place for three decades.72 Through this exclusionary legislation and related administrative regulations and judicial rulings, federal officials constructed a body of nationality law that was premised on a firm belief in a natural racial hierarchy: white Anglo-Saxon Protestant immigrants were welcomed, southern and eastern Europeans were allowed to enter in limited numbers, and Asians and most people of African descent likely to immigrate were excluded.73 The belief in a hierarchy of races also informed the federal government’s response to questions concerning the citizenship status of indigenous residents of America’s “insular territories”—places like Guam, Puerto Rico, and the Philippines—which were controlled by the United States but were not given statehood or a path to statehood.74
In addition to explicitly race-based nationality laws, gender-asymmetrical domestic relations law principles were incorporated into U.S. nationality law in order to resolve various conundrums created by mixed-nationality marriages, almost always in ways that compromised American women’s citizenship status. Starting in 1855, Congress incorporated the gender-based principle of “marital unity”—the notion that “the husband and wife are one person in law” and the “legal existence of the woman is suspended during the marriage”75—into nationality law by decreeing that when a foreign woman married an American man, she automatically became an American citizen.76 However, the converse was not true: an American woman who married a foreign man could not secure citizenship for her husband. Indeed, starting with an influential federal appeals court opinion in 1883,77 the principle of “marital unity” and women’s subordinate and dependent status in marriage translated into laws that stripped American women of their citizenship upon marriage to a foreigner. Congress codified that principle in the Expatriation Act of 1907, and thereby preserved the doctrine of coverture in federal citizenship law.78
By design, the race- and gender-based principles that informed the core functions of American nationality law often operated together. For example, the benefits of the 1855 citizenship law that automatically bestowed American citizenship on the non-citizen wife of an American man were limited to foreign women who “might lawfully be naturalized”—thus restricting naturalization-by-marriage to white women, since at that time only white people could naturalize.79 Moreover, although all American women were expatriated upon marriage to a foreign man under the Expatriation Act of 1907, when that law was partially repealed by the Cable Act of 1922, lawmakers purposefully left intact formal race-based restrictions on married women’s citizenship rights by continuing to expatriate American women who married foreign men who were “ineligible to citizenship.”80 In 1922, that category included men of Asian descent, thus confirming the continued expatriation of all American women, whatever their individual racial identity, who married a non-citizen Asian man.81
The principle of “marital unity” and racially exclusionary immigration laws—operating separately and in conjunction—not only shaped the citizenship rights of men and women who entered mixed-nationality marriages, but also helped determine the rights of children under American nationality law. Within marriage, until 1934, jus sanguinis citizenship followed the male line: the foreign-born children of American fathers, but not mothers, were recognized as citizens.82 This patrilineal rule conformed to the principle of coverture and the related understanding that fathers determined the national culture and political allegiance of their children, in addition to that of their wives.83 Even after 1931, when Congress recognized American women’s right to retain their citizenship upon marriage to a non-citizen, regardless of his race,84 women’s organizations had to fight several more years to secure citizenship for American women’s foreign-born children. In 1934, married American mothers could, for the first time, secure citizenship for their foreign-born children, although after 1940 their ability to do so was more constrained than that of married American fathers.85
But what about children who were born outside marriage? Until 1940, this issue was not addressed by the jus sanguinis statute. As I demonstrate in detail below, however, their citizenship status was determined by a body of judge- and administrator-made gender-asymmetrical standards. Starting in the early twentieth century, administrators in the Department of State and the Bureau of Immigration recognized the nonmarital foreign-born child of an American mother as an American citizen (before the jus sanguinis statute provided for mother-child citizenship transmission).86 And, as a default rule, the nonmarital foreign-born child of an American father was not a citizen—the principle that the Maryland court established in Guyer. This rule was not race neutral, however. Just as we miss a crucial dimension of Guyer if we fail to understand the case as part of the larger contest over the citizenship status of black people in the mid-nineteenth century, we miss a crucial dimension of the development of gender-asymmetrical jus sanguinis citizenship law if we fail to account for the important ways that restriction of father-child citizenship transmission outside the marital family regularly operated to exclude nonwhite children from citizenship.
In the following two Sections, I support that core assertion by drawing on the historical records from two important periods in the history of American nationality law. First, I demonstrate how, in the late nineteenth century, domestic relations law served as an important tool for American officials who sought to limit the citizenship claims of “half-caste” children of American men living in Samoa, at that point the location of a small outpost in the fledgling American empire. Next, I examine the Guyer rule’s role as an instrument of exclusion in the enforcement of the infamous Chinese exclusion laws, as it provided a means by which Bureau of Immigration officials could limit the entry of foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers. By tracing the Guyer rule’s long legacy in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, I demonstrate that the gender- and marriage-based regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship was shaped by the logic of racial hierarchy and exclusion that informed American nationality law well into the twentieth century.
B. Guyer as a Rule of Empire
In the second half of the nineteenth century, as America’s international presence expanded, officials began to actively protect and define the contours of American citizenship in consular offices around the world: China, Puerto Rico, Samoa, the Philippines, Hawaii, Guam, and elsewhere. American expansion gave rise to all manner of legal puzzles, many of which were vetted in the Insular Cases.87 Likely the best-known of these issues was whether the indigenous residents of U.S. territories were American citizens, enjoying the full protection of the Constitution. In other words, did the Constitution follow the flag?88 The answer, although notoriously complicated, was generally understood to be no.89
Another, less well-documented concern of officials charged with tending to America’s interests abroad was the citizenship status of children born to American parents in the insular territories and in foreign countries. The United States’s presence abroad was not virtual; it was physical. In addition to military personnel, the United States sent ambassadors, consuls, commercial agents, and other civil servants and employees to foreign countries near and far to represent American interests and to spread American values.90 In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, the vast majority of those Americans abroad were men,91 and some of them had relationships with local women. Many of the children born of these unions, and their parents, were of the view that the child of an American father and a local woman was an American citizen. Given that the jus sanguinis citizenship statute appeared to recognize children of American fathers as citizens regardless of the fathers’ marital status, the children’s claims were, at the very least, grounded in the letter of the law. Moreover, some of these children claimed that their parents were married, a fact that would seem to guarantee the children’s status under any interpretation of the statute.
But the citizenship claims asserted by children of American fathers and local women were not generally given the benefit of the jus sanguinis citizenship statute, as the case of Samoan-born children of American fathers illustrates. Officials evaluating these children’s claims not only presumed that a child must be legitimate in order to qualify for American citizenship but also employed a definition of marriage that denied the legality of marriages that American men entered into “beyond Christendom”—marriages that frequently involved interracial unions. The children born of those unions were illegitimate and hence not citizens.
1. Samoa and “an Institution of Our Civilization”
The first American commercial agent arrived in Samoa in 1853, joining Calvinist, Methodist, and Catholic missionaries who had settled there in the 1830s, along with English and German traders and officials.92 For several decades, Samoa remained a relatively sleepy way station, but in the 1870s, with an eye toward “increasing our commercial relations” in the South Pacific, President Grant appointed Albert Barnes Steinberger as a special agent with instructions “to secure more reliable information in reference” to Samoa.93 Steinberger’s report, written in the style of Victorian ethnography, catalogued the flora and fauna of the islands and the language, religion, and customs of the people, including their marriage rituals and practices. “Polygamy,” he explained, “is common on the part of men, never on the part of women, though two wives seldom live in the same house. A plurality of wives is not common, a husband usually sending a wife to her people when he takes to himself a new one.”94 Missionaries tried to eradicate the practice of polygamy in Samoa. Their influence is evident in a provision in the Samoan council’s 1873 laws that—as reported by Steinberger to Congress—declared that “[p]olygamy is strictly forbidden” and criminalized the practice with a penalty of two years’ hard labor for the guilty parties and a hundred-dollar fine for the husband.95 One suspects that the 1873 law and other bans on polygamy were directed not only at native Samoans but also at the western men living in Samoa. One of the first American commercial agents in Samoa, Jonas Coe, married at least six Samoan women and fathered at least eighteen children.96 And Albert Steinberger became intimately involved with Coe’s famously beautiful daughter Emma Coe, who was the second child of Coe’s first wife.97
Eventually, questions concerning the citizenship of the Samoan-born children of American fathers made their way to Washington, D.C. In 1887, Assistant Secretary of State George Rives received an inquiry from Harold Marsh Sewall, the American Consul General in Samoa. Soon after taking up his post, Sewall had received an inquiry from one “A[viga] Chapin, who ha[d] applied for protection as a citizen of the United States.”98 Aviga Chapin was the adult son of an American man, Virginius P. Chapin, and an unnamed “native woman.”99 The elder Chapin had served as the commercial agent of the United States in Samoa from 1853 to 1854, and he remained in Samoa for some time thereafter operating a private partnership.100 Sewall explained that, upon his departure, Virginius had left Aviga in the charge of a British man, George Pritchard, who “states that [Aviga] has always claimed American protection.”101 Nevertheless, Sewall had “refused [the younger] Chapin’s application” for citizenship, but was uncertain enough about the matter that he requested “instructions not only upon [Chapin’s] case” but also “the status of men who, like him, are the children of American fathers by Samoan women.”102 Sewall advised his superior that his own “opinion is strongly in favor of restricting this recognition [of the children of Samoan mothers and American fathers] as much as possible.”103
The response from Assistant Secretary of State Rives was as telling for what it assumed as for what it made explicit. After setting out the facts, Rives immediately began his analysis of the law governing the enforceability of foreign marriages in America. In so doing, he assumed that only marital foreign-born children of American fathers could claim American citizenship, even though the governing jus sanguinis citizenship statute said nothing about marital status.104 As a consequence, marriage was central to his analysis, and the important question was whether marriages between American men and Samoan women qualified as legal marriages, which would make the children born of those unions legitimate and citizens.
Rives’s answer was no, despite the “general principle of private international law that a marriage celebrated according to the requirements of the law of the place where the ceremony is performed is to be recognized as valid.”105 Rives explained that “this rule completely applies only to the countries of Christendom.”106 “In Mohammedan . . . or in uncivilized lands like Samoa . . . the privileged foreign residents carry with them their local law.”107 “It follows,” he continued,
that the custom of Samoa in regard to the lawful cohabitation of men and women can not be accepted as a rule by which to determine the character of the cohabitation of an American citizen with any woman, whether native or foreign. The character of such cohabitation must be decided by the law of the United States.108
With that in mind, Rives concluded that, “[v]iewed as an institution of our civilization,” a valid marriage contract “should be exclusive and for life. Cohabitation for a term of years or at will does not constitute a matrimonial alliance.”109
Relying on Steinberger’s 1874 report, Rives then observed that “[p]olygamy is common on the part of [Samoan] men”110 and concluded that “cohabitation ‘fa’a Samoa’ is neither exclusive nor for life and so fails to fulfill the essential conditions of marriage in the United States.”111 Given this, the children of American men and Samoan women were not American citizens. In Rives’s assessment, this conclusion applied to the claim of Aviga Chapin, despite the fact that Sewall had not stated with any clarity that Virginius Chapin’s relationship with the unnamed “native woman” was, in fact, polygamous. Indeed, in a further letter that was intended to clarify the standards that the Department of State would use in assessing the legitimacy of the “half-caste” children of American fathers residing in Samoa, Rives explained that no marriage between a Samoan woman and an American father could satisfy the American standard for legal marriage—“exclusive and for life”—because, regardless of the intent of the parents or the nature of their union, if Samoan law allowed the parties to separate, then such a marriage would not be recognized under American law.112 Under this interpretation, no child of an American father and a Samoan mother could be recognized as a citizen under the jus sanguinis citizenship statute.
2. Half-Castes, Polygamy, and the Presumption of Legitimacy
On the one hand, Rives’s analysis, and his insistence that “half-caste” children in Samoa were not American citizens, is hardly surprising. In the 1880s, many considered racial mixing a sin that posed a danger to the purity of the white race.113 In the United States, most of the states had laws barring interracial marriage, and the practice was socially taboo.114 Although Rives did not rely on such laws as the foundation of his opinion, a construction of the law of marriage that denied the legitimacy of marriages between white American men and Samoan women under any circumstances was consistent with prevailing legal and social norms of the time.
Rives’s ready assumption that all American-Samoan marriages were polygamous and his conclusion that polygamous marriages were invalid was also predictable given the ferocious anti-polygamy sentiment of the time. By the 1880s, the federal government had committed substantial resources to exorcising Mormon polygamy from the nation-state.115 In that campaign, Mormon polygamy was portrayed as a perversion of monogamous, Christian marriage.116 And polygamy’s routine identification with African and Asian peoples imbued the domestic anti-polygamy campaign with racial salience.117 For example, eight years before Rives rejected Chapin’s claim to citizenship, the Supreme Court upheld the federal government’s power to criminalize polygamy, explaining that polygamy was a practice of “Asiatic and . . . African people” that was “odious” to European nations.118 It was feared that Mormon polygamy was evidence of white people’s slippage into practices associated with supposedly lower-order races, and hence their racial denigration.119 American men’s alleged predilection toward polygamy in Samoa may have triggered a similar anxiety in officials charged with determining the citizenship claims of foreign-born children of American men residing in Samoa. If the government would not tolerate—or grant statehood to—a white, arguably Christian people who practiced polygamy within the geographical bounds of the United States, they surely would not welcome the offspring of possibly polygamous relationships between American men and Samoan women, born oceans away, into the American polity. In many respects, then, Rives’s analysis and conclusion seems to have been overdetermined by contemporary cultural and legal commitments against interracial marriage and polygamy.
But one should not overlook the relevant legal authorities and norms that pointed in the other direction. As an initial matter, it bears repeating that the governing jus sanguinis statute was silent regarding the father’s marital status.120 Moreover, not everyone thought that an interpretation of this statute that recognized nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers as citizens would have strained common sensibilities of the day. Significantly, Rives’s opinion effectively overruled an earlier practice that recognized the possibility of Samoan-American marriage and limited citizenship rights for “half-caste” children born of such unions.121 And just a few years before Rives penned his letter, an American diplomat stationed in China, John Russell Young, concluded that the illegitimacy of a “negro” American father’s foreign-born child was irrelevant to the Department of State’s determination of that child’s citizenship under the same jus sanguinis statute. Young based his reading of the statute on the guiding principle that “the misfortune of an illegitimate birth cannot deprive a man of his nationality. . . . He is a part of society.”122 In short, like the judges who presided in Guyer, Rives made an interpretive choice in reading the statute to limit citizenship to marital children of American fathers, and in determining that, regardless of the nature of the particular marriage, Samoan-American marriages did not constitute legal marriages.
Rives’s interpretation of the jus sanguinis statute also ignored one of the most fundamental principles of nineteenth-century marriage law. The legal maxim semper praesumitur pro matrimonio—always presume marriage—was a well-established and closely followed tenet of late nineteenth-century domestic relations law.123 Its influence was considerable, and, quite intentionally, it operated to legalize marriages and legitimize children in a whole range of circumstances. For example, as Rives surely knew, in most parts of the United States, common law marriage—“cohabitation for a term of years” combined with public recognition of the couple as husband and wife—constituted a lawful “matrimonial alliance.”124 Judges and lawyers acknowledged that a primary purpose of common law marriage was to ensure that children born of such a union were legitimate.125 In many states’ domestic relations laws, the child born to a couple who married after the child’s birth was deemed legitimate nunc pro tunc, from the day he or she was born.126 The presumption of legitimacy was so strong that even if adultery was suspected on the part of a married woman, any child she bore was assumed to be the child of her husband, subject only to strong contrary proof.127 Indeed, a whole body of evidentiary law supported the presumption in favor of marriage and legitimacy.128 In light of these strong norms, Rives’s determination that the marriages of American men and Samoan women were invalid—and the children illegitimate—denied those children the presumption of legitimacy that helped protect many children in America from the legal liabilities and profound social stigma of illegitimacy at that time.
But in domestic relations law, as in nationality law, there were racial limits on the operation of the presumptions of marriage and legitimacy. For example, the children of interracial couples did not benefit from legal presumptions that would have made them legitimate.129 One can see similar racialized understandings of the law of marriage and legitimacy operating in the citizenship determinations of Samoan-born children of American fathers that resulted in those children’s exclusion from membership in the American polity. The role that racialized domestic relations laws served in the hands of officials charged with making citizenship determinations was by no means identical to the ends they served in other contexts. Domestically, such laws reinforced sociolegal racial hierarchies by limiting nonwhite children’s access to the status and material benefits of legitimacy. In the context of interpreting the jus sanguinis statute, the non-recognition of marriages between American men and the “native women” of Samoa reflected anxieties of empire—the fear that America’s imperial project at the periphery would dilute or corrupt the polity at the center, in this case by recognizing “half-castes” as American citizens.130 But whether deployed at home or in the furthest reaches of America’s fledgling empire, malleable but durable domestic relations law principles aided in the racial construction of family and nation.
3. Presumptions and the Pliability of Domestic Relations Law
Not all foreign-born children of American fathers were denied the benefit of the presumption of legitimacy and other liberal rules of recognition that were common in nineteenth-century domestic relations law. Presumptions concerning marriage and legitimacy, along with a healthy dose of administrative discretion, were incorporated into citizenship law, allowing for selective determinations of legitimacy and citizenship status—determinations that were shaped by considerations of the children’s ethno-racial identity.
For example, contrast Rives’s insistence that, for purposes of determining the citizenship of foreign-born children of American fathers, the children must be born into a marriage that is “exclusive” and “for life” with the Department of State’s treatment of Louis Rover in 1901. Louis was the son of Léon Jean Rover, an American born in New York, and Germaine Rivère, a Frenchwoman.131 Louis was born out of wedlock in France in 1888, and his parents married three years later in London. Shortly afterward they legally parted and Louis remained with his mother.132 Confronted with Louis’s claim for citizenship, Department of State officials were uncertain how to proceed. Louis was born out of wedlock and therefore appeared to fall outside the jus sanguinis statute, which, as per Guyer, applied only to an American father’s marital children. On the other hand, Léon and Germaine eventually married, which may have “legitimated” Louis. Would such a child be counted as an American citizen?
One possibility for Department of State officials was to adopt a strict rule that could be applied easily by administrators charged with making citizenship determinations: all children born out of wedlock were illegitimate and hence could not take citizenship through their American fathers. Instead, Louis Rover’s case provided the occasion for the crystallization of an important exception to the Guyer rule: nonmarital foreign-born children who were “legitimated” by their American fathers would be recognized as American citizens. Rather than concluding that Rover was not a citizen under the jus sanguinis citizenship statute because he was born out of wedlock, Acting Secretary of State Alvey Adee took the initiative to write to the Attorney General of New York, John Davies, to inquire whether, under New York law, a child born out of wedlock was legitimized by his parents’ subsequent marriage. Relying on Davies’s assurance that, under New York law, Louis had been legitimized by his parents’ nuptials,133 the Department recognized Louis as a United States citizen.134 Louis’s parents had not been married when he was born, and it does not appear that Louis spent considerable time living in his father’s household. Yet Louis’s claim to American citizenship was granted. Semper praesumitur pro matrimonio.
As with the Guyer rule, the Department of State’s legitimation exception would become a standard interpretive gloss on the jus sanguinis citizenship statute.135 But it was often applied in a race-selective manner. For example, in the years just after the Rover case, the Department of State did not use the same generous interpretation of the laws of marriage and legitimacy in cases involving the foreign-born children of American men and Chinese women. Summarizing Department of State practice in his 1904 handbook titled Citizenship of the United States, Assistant Solicitor Frederick Van Dyne explained that “[i]llegitimate children born to a Chinese woman in China do not become American citizens by the subsequent marriage of the mother to a citizen of the United States.” Citing Guyer as the lead case, Van Dyne reasoned that “[i]llegitimate children follow the status of the mother, and the mother being Chinese, and not capable of being lawfully naturalized under the laws of the United States, her marriage to a citizen of the United States did not confer American citizenship on her.”136 Van Dyne’s account of the citizenship status of nonmarital children born to American fathers and Chinese mothers makes no suggestion that a child born to a Chinese mother could be legitimized by her marriage to the American father, and thus acquire citizenship through the father, though that rule had been followed just two years earlier in the Rover case.
Van Dyne’s assessment of the status of the nonmarital child of a Chinese-American union is just one example of how the law of marriage and legitimacy aided in the enforcement of the Chinese exclusion statutes, a subject I turn to in the next Section. Before doing so, however, it is worth observing that although the racial operation of domestic relations law principles in nationality law was often obscured, this was not always the case. A few years after Rives wrote his letter to the American consul in Samoa, John Bassett Moore, a towering figure in international law—and one-time secretary to the Conference on Samoan Affairs—reported and summarized the laws governing jus sanguinis citizenship. In his discussion of the citizenship status of nonmarital children, Moore cited Rives’s letter and comfortably declared that “[h]alf-castes born in Samoa, of American fathers by Samoan women, with whom the fathers lived ‘fa’a Samoa,’ are not citizens of the United States.”137 And in 1915, when Moore’s protégé Edwin Borchard wrote The Diplomatic Protection of Citizens Abroad, he reiterated and translated the conclusion of his mentor—“it seems clear that illegitimate half-castes born in semi-barbarous countries of American fathers and native women are not American citizens”—citing Guyer v. Smith.138
C. Guyer as a Rule of Exclusion
[T]he question of [jus sanguinis] citizenship, as it exists in Chinese cases, rarely became the problem of any other nationality.139
–Wen-Hsien Chen (1940)
In the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, the pressing questions of nationality law involved the status of persons of Chinese descent and others from the “Asiatic zone.”140 In this fiercely anti-Asian context, exclusionists vigorously challenged the citizenship status of American-born individuals of Chinese descent, and immigration officials attempted to use the exclusion laws to bar the entry of American-born citizens of Chinese descent returning from sojourns abroad.141 But for the Supreme Court’s 1898 intervention in Wong Kim Ark,which established that the Citizenship Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment applied to native-born Chinese American citizens, the exclusionists would likely have succeeded in ensuring Chinese Americans’ exclusion from the United States.142 Unable to categorically exclude native-born Chinese Americans from the United States, exclusionists made a concerted effort to limit jus sanguinis as a route to citizenship for the foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers.143 These efforts were part of a larger process by which Chinese American citizens were marked as “alien citizens”—persons who, although “born in the United States . . . remained alien in the eyes of the nation.”144 They were also part of an effort to maintain the purity and predominance of the white race in the United States.145 This Section examines how the Bureau of Immigration embraced the Guyer rule in service of the racial exclusion laws.
1. Chinese American Fathers and Jus Sanguinis Citizenship
For a whole host of reasons—including the illegality of interracial marriage and the severe gender imbalance in the ethnic Chinese population in America—it was not uncommon for a Chinese American man to marry a Chinese woman who remained in China while he traveled back to the United States.146 Those couples had children, born in China, and the citizenship status of those children was an important, and vexing, question for the Bureau of Immigration. The Bureau was clearly concerned about fraud, and there is substantial evidence that fraudulent claims to a filial relationship with a Chinese American father had become a common way of evading the harsh exclusion laws.147 But the Bureau’s obsessive effort to restrict the transmission of citizenship between Chinese American fathers and their foreign-born children was not only animated by worry about fraud; it was animated by a racial xenophobia that characterized the exclusion laws more generally. In his 1916 annual report to the Secretary of Labor, for example, Commissioner General of Immigration Anthony Caminetti lamented the recognition of foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers under the jus sanguinis citizenship statute. Caminetti objected to the fact that American-born individuals of Chinese descent were birthright citizens under the Fourteenth Amendment’s Citizenship Clause, and found it even more troubling that their foreign-born children could be considered citizens as well. Contending that “a person of the Mongolian race who is so fortunate as to be born here is vested by the ‘accident of birth’ with American citizenship,” Caminetti thought it a travesty that such an individual could go “to the native country of his parents and marry[] . . . and there beget[] children . . . [who] could come to the United States, [and] be freely admitted at our ports.”148
The jus sanguinis citizenship statute contained no racial limitations, however; it was, as we say today, facially race neutral. But consistent with its animosity toward jus sanguinis citizenship for children of Chinese descent, the Bureau of Immigration implemented policies and procedures limiting its availability for the foreign-born sons of Chinese American fathers.149 For example, in 1915 the Bureau issued a regulation stating that foreign-born male children of Chinese American fathers would be recognized as citizens only if they were found to be dependent members of the father’s household—a limitation that was not imposed on any other racial or ethnic group of American fathers seeking citizenship for their foreign-born children.150 But when that policy was challenged in federal court in California, where habeas petitions challenging Bureau rulings were often heard, the court refused to enforce the regulation, explaining that the statute did not make “race a distinction in American citizenship.”151
As an additional or alternative strategy for restricting the availability of jus sanguinis citizenship for the children of Chinese American fathers, the Bureau strictly applied the Guyer rule in an effort to exclude at least some foreign-born children of Chinese descent from citizenship. The question of legitimacy often arose in cases involving an individual whom immigration officials suspected to be the child of a Chinese American father’s second wife.152 The legal question confronting immigration officials and judges was whether the children of second wives were eligible for citizenship under a statute that provided that children “whose fathers were or shall be at the time of their birth citizens of the United States, shall be deemed . . . citizens” and that was silent on the marital status of the parents.153 Consistent with the interpretation given to the jus sanguinis statute in Guyer and the Samoan case, in cases involving the children of Chinese American fathers, the Bureau of Immigration insisted that the statute applied to marital children only—a category that did not include the children of polygamous (or allegedly polygamous) marriages.154 It also made good use of the Guyer rule in briefs and intra-office memoranda, relying on it to reject the possibility that the Department of State’s legitimation exception—established in the Rover case and formally ratified by the Department of Justice in 1920—could apply to the children of Chinese American fathers.
2. The Legitimation Exception and Polygamous “Stock-Farms”
Dismissing the legitimation exception to the Guyer rule was no small matter. Starting as early as 1901, the Department of State consistently recognized the legitimation exception, and in 1920 the Attorney General’s Office issued a lengthy formal opinion analyzing and approving it.155 Confronted with citizenship claims of three nonmarital sons of three different American fathers, Acting Attorney General Charles Bismarck Ames explained that “[t]he State Department has for many years held that a child born out of wedlock which, by the laws of its father’s domicile has been legitimated, is a citizen of the United States within the meaning of Revised Statutes, section 1993.”156 Expressly departing from the rigid rule announced in Guyer v. Smith, Ames endorsed the Department of State’s “legitimation exception” because “the recognition of the relationship of an illegitimate child to a father whose identity has been established . . . is no longer against public policy.”157 Underscoring that central point—and likely to the dismay of immigration officials—Ames added that “[t]here appear to be no considerations of public policy which require a different decision.”158 Notably, all of the three cases at issue in the Attorney General’s 1920 opinion involved children who were not racially excludable: Jacques Robert Smith, William Alonzo Oppenheimer, and Gustav Feuerbach.159
In the 1920s, Bureau of Immigration officials, charged with excluding all persons from the “Asiatic zone,” disagreed with the Attorney General’s assessment of the Department of State’s “legitimation exception.” In three cases brought during that decade, the children of Chinese American fathers sought the benefit of the Attorney General’s opinion.160 In each case, Bureau officials denied citizenship—and entry—to these Chinese-born children of Chinese American fathers because the officials found that the applicants were children of second wives, and therefore illegitimate and unable to claim citizenship through their fathers. In each case, the federal court of appeals affirmed.
Given the fever pitch of opposition to Asian immigration in the 1920s, it is unsurprising that the department charged with enforcing Chinese exclusion laws fully embraced the Guyer rule, repudiated the legitimation exception, and rejected these children’s claims to citizenship. Nevertheless, a closer examination of these cases helps underscore that, in the hands of administrative officials charged with gatekeeping for the American polity, domestic relations laws could be, and were, used to further the racially nativist policies of contemporary nationality law. They did so by enlisting a rigid understanding of marriage law that precluded any possibility of patrilineal status transmission outside marriage.
Take the case of Ng Suey Hi, who arrived in Seattle in 1926. She sought entry as an American citizen as the daughter of Ng Ock, whom Bureau lawyers described as a “native-born citizen of this country, of the Chinese race.”161 The precise basis for the Bureau’s initial refusal to recognize Ng Suey Hi’s claim to citizenship, and her right to enter the country, is not entirely clear from the record—it appears that the Bureau challenged almost every factual assertion underlying her claim to citizenship, with no success. But by the time the case was on appeal in the Ninth Circuit, the pivotal question had emerged: Was Ng Suey Hi “illegitimate,” and, if so, did that status defeat her claim to citizenship under the jus sanguinis citizenship statute?
Ng Suey Hi’s attorneys first insisted on a plain-text reading of the jus sanguinis citizenship statute; it did not matter whether their client was considered “illegitimate.” By the “express statement of the National Congress,” they argued, “the question of legitimacy or illegitimacy would seem to be entirely removed.”162 However, they would have been foolish to rest on that argument given the default rule that nonmarital children of American fathers were not citizens—a default rule that went unaltered by the 1920 Attorney General Opinion. Citing that opinion, Ng Suey Hi’s attorneys next argued that “a child born out of wedlock, in a foreign country, of an American father and an alien mother, and subsequently legitimated by acknowledgment by the father is a citizen of the United States within [the statute].”163 Noting that claims of legitimacy enjoy “the strongest presumptions known to law,” they observed that Ng Ock’s first wife had died, and hence Ng Suey Hi had been legitimated by her father’s continued marriage to her mother.164 “[T]he Federal Courts recognize common law marriage,” they explained, “and certainly in view of the death of the first wife a common law marriage to the second wife has been completely established.”165 Calling on Corpus Juris for support, they urged that “for the purpose of sustaining legitimacy, a marriage may be inferred from cohabitation, reputation, and other circumstances.”166 Even “the issues of null and void marriages have nevertheless been deemed to be legitimate,” they maintained, and “[t]he fact that a former subsisting marriage of one of the parties is the cause of its invalidity does not affect the operation of the rule.”167
The arguments made by Ng Suey Hi’s attorneys were not spurious given the strong presumption of legitimacy in American domestic relations law, and a growing trend to provide for and recognize paternal legitimation of nonmarital children.168 Even attorneys for the Bureau conceded that “the general rule is that the validity of a marriage is determined by the law of the place where it is contracted,”169 and acknowledged that the term “children” “may include natural and illegitimate children.”170 Indeed, as is discussed below, the Bureau was willing to apply those general principles in an important citizenship case concerning the white foreign-born child of a polygamous marriage.171 However, in cases involving the children of Chinese American fathers, such as Ng Suey Hi, the Bureau leaned heavily on the Guyer rule and its rigid insistence on marriage as central to the determination of foreign-born children’s claims to citizenship through the father. Citing and paraphrasing Guyer, the Bureau insisted that “[i]llegitimate children, born abroad, of citizens, being nullius filii are not within the contemplation of [the statute].”172
But attorneys for the Bureau did not rest on doctrinal formalisms alone. Likely sensing that their reading of the law governing the status of nonmarital children was in tension with important strands of contemporary domestic relations law, and was definitely inconsistent with the Attorney General’s interpretation, they made very clear to the court what they believed was at stake in the case of Ng Suey Hi: the threat of mass reproduction of American citizens of Chinese descent. If the construction of the jus sanguinis statute proffered by the petitioner were correct, they warned, “there would be nothing to prevent American citizens of the Chinese race from going to China and establishing stock-farms, peopled with any desired number of polygamous wives, or concubines, for the intensive propagation of American citizens, and later bringing all the offspring of these various women to this country under that status.”173
The image of a “stock-farm” drew on multiple anxieties that animated the Chinese exclusion laws. Concern that Chinese women would become “breeders” for a new generation of Chinese Americans had helped give rise to exclusion laws and regulations that targeted Chinese women starting with the Page Act of 1875,174 as well as state anti-miscegenation laws that explicitly prohibited Asian-white marriages.175 By excluding Chinese women from the United States and attempting to limit the creation of mixed-race families, exclusionists tried to limit the number of American-born children of Chinese descent who would be citizens by virtue of the Fourteenth Amendment’s Citizenship Clause.176 In addition, the practice of polygamy was held up by exclusionists as a key reason for the complete exclusion of the Chinese from America, in part because polygamy was evidence of the Chinese women’s “slave-like mentality” and moral inferiority as a race, and hence their unsuitability for citizenship in a republic.177 The government’s reference to “stock-farms peopled with any number of wives, or concubines” drew on these powerful images—the fecundity of the Chinese and the polygamist wife as slave—to underscore the importance of the strict application of the Guyer rule in Ng Suey Hi’s case.
The judges of the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals did not overtly betray the same racial anxieties that animated the Bureau’s interpretation of the jus sanguinis statute and relevant domestic relations law. Rather, reasoning in a formalist, common law juridical mode, the Ng Suey Hi court adopted the Guyer rule, rejected the Department of State’s legitimation exception, and—in the alternative—embraced a constrained definition of legitimation. Paraphrasing the Guyer opinion, the court announced that “[i]llegitimate children, born abroad of citizens, being nullius filii, are not within the contemplation of section 1993 of the United States Revised Statutes, and hence are not themselves citizens,”178 thus rejecting the Department of State’s legitimation exception out of hand. Abandoning any and all of the presumptions of legitimacy that were part of the fabric of American domestic relations law, the court also reasoned that “at common law an illegitimate child could only be made legitimate by act of Parliament,” adding—incorrectly—that “such is the law in this country.”179 Thus, the court concluded, “there is no evidence of such legitimation in this case.”180
This pattern was repeated in two other precedent-setting cases that reached the federal courts of appeals in the late 1920s: Mason ex rel. Chin Suey v. Tillinghast181 and Louie Wah You v. Nagle.182 In both cases, attorneys for Chinese-born children of American citizen fathers drew on the long-standing presumption in domestic relations law that jurists were to presume marriage and legitimacy, as well as the liberalization of laws governing legitimation. But in both cases, as in Ng Suey Hi,the courts followed the Bureau’s lead, turning to a restrictive, explicitly Guyer-based interpretation of the citizenship statute and a narrow definition of marriage and legitimacy in order to deny the petitioners’ citizenship claims. On the statutory interpretation question, for example, in Chin Suey the First Circuit explicitly rejected the Department of State’s legitimation exception and instead ruled that “[t]he statute applies to legitimate children only, and no provision is made in it in regard to the citizenship of illegitimate children who may be thereafter legitimated by marriage,” citing Guyer v. Smith.183 The court also concluded, without elaboration, that “children of secondary wives are not legitimate, and therefore could not be born citizens of the United States, if born abroad, although the father was an American citizen.”184 This would be so, the court insisted, “even if the father and the secondary wife married after the death of the first wife,”185 a conclusion that ran counter to the law of many states, including Massachusetts (where the case arose), and was contrary to the presumption of legitimacy that was well established in American domestic relations law.186
In Louie Wah You, after the Bureau once again warned the court about polygamous “stock-farms,” the Ninth Circuit drew on a definition of legitimation that was impossible for the appellant to satisfy because of the race-based exclusion laws. Not only must the father publicly acknowledge his child, but he must also receive him into his household—“a settled place of habitation of which he is the head.”187 But, of course, Louie Wah You could not reside with his American citizen father unless he was permitted to enter the country, which he could not do as a person of Chinese descent.
In all three cases, the courts of appeals used the law of domestic relations, as it had been incorporated into citizenship law in the Guyer opinion, as a basis for denying the benefit of the jus sanguinis citizenship statute to the child of a Chinese American father. Of course, what was at issue in these three cases was not the niceties of the law of legitimation or the continued vitality of the presumption of legitimacy, but the race-based exclusion laws that the Bureau was charged with enforcing. Confronted with the citizenship claim of a foreign-born child of a Chinese American father, the Bureau rejected, resisted, and narrowed the legitimation exception that had been crafted to accommodate cases involving white nonmarital children. It did so using a malleable, race-salient understanding of marriage and legitimation. What Ng Suey Hi, Chin Suey, and Louie Wah You show in hindsight is how the Guyer rule—adopted by the Bureau of Immigration and affirmed in three court of appeals cases—was insinuated in the logic of the Asian exclusion laws that by the late 1920s had been a part of America’s immigration laws for over forty years.
3. Race, Polygamy, and Legitimacy
Now, one might resist this assertion on the ground that these cases provide less evidence of racial bias than of a moral objection to polygamy that would have determined their outcome regardless of the race of the would-be citizen. In light of the harsh efforts to exclude Mormon polygamists from the American polity,188 it is possible to read these three cases concerning the Chinese-born children of Chinese American fathers as evidence of an official policy of polygamist exclusion rather than racial exclusion. The records of the Bureau suggest, however, that immigration officials were far less rigid in their conception of “legitimacy” in cases involving foreign-born children of white American Mormons than in cases involving foreign-born children of Chinese Americans.189
Take, for example, the case of Leah Skousen O’Donnell. She was the daughter of a white Mormon father, Donald Skousen, who had emigrated from Utah to Colonia Juárez, Chihuahua, Mexico, as part of a mass exodus of Utah Mormons to Mexico to escape federal bans on, and criminalization of, polygamy.190 Donald was born in Utah and had been an American citizen until he voluntarily expatriated and naturalized as a Mexican citizen in the 1890s, several years before Leah was born.191 Leah’s mother, Sarah, also an American-born Mormon, was Donald’s “second wife.”192 By the time Leah’s citizenship was called into question by Bureau officials, Donald’s first wife was dead, and, immigration officials explained, “he is now living with the mother of [Leah,] with whom he went through a religious ceremony of marriage in the Mormon Church prior to his first wife’s death.”193 The Board of Review of the Bureau of Immigration concluded that Leah had been “legitimated” by the death of Donald’s first wife, and conceded that, as a legitimated child of an American father, Leah could have acquired citizenship from her father had he remained a U.S. citizen at the time of her birth. Because Donald had expatriated, the Board observed that she could “take nothing by reason of her alleged father’s citizenship because he is a citizen of Mexico.”194 But the assumption underlying the Board’s analysis is important: consistent with the law of many states, the death of a first wife served to legitimate the children of a bigamous or polygamous marriage, if the father and the mother continued to live together as husband and wife.195
That was, of course, precisely the argument that the Bureau and the federal appeals courts had rejected in Chin Suey’s and Ng Suey Hi’s cases, suggesting that antipathy for polygamy was not all that was at stake when Bureau officials interpreted the jus sanguinis citizenship statute in cases involving foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers.196 In the early twentieth century, polygamy’s salience as a threat to American identity continued to haunt questions of racial exclusion in immigration and citizenship law, not only because of Americans’ idealization of monogamous marriage, but also because polygamy stood as a central marker of the Chinese people’s racial identity and inferiority, and their ineligibility for citizenship. In the hands of Bureau of Immigration officials, the rigid enforcement of jus sanguinis citizenship principles, and the domestic relations law principles that had become part of American nationality law, provided a means of furthering the racial exclusionary policies that were at the core of the Bureau’s mission.
D. The Practice of Jus Sanguinis Citizenship
By the late 1920s, the basic contours of father-child derivative citizenship had been established in judicial and administrative interpretations of the federal jus sanguinis statute. In 1940, those interpretations were by and large codified in the Nationality Act—a statute that was drafted by administrators from the Bureau of Immigration, the Department of State, and the Department of Justice.197 Because the practices of early twentieth-century administrators became the basis of the first major nationality statute—and continue to provide the basic architecture for the modern parent-child derivative citizenship statute—it is worth briefly taking stock of the critical features of those interpretations.
With respect to the ability of fathers to secure citizenship for their foreign-born children, the core interpretive commitment of the Guyer opinion—that is, the common law inspired holding that only the marital children of American fathers were contemplated by the jus sanguinis citizenship statute—remained a vital and racially exclusionary principle from the late nineteenth century into the early twentieth century. The marriage requirement was racially exclusionary because marriage was not a race-neutral institution. Interracial marriage was illegal in many American states and was generally socially taboo. The marriage requirement was also racially exclusionary because administrators, who were given significant discretion in interpreting the jus sanguinis statute, tended to use what were, for that time, constrained definitions of marriage and legitimacy in cases involving citizenship claims of nonwhite children. In the early twentieth century, resistance to citizenship transmission from fathers to nonmarital children had begun to loosen from its strict common law origins, as evidenced by the Department of State’s development of an exception for “legitimated” children that was adopted and affirmed by the Attorney General in a formal opinion in 1920. However, in the hands of Bureau officials and federal judges, that exception was narrowly construed and even outright rejected in cases involving Chinese-born children who, unless they could claim citizenship through their American fathers, would be subject to the exclusion laws.
The story of the development of racialized jus sanguinis citizenship law also reveals a complex dialogue among jurists, administrators, and legislators. For example, the differing interpretations of Guyer offered by the Department and the Bureau appears to have tracked subtle but important institutional differences between the two agencies that routinely administered the jus sanguinis citizenship laws. The Department of State was the primary agency that dealt with the citizenship claims of foreign-born children of American citizens, as it was responsible for issuing passports for citizens, providing protection for citizens residing abroad, and registering foreign-born children of American citizens.198 But the foreign-born children of American citizens who were of an excludable racial-ethnic group, such as Chinese citizens and their children, were treated as foreigners, and hence were also subject to rigorous screening and, often, detention by the Bureau of Immigration, which oversaw and administered the Chinese exclusion laws.199 The fact that the Bureau remained especially committed to a strict enforcement of the Guyer rule was thus consistent with its central institutional mission of enforcing the racial exclusion laws.200
Courts also played an important role in the development of racialized jus sanguinis citizenship laws, often in dialogue with administrators. In Guyer, a Civil War-era case involving the citizenship status of two children of African descent, the Maryland Court of Appeals interpreted the jus sanguinis citizenship statute by including only marital children as citizens.201 Administrators in the Bureau of Immigration followed the same rule, often citing Guyer for authority. Gradually, administrators in the Department of State crafted a legitimation exception to the judge-made Guyer rule—an administrator-made exception to a judge-made exception—which the Bureau of Immigration and the circuit courts subsequently construed narrowly or rejected entirely in Ng Suey Hi, Chin Suey, and Louie Wah You. Through these interpretive processes, the exclusion of children on the basis of race-salient illegitimacy laws was engrained in judicial and administrative practice.
Why did administrators, government attorneys, and judges rely on domestic relations law to achieve nativist policy goals, rather than simply relying on racial classifications? This question is especially significant in light of the Supreme Court’s 1889 opinion in Chae Chan Ping v. United States (also known as the Chinese Exclusion Case), in which the Court proclaimed the political branches’ plenary power over immigration law.202 Someone intent on excluding the foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers could have argued that the political branches had the authority to exclude any person or any group—including the children of American citizens—for any reason, including race. At the time, however, there were doubts as to the legality and wisdom of explicit race-based restrictions on jus sanguinis citizenship. For example, the lower federal courts did not permit the Bureau of Immigration to read racial limitations into the jus sanguinis citizenship statute.203 Similarly, Congress did not alter the jus sanguinis statute to exclude children of citizens who were otherwise racially “ineligible to citizenship,” and there is evidence to suggest that many legislators had doubts about Congress’s authority to do so. For example, in the 1930s, legislators considered several bills that would have provided American women the right to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children.204 Responding to concerns that such equalization of parental citizenship rights would result in the admission of children who were racially excludable, a proviso was introduced that would have eliminated parent-child citizenship transmission when the alien parent was “ineligible to citizenship.”205 Some legislators argued that the exclusion of such children was intolerable race discrimination206—an argument that appears to have had some effect, as the racial restriction was eliminated from the final version of the 1934 act that recognized American mothers’ foreign-born children as citizens.207 Thus, even though legislators had the power to exclude non-citizens on the basis of race, and although the Fourteenth Amendment applied only to states, within Congress there was significant uncertainty concerning legislative power to use overt racial restrictions to exclude the children of citizen parents because such restrictions implicated those citizens’ rights.208 The Guyer rule provided officials who enforced the racial exclusion laws with an alternative means of limiting the reach of jus sanguinis citizenship in a manner that helped insure the integrity and efficacy of those laws.209
Domestic relations law, and particularly the law of marriage and illegitimacy, was particularly well suited to this task for several reasons. First, the Guyer rule was consistent with the long-standing notion that the husband, as head of the family, would determine the political and cultural character of the marital family.210 It was also consistent with the principle that illegitimate children were excluded from the father’s family, and that fathers had no rights with respect to children born outside of marriage—and, as a default matter, had no responsibilities.211 By the early twentieth century, these aging notions of the political and legal significance of marriage, gender, and legitimacy were incrementally waning. But the male-headed marital family remained a central sociolegal institution, and the Guyer rule helped sustain, and was sustained by, its continued authority.
Second, racially nativist nationality laws were well served by domestic relations laws because the practice of using gender-based domestic relations law as an instrument of racial designation, and often as a means of preserving racial hierarchies within American society, was entrenched in the practices of American jurists, lawyers, and administrators. Long before the Guyer brothers tried to secure their ownership of Yamland in war-torn Maryland, gender-based laws governing birth status had been woven into American law—both laws governing the rights and status of individuals in the United States, and laws determining their citizenship. Thus, the law of slavery incorporated the maternal line rule to determine the status—slave or free—of individuals born to at least one enslaved parent.212 In the context of citizenship law, gender- and marriage-based laws governing birth status had been incorporated into race-based American citizenship laws, as reflected in the Dred Scott opinion.213 Laws prohibiting interracial sex and marriage were written to preserve and protect white purity and supremacy, and hence it followed that the generous domestic relations law principles that worked to bring children within a marital family, such as legitimation laws, often did not apply to children of interracial unions.214 In short, to reason about foreign-born children’s citizenship status using racialized gender-asymmetrical principles of descent and status was a familiar exercise, and one that was easily incorporated into the interpretation of the jus sanguinis citizenship statute.
A third reason that the Guyer rule—in its common law and modernized formulations—functioned as an effective resource for various officials is the pliability of the domestic relations law principles it incorporated into citizenship determinations. One might reason that by using marriage and legitimacy as bases for allocating citizenship, officials simply selected pre-existing statuses as eligibility criteria. But in the context of nationality laws, government officials—judges, administrators, lawyers—did not simply employ pre-existing, singular notions of “marriage” and “legitimacy” as bases for making citizenship determinations of foreign-born children of American citizens. Rather, they sometimes borrowed, sometimes ignored, and often adapted domestic relations law principles from state law or general law sources, shaping the metes and bounds of marriage and the family in part in response to the pressure created by particular policy objectives of nationality law. In one case, administrators could recognize “legitimation” as a valid means by which some American fathers could secure citizenship for their nonmarital children, affirming those men’s prerogatives: fathers like Léon Rover, Edgar Smith, and Edward Oppenheimer could secure citizenship for their white nonmarital children.
In other cases, by employing a more rigid version of the Guyer rule, or by using a constrained definition of marriage, officials limited the reach of jus sanguinis citizenship. Such limitations on the transmission of citizenship from fathers to nonmarital children may have been experienced by some fathers as protecting their prerogatives (as was possibly the case for Virginius Chapin) and by others as violating their rights as fathers and as citizens (as was almost certainly the understanding of the Chinese American fathers whose children were refused entry in Ng Suey Hi, Chin Suey, and Louie Wah You).215 And, undoubtedly, officials made determinations regarding the father-child relationship in different cases for different reasons, but the very pliability of the definitions of marriage and legitimacy made them useful in the enforcement of various policy goals, including the nativist aspirations of American nationality laws of the time.
III. the guyer rule in the modern era of nationality law
One might anticipate the Guyer rule’s demise along with the gradual end of explicit race- and gender-based regulation of nationality during the middle decades of the twentieth century. In the 1920s and 1930s, American women’s organizations successfully lobbied Congress for repeal of many overt limitations on women’s citizenship rights.216 And, starting with the removal of Chinese from the long list of racially excludable peoples in 1943, Congress gradually purged immigration law of racial and national origins restrictions,217 ending outright racial bars to immigration in 1952 and abolishing the quota system in 1965.218
But sociolegal change rarely conforms to neat and tidy progress narratives,219 and it would be misguided to presume that the repudiation of many of the formal race- and gender-based classifications from nationality law signaled a complete departure from the concept of “marital unity” or racially nativist principles that by the mid-twentieth century had shaped American nationality law for over 150 years. In this Part, I show how the jus sanguinis provisions in the Nationality Act of 1940 codified many of the gendered and racialized practices of early twentieth-century administrators, including restrictions on citizenship transmission from fathers to their nonmarital children. I then turn to the application of the Nationality Act’s jus sanguinis citizenship provisions, demonstrating how the law continued to limit father-child citizenship transmission in a racialized manner into the late twentieth century, especially in theaters of war.
A. Modernizing and Codifying Guyer: The Drafting of the Nationality Act of 1940
The Nationality Act of 1940 was the first omnibus codification of American nationality law, providing the template for many of our current laws, but it has received surprisingly little attention from historians and legal scholars.220 To understand the jus sanguinis citizenship provision of the Act, one cannot rely solely on the normal sources of legislative history, such as committee reports, hearings, and floor debates. The Nationality Act was drafted by an interdepartmental committee of officials appointed from the Department of State, the Department of Labor (which then housed the Bureau of Immigration), and the Department of Justice, and it is the archival records of those departments that shed the most helpful light on the system created by the Act.221
What forces led to this reform? The archives reveal three primary sources of pressure. First, efforts to convene the interdepartmental committee that drafted the Nationality Act appear to have been initiated by lawyers in the Department of State who worked daily with the patchwork of nationality laws and who believed that wholesale codification and revision would achieve greater clarity and consistency within the corpus of American nationality law.222 Second, nationality law was also front and center within the international law community as a subject that needed to be addressed through multi-national treaties that would help countries minimize conflicts between their different systems of nationality law.223
The third and possibly most substantively influential source of pressure for the reform of the nationality laws that regulated family-based immigration, naturalization, and jus sanguinis citizenship was women’s organizations’ sustained campaign for gender equality during the 1920s and 1930s. Following the ratification of the Nineteenth Amendment in 1920, American women’s organizations, and especially the National Woman’s Party, turned their attention to the nationality laws and equal citizenship rights for women.224 In so doing, they made a set of demands that had far-reaching implications for the administration of American nationality law, including race-based exclusion laws and national origins quotas. As a consequence, women’s demands triggered considerable debate and resistance within the agencies charged with enforcing those laws. In 1933, it was those very agencies—the Department of State, the Department of Labor, and the Department of Justice—that President Franklin Roosevelt directed to “designate a committee . . . to review the nationality laws of the United States, to recommend revisions . . . and to codify those laws into one comprehensive nationality law.”225 Five years later, that committee produced the Proposed Code that, with a few relatively minor changes by legislators, would become the Nationality Act of 1940.226 In this Section, I demonstrate that the racialist concerns of administrators shaped not only their implementation of the laws, but also their work drafting the first modern jus sanguinis citizenship statute.
1. Women’s Claims to Equal Citizenship Rights as a Threat to the Exclusion Laws, 1922-1940
Although Roosevelt charged the interdepartmental committee with revising American nationality laws “particularly with reference to the removal of certain existing discriminations,” the committee was staffed by officials from the three key departments that had long implemented the gender- and race-based nationality laws. The reaction of some committee members to women’s claims to gender equality reveals a strong commitment to those traditional modes of regulating nationality. For example, in 1922, Richard Flournoy—then an assistant solicitor in the Department of State and later a member of the interdepartmental committee—found the idea that a married woman would maintain her American citizenship upon marriage to a foreigner “very objectionable” on the ground that it was “obviously a direct blow at the principle of family unity”227—a reference to the principles of coverture that resulted in women’s loss of independent civil identity upon marriage. When women’s organizations went one step further and proposed that Congress amend the nationality laws to allow married American women to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children, Flournoy wrote a lengthy memo dismissing the proposition as “so ridiculous that it is hard to discuss it.”228
Resistance to gender equality in the nationality code was inextricably linked to the prevailing commitment to racial exclusion and national origins quotas. For example, one reason why gender equality in jus sanguinis citizenship was seen as “ridiculous” was that liberalization of those laws in the name of gender equality would frustrate enforcement of the race-based exclusion laws. Thus, Flournoy worried that recognizing married American mothers’ right to secure citizenship for their children “would . . . open the doors of the United States to the free and unrestricted entry” of “thousands” of children of American mothers, including “Orientals.”229 In the 1930s, another Department of State official worried that allowing American mothers to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children would have “far reaching effects” on immigration, extending citizenship in “thousands of cases . . . involving persons in various countries, including Oriental countries,” thus “letting down the immigration barriers established by the Immigration Act of 1924.”230
Concerns about the racial implications of jus sanguinis citizenship were voiced not only in the intra-office memos of administrators; they were also prevalent in legislative debates over sundry nationality bills proposed by women’s organizations in the decade prior to the enactment of the Nationality Act. In the early 1930s, when Congress considered a bill that would have allowed both mothers and fathers to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children, several witnesses and legislators were alarmed. Testifying at a committee hearing, the president of the International Seamen’s Union explained that the expansion of jus sanguinis citizenship would “leave[] the door open so that you can largely destroy your Chinese exclusion act.”231 Legislators’ questions directed at Burnita Shelton Matthews of the National Woman’s Party, which sponsored the bill, betrayed similar anxieties: Representative Charles Kramer of California asked, “Don’t you feel that we are increasing the probability of bringing in more of the Chinese and Japanese, and ‘what have you’, from these nations over there, by reason of this bill?”232 Personalizing—and sexualizing—the issue, Kramer pressed the matter further: “How would you feel if you had a daughter, and she was sitting alongside Chinese and Japanese boys in school every day . . . ?”233
Representative William Traeger, also of California, similarly worried that gender equality in jus sanguinis citizenship would lead to a dramatic increase in Chinese and Japanese American citizens.234 He was also concerned about another group which had more recently become the target of immigration restrictions:
I am wondering whether the ladies who are sponsoring this bill have studied the situation in California in the past year or two . . . . Our country began to deport Mexicans [but] . . . [t]hose nationals remained in Los Angeles County long enough to produce children. Those children naturally . . . became citizens of the United States.235
Although the children had been deported along with their parents, Traeger worried that, under the pending bill, the female children would, years later, be entitled to bring their children to the United States as citizens.236 In light of these concerns, Traeger drew a clear line: “If the law can be amended to preclude that sort of thing, I am for it; otherwise I am against it.”237
Worried that the bill would be defeated, the Committee on Immigration and Naturalization added a provision whereby, in the words of one of the bill’s sponsors, all children born abroad to a mixed-nationality couple of whom the “alien parent is an alien ineligible to citizenship by naturalization, would not derive citizenship from their citizen parent, either mother or father,”238 thus proposing to exclude virtually all Asian foreign-born children of American citizen parents. That effort failed in the House of Representatives after considerable debate,239 and in 1934 Congress passed a statute that gave American women the ability to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children with no explicit racial limitations.240 It would be wrong, however, to conclude that the 1934 statute did not respond to concerns that the gender equalization of jus sanguinis citizenship would lead to evasion of the exclusion laws and quotas. The final version of the bill required children of mixed-nationality marriages to fulfill a five-year U.S. residency requirement241—a requirement was intended by some legislators to exclude children of citizens who were otherwise racially excludable. When Senator William King of Utah expressed concern that the foreign-born children of “a Japanese or a Chinese [woman] or a woman from India . . . [married to] a man who is a citizen of the United States” would be considered citizens, his colleague Senator Royal Copeland assured him, “[T]hat is all fixed by necessity of the term of residence.”242
Concern about the racial implications of gender equality in nationality law also shaped the code that the interdepartmental committee drafted and submitted to Congress in 1938, and that eventually became the Nationality Act of 1940. In addition to the five-year child residency requirement introduced in 1934, the interdepartmental committee proposed a ten-year parental residency requirement.243 Although the parental residency requirement was race neutral by design, the committee defended it in terms that would appeal to nativist sensibilities. Testifying before Congress on behalf of the interdepartmental committee, Richard Flournoy explained that the Nationality Act’s jus sanguinis provision “improved” the 1934 Act by introducing a significant parental residency requirement. One worry was that American citizens of Chinese or Mexican descent would leave the United States, return to China or Mexico, and have children who “are born citizens of the United States”244—not only spreading citizenship too thin, but giving it to the wrong sort of people. The Nationality Act’s provision, he explained, “is not so loose as that because it requires that a citizen must have resided 10 years in the United States in order that he or she may transmit citizenship to the children born abroad.”245
In sum, in the decades prior to the enactment of the Nationality Act of 1940, efforts to secure gender equality in jus sanguinis citizenship law triggered concern that such equalization would lead to the recognition and admission of racially excludable children as citizens. This was not the only concern voiced by administrators, who also worried that departure from the patrilineal norm that had long characterized jus sanguinis citizenship would lead to more cases of dual citizenship, and ran contrary to the fundamental principle that the husband determined the political allegiance of his dependents.246 But concern about the breakdown of the carefully crafted ethno-racial limitations on immigration and naturalization was prevalent among administrators and legislators who resisted gender equality in American jus sanguinis citizenship law. In short, as women’s organizations and their allies in Congress pressed for gender equality in nationality law, it became apparent that gender- and marriage-based restrictions on parent-child citizenship transmission were serving racially exclusionary ends.
2. Nonmarital Children of American Fathers and the Proposed Code
If the felt need to protect nativist immigration policies helps explain resistance to extension of jus sanguinis citizenship to the children of married American mothers, it also helps explain officials’ particular resistance to recognizing the nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers as citizens. In the 1920s and 1930s, questions regarding the citizenship status of mixed-race and non-white nonmarital children of American fathers was a source of confusion and consternation among officials residing abroad and administrators in Washington, D.C. The Department of State frequently received inquiries from members of the Foreign Service concerning the citizenship status of foreign-born mixed-race children of American fathers. In 1928, the Department received a letter from the consul in Calcutta concerning “the illegitimate child of an American father and Burmese mother.”247 In 1933, a dispatch from an American official in Tahiti inquired as to the citizenship of an “illegitimate child born at Tahiti of [an] American father . . . and [a] Tahitian girl . . . who has an admixture of about one-eighth white blood.”248 In 1935, the Department received an application for citizenship from a child born out of wedlock to an American citizen father and a Haitian mother.249 And, as detailed above, concern that jus sanguinis citizenship was being used to evade the race-based exclusion laws had been voiced by the Bureau of Immigration in multiple contexts, including Ng Suey Hi, Louie Wah You,and Chin Suey.250
The rule that only marital foreign-born children of American fathers would be recognized as citizens had provided an easy answer to some of those inquiries. For example, regarding the suggestion that the nonmarital child of an American father and a Burmese mother had a claim to American citizenship, the Department of State official noted tersely that “it is clear the child referred to in the despatch cannot claim American citizenship.”251 Similarly, the daughter of the American father and the Haitian mother was not a citizen because, even though acknowledged by her father, “it is evident that Miss Harris has not been legitimated.”252 And, as shown above, limitations on father-child citizenship transmission outside the legally recognized marital family had served Bureau of Immigration officials well in their effort to enforce the exclusion laws against foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers.253
In 1938 the interdepartmental committee proposed codifying the modernized version of the Guyer rule: nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers would not be recognized as citizens unless and until they had been legitimated by the father.254 Modeled after the Department of State’s legitimation exception—which the report cited—this provision liberalized the absolute prohibition of citizenship transmission by fathers outside marriage that the Bureau of Immigration had favored in litigation over the citizenship claims of children of Chinese American fathers. But adopting the Department of State’s legitimation exception marked a departure from the Guyer rule, not its complete repudiation, as the exception largely maintained marriage as a requirement of father-child citizenship transmission. In 1938, as in the 1920s, in the majority of states the only way a father could fully legitimate his child was to marry the mother.255 Accordingly, by requiring legitimation, the Proposed Code—and the Nationality Act that transformed the Code into law—maintained marriage as the key to father-child citizenship transmission in most instances.256 The legitimation requirement was race neutral on its face, but administrators incorporated state law restrictions on marriage into federal nationality law,257 including bans on interracial marriage, as well as the race-salient non-recognition practices of the sort developed by the Department of State in the case of Aviga Chapin and the Bureau of Immigration in the exclusion law cases. As I discuss below, those limitations on marriage would play a significant role in the exclusion of Amerasian children from citizenship in the mid and late twentieth centuries, as the United States deployed hundreds of thousands of soldiers to Asia.258
3. The Maternalist Exception: Nonmarital Children of American Mothers
Before turning to the wartime operation of jus sanguinis citizenship laws, it is important to consider the dramatic gender asymmetry in the Nationality Act’s regulation of citizenship of nonmarital foreign-born children. Although the Act restricted father-child citizenship transmission for nonmarital children,it provided for automatic transmission of citizenship between American mothers and their nonmarital foreign-born children, contingent on a very liberal maternal residency requirement.259 Why the special solicitude for the nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers?
As is true of the limitations imposed on citizenship transmission between American fathers and their nonmarital foreign-born children, the generous recognition of nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers found in the Nationality Act originated in the prior practices of administrators. Administrative recognition of nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers as citizens began before 1934, the year that Congress first granted women the right to transmit citizenship to their children. Hence, the recognition of such children as citizens represented a departure from the pre-1934 statute.260 The interdepartmental committee that drafted the 1938 Proposed Code was aware of the practice, explaining to Congress that the Department of State had “uniformly held that an illegitimate child born abroad of an American mother acquires at birth the nationality of the mother.”261 The Proposed Code suggested codifying this practice: “[I]f the mother had the nationality of the United States at the time of the child’s birth, and had previously resided in the United States or one of its outlying possessions, [the child] shall be held to have acquired at birth her nationality status.”262 When Congress passed the Nationality Act, it adopted the language of the Proposed Code verbatim.263
One way to understand the solicitude shown for the nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers is as a product of the gender-asymmetrical common law principles that also shaped (and restricted) citizenship transmission between a father and his nonmarital child.264 If the default rule that nonmarital children of American fathers were not citizens found support in the common law rules that refused recognition of the father-child relationship outside marriage for status determinations, the corollary that outside marriage the child’s citizenship status followed that of the mother also found support in American common law.265 There is certainly evidence that administrators who endorsed the practice drew on such principles. For example, the drafters of the Proposed Code explained the recognition of unwed mothers’ foreign-born children as citizens using the formalized (and gender-based) logic of the common law: it was premised on the longstanding domestic relations law principle that “the mother in such a case stands in the place of the father.”266
But fidelity to common law principles provides only a partial explanation for the administrators’ behavior. Although the maternal line rule had a long pedigree in American law for purposes of determining other forms of status—such as domicile, slave status, and racial status—its application in the context of jus sanguinis citizenship appears to have originated in the early twentieth century. Why then? The historical sources suggest that administrators’ recognition of mother-child citizenship transmission outside marriage was animated by the powerful maternalist norms that shaped early twentieth-century American social policy. At their core, maternalist social policies were committed to supporting women as mothers, as reflected in a wave of state law Mothers’ Aid statutes in the 1910s and, at the federal level, the creation of the Children’s Bureau in 1912, the enactment of the Sheppard-Towner Act in 1921, and the creation of Aid to Dependent Children in the Social Security Act of 1935.267 As such, many of the laws and policies that maternalist activists and reformers instituted were also deeply gendered, as they were premised on the view that mothers were the natural caregivers of children.268
In the particular context of jus sanguinis citizenship law, the maternalist turn largely originated in the practices of front-line administrators in the Bureau of Immigration. Although questions concerning the citizenship status of nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers arose in several contexts, the issue was especially pressing at crossings along the U.S.-Canadian border. In the 1920s, if not earlier, immigration officials on both sides of that border began recognizing the nonmarital foreign-born children of American and Canadian mothers as citizens of the mother’s country. Despite the lack of authorizing legislation in either country, this practice was memorialized in a cross-border reciprocal agreement in which officials of both countries agreed that the minor foreign-born child of an American or Canadian unwed mother would be recognized as a citizen by the mother’s country—and allowed to cross the border.269
Because recognition of nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers as citizens marked a departure from the jus sanguinis citizenship statute, immigration administrators were frequently pressed to defend the policy, especially as some of the children would have been denied entry under the race-based exclusion laws or national origins quotas. In fact, in the late 1920s, that very issue arose in a series of cases involving Canadian and American mothers seeking to return home with a nonmarital child in tow.270 The cross-border agreement almost fell apart when American border officials questioned whether such children should be recognized as citizens if they were of a race “ineligible to citizenship.”271
In the case of nonmarital children of American mothers, the practical problem of who would take responsibility for those children, and concern about the costs and public relations embarrassment that could result if border officials separated children from their mothers, appear to have trumped concerns about the evasion of race-based exclusion laws and national origins quotas. Memo after memo explaining and defending the cross-border agreement reveals U.S. officials’ nearly uniform view that it was only practical to keep mothers and their nonmarital children together, as mothers were the presumed caretakers of such children. In 1929, the Commissioner General of the Bureau of Immigration explained that “the only purpose [for the rule] . . . is to provide against the separation of mothers and children.”272 “It can well be foreseen,” explained one Bureau official, “that much distress and possible criticism would result if enforced separations of mothers and children were occasioned by the attitude which has been assumed by the Canadian Government and our own in dealing with the question.”273 No such distress and criticism attended the rule that recognized only marital or legitimated children of American fathers as citizens, for, as all agreed, “as a practical matter, it is well known that almost invariably it is the mother who concerns herself with [the illegitimate] child.”274
How are we to understand administrators’ willingness to recognize foreign-born children of American mothers as citizens? The fact that such recognition allowed some children who would have been subject to the exclusion laws to enter the United States—and to be recognized as citizens—certainly gave rise to concern among some officials. But the documents recording the back and forth between Canadian and American officials do not register anxiety that such practices would significantly compromise the system of racial exclusion laws. One very likely reason is that, given the reciprocal nature of the cross-border agreement, American officials were faced with the possibility that, unless they allowed American mothers to bring their children into the United States—even if the child was racially excludable—the Canadian border officials would refuse to allow Canadian mothers and their children to cross the border into Canada.275 As one Canadian official reminded his counterpart in the Bureau of Immigration, some of those mothers and children would have been ineligible to enter Canada,which also had racial exclusion laws and other immigration restrictions.276 Given this, denying entry to otherwise excludable children of American mothers may not have effectively served the ends of America’s restrictions on immigration. In addition,in the early twentieth century, single women likely traveled and resided internationally with much less frequency than men or married women.277 With that in mind, it is understandable that recognition of the foreign-born nonmarital children of American mothers as citizens generated little concern about massive evasion of the exclusionary laws, in contrast to other proposals to introduce gender equality into jus sanguinis citizenship.278 Given these circumstances, the relatively low-level officials faced with an unwed American mother attempting to return to the United States with her child reasoned comfortably from the maternalist premises that characterized early twentieth-century social policy more generally, lamenting the fact that compliance with the jus sanguinis statute would result in “separation of mothers and children.”279
With a general consensus among administrators that nonmarital foreign-born children should remain with their American mothers, the interdepartmental committee incorporated the longstanding practice of recognizing those children as citizens in the Proposed Code. In 1939, when the issue came to the attention of Secretary of Labor Frances Perkins—herself a dedicated maternalist—she agreed, opining that “steps should be taken to avoid subjecting these unfortunate individuals to unnecessary hardships.”280 Attorney General Frank Murphy concurred, noting that “exclusion of [such] children is not only harsh, but largely impracticable.”281 Both agreed that the pending nationality bill should codify the administrative practice of recognizing the nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers as citizens.282 In short, the historical record reveals that the pronounced gender asymmetry of the Nationality Act’s treatment of nonmarital foreign-born children of American mothers and fathers was shaped by contemporary maternalist norms regarding the mother’s relationship with her nonmarital child—and the father’s lack of such a relationship.283
The fact that administrators were willing to allow mother-child citizenship transmission for children born out of wedlock, even when the child was racially excludable, does not mean that the gender-asymmetrical regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship was not a racially nativist practice.284 Administrators’ willingness to accommodate the foreign-born children of unwed American mothers stands out as an exception in the historical record. That record reveals officials’ commitment to the concept of gender-based “family unity” in nationality law and their commitment to maintaining the racially nativist policies that had been a core component of American nationality law for over a century and a half. In the minds of many administrators, those gender- and race-based policies were interconnected. Introducing gender equality in jus sanguinis citizenship by allowing married American mothers and unwed fathers to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children would defeat the core purpose of the exclusionary and quota-based regulations: the exclusion or limited admittance of ethno-racial groups that had been deemed inferior or inassimilable. The significantly expanded parent and child residency requirements found in the Nationality Act were added in part to ensure the integrity of the racial bars and national origins quotas that, in the minds of some administrators, had been compromised by granting married mothers the right to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children. Most important for present purposes, as with pre-1940 practice, the Nationality Act of 1940 largely maintained marriage as a key to citizenship for foreign-born children of American fathers and, in so doing, the Act incorporated state laws barring interracial marriage and race-salient non-recognition rules into federal nationality law. For the foreign-born children of American fathers, the racially exclusionary operation of this constellation of domestic relations and nationality laws assumed new importance—and took on new dimensions—as the United States went to war.
B. The Guyer Rule at War: War Brides, War Babies, and “Bui Doi”
The Nationality Act of 1940 was not a war measure in the traditional sense, as it was not drafted in anticipation of the United States’s entry into World War II.285 However, shortly after the statute’s enactment, the wartime deployment of American soldiers to battlefields—both within and beyond “Christendom”—led to the births of inestimable numbers of foreign-born children to American fathers. In this Section, I demonstrate how the modernized Guyer rule—the default rule that nonmarital foreign-born children of American fathers were not citizens—operated in combination with the race-based citizenship laws and the marriage and fraternization policies of the United States military during World War II, the Korean War, and the Vietnam War.286 Under the Nationality Act of 1940, state marriage laws were important in determining the legitimacy of the foreign-born child of an American father, and hence the child’s citizenship status, as the statute directed that the laws of the father’s “domicile” would be used to determine the child’s legitimacy.287 But for the men who were stationed abroad as soldiers, and the children they fathered while there, the military policies that governed the marital and sexual practices of soldiers were just as significant and, as I explain below, further amplified the impact of state law bans on interracial marriage. Even a brief analysis of the United States’s welcoming treatment of children born to American soldiers and their European “war brides” during World War II—and its resistance to marriages between American soldiers and their Asian girlfriends during that war, the Korean War, and the Vietnam War—demonstrates an essential point: the limitations on father-child jus sanguinis citizenship for nonmarital children continued to be used to exclude nonwhite children from citizenship and thus served a racially nativist nation-building project.
Take the much-celebrated European “war brides” and “war babies” of World War II. During and following World War II, the military often encouraged soldiers to wed their European girlfriends with whom they had fathered children, and Congress provided the soldiers’ non-excludable war brides and children with special immigration status through the War Brides Acts.288 Congress funded a massive initiative to bring the European war brides—and their many babies—“home” to the United States,289 and the Red Cross established “war brides’ schools” to help ease these women’s transition into American society and prepare them to raise a new generation of citizens. But, as Susan Zeiger has chronicled in great detail, neither the military nor Congress was welcoming to all overseas girlfriends, fiancées, and wives of American soldiers—or the children they fathered with those women. The War Brides Acts specifically excluded women who were “ineligible to citizenship” because of their race, and the promise of preferential immigration status was denied those women.290
The racial prohibitions incorporated into the War Brides Acts meant not only that a soldier could not bring his racially excludable wife home, but also—pursuant to explicit military policy—that the soldier would not likely be given permission to marry his racially excludable girlfriend in the first place.291 Starting in 1939, every member of the military stationed abroad was required to obtain permission from his superiors to marry.292 The work of Nancy Ota and Rose Cuison Villazor shows that, as a general matter, permission to marry was to be given liberally, but official military policy counseled against giving permission in cases where the soldier sought to marry outside his race.293 Because of racially restrictive immigration law and state law restrictions on interracial marriage, the military contended, marriage to a racially excludable woman was likely to fail because the soldier would be unable to take his bride home to the United States.294 Given the Nationality Act’s requirement that only legitimate or legitimated foreign-born children of American fathers were recognized as citizens—and that legitimation generally required marriage—the military’s restrictions on interracial marriage amplified the reach of state laws banning interracial marriage. In turn, the military ban on interracial marriage had obvious implications for the many children born out of wedlock to American soldiers and Asian women: under the rules governing father-child citizenship transmission, they were excluded from citizenship.
In 1947, Congress provided a brief amnesty from the racially restrictive policy on the immigration of Asian war brides that allowed them to enter the United States under the permissive terms of the War Brides Act if they were married within thirty days.295 But the 1947 Act was a temporary concession and did not overcome the military’s policy against interracial marriages between American soldiers and Asian women.296 Moreover, the 1947 Act did not clarify the status of the many children born abroad to American soldiers and their Asian wives prior to marriage. In an urgent telegram sent to the Department of State several months after the 1947 Act was passed, the American Consul in Yokohama asked for guidance concerning the citizenship status of the “[c]onsiderable numbers of children born to service personnel prior to marriage of American citizen husbands to Japanese wives.”297 Although the soldiers’ “alien wives” were admissible under the 1947 Act, “apparently alien children ineligible [to] citizenship [are] not admissible under those acts,” the consul explained, and it was “[t]hus essential [to] determine whether [a] child [was] legitimated by subsequent marriage and therefore [was an] American citizen prior to departure.”298
In a responding airgram, intended to help American officials in Japan with this process, Department of State officials noted the states in which legitimation was effected by the marriage of the parents, but cautioned that “certain States forbid marriage between certain races.”299 If the husband’s home state would not recognize his marriage, the marriage could not provide the basis for a child’s legitimation under the Nationality Act, which explicitly required that the child be legitimated under the laws of the father’s domicile.300 Moreover, when the temporary exemption from race-based exclusion laws expired, it left in place a military policy that effectively banned interracial marriage in many countries where American soldiers were stationed, which thwarted the marriage plans of many couples. The children born to such unions, along with the thousands of other children born out of wedlock to American soldiers and Asian women during World War II and its aftermath, were excluded from citizenship.301
In 1952 Congress eliminated all explicit race-based exclusions from American nationality law, and thirteen years later, it removed all national origins quotas, thus lifting a significant barrier to the immigration of Asian wives of American servicemen.302 In 1967 the Supreme Court declared unconstitutional all laws banning interracial marriage.303 But the marriage and legitimation requirements in the jus sanguinis citizenship statute—by then recodified in the 1952 Immigration and Nationality Act304—continued to serve as a race-salient limitation on the recognition of American soldiers’ foreign-born children as citizens. Soldiers’ interracial marriages were no longer illegal (or presumed illegal) under state law, but military officials continued to discourage soldiers from marrying local women in many of the Asian countries where American troops were stationed. For example, as Zeiger demonstrates, during the Vietnam War the military “vigorously and systematically discouraged marriage for American service personnel in Vietnam, placing a wide array of bureaucratic and financial obstacles in front of marriage aspirants.”305 Instead, drawing on a set of conventions and practices that had emerged during the Korean War, the military encouraged nonmarital sexual liaisons between American soldiers and local women, including long-term “contract” arrangements.306 The children born to such relationships were illegitimate and hence not American citizens. Unlike in World War II Europe, where military officials had frequently encouraged soldiers to marry their pregnant English girlfriends, no pressure was used to encourage American soldiers to marry the Vietnamese mothers of their children; no special ships were commissioned to bring the soldiers’ new families “home,” and no “war brides’ schools” were established to help these women adjust to American life—or to raise a new generation of citizens.307
It is impossible to know how many children were born out of wedlock to American soldiers stationed in Asia or elsewhereduring the late twentieth century.308 It is also impossible, of course, to determine the extent to which legal and military policy barriers to marriage shaped the decisions of individual soldiers and the women with whom they had relationships. For example, despite these policies, many American soldiers did marry their Korean and Vietnamese girlfriends—and legitimized their children in so doing.309 And even when a child was born, presumably many couples would have opted out of marriage regardless of the policies discouraging or prohibiting the solemnization of their relationships.310
Nonetheless, the differences between the legitimacy and citizenship status of children fathered by American soldiers in England circa 1945, Japan circa 1947, and Vietnam circa 1968 lay not just in the private choices of individuals entangled by war, but also—and significantly—in the official race-based marriage and fraternization policies of the United States military and jus sanguinis citizenship laws enacted by Congress.311 The combined operation of those laws and policies undoubtedly shaped the marriage practices of American soldiers stationed abroad and, on aggregate, helped determine the citizenship status of children fathered by those soldiers: the predominantly white babies of World War II soldiers became citizens and “baby boomers,” while a very significant population of nonmarital Amerasian babies were excluded and became “bui doi”—children of the dust.312
The plight of the “bui doi”—Amerasian children born to American soldiers stationed in Asia—became a regular news item in the 1970s.313 And in the 1980s, under pressure from civil rights organizations, the racial operation of jus sanguinis citizenship and its impact on the citizenship status of foreign-born Amerasian children was eventually raised in Congress.314 In 1981, Representatives Barney Frank and Patricia Schroeder introduced a bill that would have provided an immigration preference and a fast track to citizenship for Amerasian children born during periods of American military presence in certain Asian countries.315 Testifying in support of the measure, Representative Stewart McKinney explained:
Since 1950 the United States has sent hundreds of thousands of military personnel to the Asian area with ramifications that are well known around the world. However, little has been said or done concerning the plight of the thousands of mixed-race children left behind in inhuman social and political conditions by their U.S. fathers.316
Encountering significant resistance from Department of State officials, Representative Schroeder quarreled with the notion that “the military can go into foreign countries and do whatever they want, and they won’t be responsible.”317 During the hearings on the bill, the committee demanded documentary evidence of the military’s fraternization policies during the Vietnam War, drawing a direct link between those policies and the creation of an underclass of Amerasian children who, because of the requirements of the jus sanguinis citizenship statute, were not recognized as American citizens.318
The bill initially failed, but when it was introduced again in 1982, testimony offered at congressional hearings also drew the connection between the limits on jus sanguinis citizenship and officials’ resistance to approving or recognizing marriages between American soldiers and Asian women. An immigration lawyer who testified at the hearings noted that resistance to such marriages had tainted the bureaucratic procedures of Department of State officials responsible for processing passport applications submitted by foreign-born children of American soldiers. She explained that many Amerasian children left behind were, in fact, legitimate or legitimated by their parents’ marriages and were therefore “already entitled, under current law, to full U.S. citizenship.”319 Recounting practices that bear a resemblance to the Bureau of Immigration officials’ efforts to deny entry to the children of Chinese American fathers based on inadequate evidence of their status, the attorney explained that the Department of State had “refused in many cases to issue passports to such Amerasian children,” placing the burden on the children to prove that the documentary evidence of their parents’ marriage was not fraudulent.320 “This heavy burden of proof is not required in cases arising out of Canada or Europe, where the applicants are usually white,” she noted; “[r]ather, this insurmountable burden of proof is applied solely in cases involving nonwhites, and especially Asians.”321
Although efforts to secure citizenship for Amerasian children foundered in Congress, legislators did enact an immigration preference for Amerasian children from certain countries.322 As remarkable as even the partial recognition of Amerasian children in American immigration law, however, was the fact that the congressional debates leading up to that legislation contained explicit acknowledgment of the racial operation of America’s gender-based jus sanguinis citizenship principles and the government’s role in enacting policies that led to the exclusion of Amerasian children from citizenship. Historically, recognition of the racial operation of jus sanguinis citizenship has been selective at best. Although the racial dimension of the “war baby” problem has long been acknowledged in popular culture, the role of jus sanguinis citizenship laws in the exclusion of those children from citizenship is rarely recognized, especially by military officials, executive branch officials, and legislators. The racialized operation of jus sanguinis citizenship laws has also been obscured in modern debates concerning the continued gender-based regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship—a point that I return to in Part IV.
C. On Nation Building, Nationality, and Family Law
The racially nativist commitments that animated American nationality law for well over a century and a half are a well-studied phenomenon.323 What has been largely overlooked, however, are the significant ways that domestic relations laws were deployed in the service of those commitments to determine the citizenship of children. Malleable but durable gender-based domestic relations law principles used to determine children’s birth status were deployed by administrators, judges, and legislators in different ways at different times, often in support of a broader racially nativist nationality policy. Of course, marriage and legitimacy requirements served multiple purposes in the hands of officials who designed and implemented jus sanguinis citizenship law as it applied to the foreign-born children of American fathers. Officials voiced concern about fraudulent paternity claims.324 Administrative convenience played a significant part.325 But the historical sources reveal a much deeper resistance to recognizing the nonmarital children of American fathers as citizens—resistance that was born of a long-standing social and legal commitment to the male-headed marital family as the proper source of citizenship, and the related felt need to enforce racially nativist nationality laws. In short, racial nativism was one of several factors that informed the way administrators and legislators reasoned about the citizenship rights of foreign-born nonmarital children, and it was an important factor.
Attention to the processes by which domestic relations law principles were enlisted in the service of nationality laws’ racially nativist objectives deepens and expands our understanding of the history of American citizenship in important ways. First, careful attention to the memos, case files, briefs, opinions, and notes of early twentieth-century administrators, lawyers, judges, and legislators reveals the complex entanglement of domestic relations law, racialized conceptions of citizenship, and gender in developing the fundamental structure of our jus sanguinis citizenship law. In some instances, administrators incorporated explicitly race-based domestic relations laws and policies into federal jus sanguinis citizenship law. This process was especially apparent in the military’s ban on interracial marriage326 and the Department of State’s interpretation of the 1940 Nationality Act’s requirement that only legitimated nonmarital children of American fathers would be recognized as citizens, subject to the restriction of anti-miscegenation laws of the father’s state of domicile. Similarly, legislators overtly excluded certain races from the benefits of family-based citizenship laws, as demonstrated by the exclusion of women who were racially “ineligible to citizenship,” and their children, from the War Brides Acts.327
In other instances, officials shaped domestic relations law in order to limit the reach of jus sanguinis citizenship in ways that were not explicitly race based, but were purposefully race salient. For example, officials charged with enforcing the nationality laws tended toward a narrower construction of laws governing marriage and legitimacy in an effort to limit the recognition of citizenship claims asserted by or on behalf of nonwhite children. This practice was at work in the Department of State’s refusal to recognize any Samoan-American marriages for purposes of determining the citizenship of Samoan-born children of American fathers.328 It was also at work in the Bureau of Immigration’s insistence that the presumption of legitimacy—a staple of early twentieth-century domestic relations law—did not apply when determining the citizenship claims of children of Chinese American fathers.329 Finally, such race-salient practices were evident in the military’s efforts to thwart soldiers’ marriages to Asian women, even after explicit race-based and national origins quotas were abandoned.330 Regardless of whether they took the form of explicitly race-based domestic relations laws that were incorporated into citizenship laws, or facially race-neutral but operationally race-salient interpretations of domestic relations laws, what is clear from the historical sources is that, at significant and formative moments, the laws governing marriage and birth status provided an alternative means of policing the racial bounds of the polity.
Second, what is also clear from the historical sources is that, as a method of shaping the racial composition of the polity, reliance on domestic relations law principles tended to obscure the racialist ambitions of decision makers and policy makers. The Guyer court could rely on the legal principle nullius filii rather than engage with the explosive question of the citizenship status of persons of African descent—a question that was being contested on the battlefield as the judges of the Maryland Court of Appeals deliberated.331 Confronted with claims to citizenship by Samoan-born children of American fathers, the Department of State could rely on a constrained definition of marriage to determine those children’s claims, helping to secure the unstable distinctions between center and periphery, citizen and noncitizen, in America’s fledgling empire.332 In deciding the citizenship status of foreign-born children of Chinese American fathers, the Bureau of Immigration could turn to the laws governing birth status and marriage when purely race-based regulation was politically infeasible.333 And after the race-based and national origins restrictions were finally eliminated from American nationality law in the mid-1960s, military officials could enlist marriage and legitimacy laws to restrict the availability of citizenship to the thousands of foreign-born children of American soldiers stationed in Asia.334 At key moments, then, domestic relations law principles were used by officials to prevent significant numbers of nonwhite children from securing citizenship through their fathers, without relying on transparently racialist reasoning.
Third, and related, by focusing on the role of domestic relations law principles in the administration and development of jus sanguinis citizenship law, one can better describe how race-salient gender-asymmetrical understandings of marriage and family became entrenched, normalized, and naturalized in the law governing parent-child citizenship transmission. Building on the insights of law and society theorists who emphasize the constitutive effects of the everyday practice of law,335 one can track how gender- and marriage-based domestic relations law became ingrained in the everyday legal practices of federal and state judges and federal administrators, and was eventually codified in statute. To identify this process of entrenchment and naturalization is to resist the suggestion that such practices are transhistorical, while also acknowledging their hold on American law. Like all sociolegal phenomena, the racialization of jus sanguinis citizenship was the product of specific social, cultural, and political circumstances that shaped Americans’ understanding of what it meant to be a member of the nation-state: who was in, who was not, and the justifications that were offered for those determinations. But as much as the history of jus sanguinis citizenship demonstrates that American nationality law developed in response to particular historical conditions, one would be remiss to ignore the common thread that runs through the regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship: the way that the gender-based domestic relations laws that structure parent-child relationships frequently operated in nationality law as instruments of racial exclusion. Indeed, a risk of doing so is to participate inadvertently in a practice of elision that has frequently characterized racially nativist discourse and strategies in the field of nationality law.
IV. reflections on the practice and politics of modern derivative citizenship
For some students of American nationality law, the importance of the history of jus sanguinis citizenship—now called derivative citizenship—lies not in its significance for our understanding of the past, but in what it may mean for how we reason about modern citizenship law. The historical account provided here bears on a wide range of important issues concerning the regulation of formal membership in the American polity, including the role of bureaucracy in the development of substantive principles of nationality law, and vice versa;336the allocation of power between the executive branch and Congress in the regulation of nationality law;337 nationality law’s modern role as a nation-building tool;338 the complex interrelationship of family-based immigration preferences and derivative citizenship law; and how the norms and processes of administrative decision making shape the contours of the legally recognized family.339 A full exploration of these topics would extend far beyond the scope of this Article. In closing, I focus on the ways that the history of jus sanguinis citizenship sheds critical light on modern citizenship dilemmas concerning the role of family, and family law, in the rules and processes used to determine citizenship today. Standing alone, history cannot resolve such dilemmas. It cannot tell us how to craft an optimal system of citizenship designation.340 However, this granular history of jus sanguinis citizenship can alert us to the ways that the complex constellation of ideas concerning family, gender, race, and political membership traced here may continue to shape both individuals’ lived experience of gender-based derivative citizenship law and the politics of citizenship law today. In addition, turning to recent contests over the constitutionality of modern gender-based citizenship laws, the history of jus sanguinis citizenship can illuminate past and present practices in ways that can productively reframe the current debate, and prompt modern jurists, lawyers, legislators, and administrators to ask different questions about the wisdom and constitutional moorings of those laws today.
A. Re-reading the Present
Lest one think that gender-based family law principles no longer play a race-salient role in the practice of American citizenship, more recent chapters in the development and implementation of jus sanguinis citizenship principles suggest that the lines drawn by our predecessors continue to inform the operation of the rules that govern membership in the American polity, as well as proposals to fundamentally alter those rules. Most obvious in this regard is the fact that past citizenship determinations premised on racialized family law policies and administrative practices continue to determine the citizenship status of individuals living today and will have intergenerational effects into the future.341 The appeals of organizations to Congress seeking recognition of Amerasian children as citizens are concrete reminders of this fact, and of current efforts to ameliorate the racial operation of derivative citizenship law in a particular context.342
There is also evidence to suggest that gender- and marriage-based derivative citizenship laws continue to function in a race-salient manner in the modern administration of those laws. The experience of Sigifredo Saldana Iracheta is instructive in this regard. Saldana Iracheta was born in 1964 in Tamaulipas, Mexico, to a Mexican mother and a Mexican American father, Sigifredo Saldana.343 Over the course of two decades, from 1992 to 2012, the son entered and was deported from the United States several times. Immigration officials repeatedly rejected Saldana Iracheta’s claim that he was an American citizen, concluding that Sigifredo Sr. could not have transmitted citizenship to him because Saldana Iracheta was illegitimate.344 His father had acknowledged him on his birth certificate, and Saldana Iracheta was raised by both parents along with seven siblings. But according to immigration officials, these undisputed facts were insufficient to legitimate Saldana Iracheta under Mexican law.345 They maintained that under the Mexican Constitution, Saldana Iracheta’s parents were required to marry in order to legitimate him. As they had not done so, Saldana Iracheta was not an American citizen under the derivative citizenship statute.346
The problem with the immigration officials’ position, however, was that one of the provisions of the Mexican Constitution they had relied on simply does not exist, and never did, and the other provision they relied on was inapposite.347 The Fifth Circuit Court of Appeals found that Sigifredo Sr.’s acknowledgment had legitimated Saldana Irachetta under the relevant body of law, the law of the state of Tamaulipas, and that consequently Saldana Iracheta had been a U.S. citizen since birth. The court also found that Saldana Iracheta’s case was not unusual: At least since 1978, immigration officials had relied on the very same non-existent and misinterpreted provisions of Mexican constitutional law in ruling on the derivative citizenship claims of children of Mexican American fathers.348
How are we to understand Saldana Iracheta’s case and those of the unknown number of Mexican-born individuals who, like him, were denationalized and deported based on immigration officials’ erroneous construction of Mexican law? One possibility, as the Department of Justice lawyers suggested in court, is that it was the result of “a mere ‘typo.’”349 That could certainly be true. Without ready access to immigration records and internal agency memoranda of the last three decades, we lack the sources that would enable a full assessment of this proposed explanation.350 But it is undoubtedly true that immigration officials labor under excessive caseloads that easily lead to errors; those errors are then compounded once they are enshrined in precedential opinions.
At the same time, reading Saldana Iracheta against the history of jus sanguinis citizenship raises the possibility that ingrained interpretive practices, along with institutional and political pressure to restrict immigration across the U.S.-Mexican border today, may also help explain the government’s multi-decade reliance on a mistaken understanding of Mexican law governing birth status.351 The point is not that Saldana Iracheta’s case demonstrates that immigration officials reason about derivative citizenship in a race-selective manner. Rather, as the history of the administration of jus sanguinis citizenship law demonstrates, political pressure to rigorously enforce immigration laws with respect to a particular group or along a particular border can lead front-line administrators to employ more restrictive practices in assessing individual claims to derivative citizenship. Because derivative citizenship claims are based on family status relationships, the status in question–and in particular “legitimacy”–tends to be interpreted restrictively in such contexts. It follows that when the border being policed is marked by an ethno-racial divide–as is the case with the U.S.-Mexican border today352–restrictive interpretation of family status will function in a race-salient manner.353
“Birthright citizenship bills”—proposals to restrict jus soli birthright citizenship for children born within the United States—reveal that the complex entanglement of gender, birth status, and race also continues in political battles over immigration and citizenship. These proposals, calculated to exclude the children of undocumented noncitizen mothers from citizenship, have also taken shape in the course of contestation over the citizenship status of individuals of Hispanic descent, and would deny citizenship to American-born children of undocumented mothers, the so-called anchor babies. Although these bills are race neutral, congressional testimony of proponents of such measures makes clear that the primary problem, as they formulate it, is recognizing as citizens the children of undocumented mothers from south of the U.S.-Mexican border.354
The birthright citizenship bills are non-starters politically, but their structure nevertheless reveals the durability of gender-asymmetrical jus sanguinis citizenship principles as a resource for those who seek to restrict American citizenship to certain ethno-racial groups. Virtually all such bills would limit jus soli citizenship using jus sanguinis principles: for a U.S.-born individual to qualify for jus soli citizenship, at least one parent must be a citizen (or, in some proposals, a lawful permanent resident).355 Some of these proposals would also use gender- and marriage-based limitations to regulate jus soli birthright citizenship, to the exclusion of nonmarital children of American fathers. For example, a bill proposed in 2005 would have denied citizenship to any nonmarital child born withinthe United States unless the mother was a citizen or lawful permanent resident. Thus, the nonmarital child of an American father and a noncitizen mother residing in the United States without official permission would be an alien.356 For good measure, the bill explicitly noted that the parents “are not considered to be married if such marriage is only a common law marriage.”357 Never presume marriage.358 A 2007 bill was slightly more generous to the nonmarital native-born child of an American father and an undocumented mother. Under that proposal, the child would be recognized as a citizen as long as the father satisfied several conditions drawn directly from the current derivative citizenship statute that applies to foreign-born children: proof of paternity by clear and convincing evidence, an agreement by the father to pay child support, and paternal acknowledgment of the child prior to the child’s eighteenth birthday.359 In short, several of the birthright citizenship bills would revive the maternal line principle—the nonmarital child’s citizenship status follows that of the mother—in the law governing citizenship of children born in the United States.360 As critics of such proposals have noted, when applied to the children of undocumented mothers the birthright citizenship bills would create a hereditary caste of non-citizens within the United States.361 What has gone unnoted, however, is that some of those bills would do so using the very same family law principles that were long used to effect, or enhance the efficacy of, racially exclusionary nationality laws.362
By observing the formal and functional parallels between the role that birth status determinations play in the context of citizenship determinations, past and present, I do not mean to diminish the significant transformation that has taken place in American nationality law. For all of the inertia and overt hostility to both gender and racial equality in laws governing citizenship transmission and nationality law more generally, in the mid-twentieth century pressure to repeal inegalitarian nationality laws gradually yielded significant changes.363 More recently, Congress prospectively altered the rules governing father-child citizenship transmission to foreign-born nonmarital children, simultaneously liberalizing and placing new requirements on recognition of the father-child relationship.364 Thus, the lines drawn by previous administrators, judges, and lawmakers dividing marital from nonmarital children, citizens from non-citizens, have transformed over time, taking varied forms in different institutional settings and at different moments. Nevertheless, despite such changes, these examples suggest that the complex entanglement of gender-based jus sanguinis citizenship principles, concepts of birth status, and race continues to inform the practice and politics of citizenship law in America.
Although these practices episodically come into public view, as in the past, the racial operation of gender- and marriage-based derivative citizenship laws is often obscured. It is obscured, I suggest, because the normalizing discourses of family law have been reaffirmed and entrenched in the practice of American citizenship, eliding and neutralizing the gendered and racialist operation of jus sanguinis citizenship law. Saldana Iracheta was repeatedly found not to be a citizen because he was “illegitimate”—a basis that, when contested, courts and executive branch officials have found to be justified because the unwed father “normally” does not have a substantive relationship with his child.365 The race-salient operation of restrictions on father-child citizenship transmission are also obscured because, as in the past, suchlaws are most often implemented by immigration officials whose work is significantly shielded from judicial and public scrutiny.366 In the everyday, inconspicuous practices of immigration officials, the boundaries of the nation and the family are affirmed and reaffirmed (sometimes erroneously), sometimes redrawn, and sometimes contested.
B. “Biological Inevitability” and Constitutional Choices
Occasionally, however, the gender-based derivative citizenship laws become the focus of legal contests in the highest profile adjudicative forum in the American system: the Supreme Court. Over the last fifteen years, the Court has heard three challenges to those laws, and in each of those cases the citizenship claim of a foreign-born nonmarital child of an American father was denied.367 The juridical records produced in these cases mention the petitioners’ country of birth only in passing, and the histories of America’s exclusionary immigration policies toward their birth countries—the Philippines, Vietnam, and Mexico368—are absent. Instead, framed by the concerns highlighted in the Court’s gender equal protection jurisprudence, debates among the Justices, lower court judges, and attorneys have focused in significant part on whether the statutes reflect and reinforce stereotypical assumptions about men’s and women’s roles as parents, or if they reflect “real differences” between the sexes.369 This is understandable, as American equal protection jurisprudence focuses on formal “suspect classifications” such as race, gender, and illegitimacy, and treats such classifications as discrete sources of injury.370 But a brief examination of the arguments that have been developed by jurists and government lawyers in defense of gender- and marriage-based regulation of derivative citizenship—interventions that have largely rejected the relevance of historical accounts of jus sanguinis citizenship, and yet are now an important part of that history—suggests that the analytic frame offered by modern gender equality jurisprudence can generate naturalizing accounts of derivative citizenship law that obscure illiberal practices of citizenship, both past and present.371
The Supreme Court’s majority opinion in Nguyen v. INS—the only one of the three cases that has resulted in a majority opinion—demonstrates this point. A core assertion in Nguyen is that differential regulation of citizen mothers and fathers in the current parent-child derivative citizenship statute passes constitutional muster because of “a biological difference between parents.”372 For mothers, the Court reasons, “the opportunity for a meaningful relationship between citizen parent and child inheres in the very event of birth, an event so often critical to our constitutional and statutory understandings of citizenship,” while that “opportunity does not result from the event of birth, as a matter of biological inevitability, in the case of the unwed father.”373 The contention that gender-asymmetrical citizenship laws mark biological difference draws on a significant, if contested, line of jurisprudence that has situated “real” difference as a permissible basis for gender-based regulation.374 However, when the Court reasons that maternal preferences and paternal restrictions embedded in derivative citizenship law are a “biological[ly] inevitab[le]” consequence of differences between men’s and women’s procreative roles,375 it portrays the regulatory scheme as fixed and transhistorical.
The historical sources suggest, to the contrary, that gender-based regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship is not fixed or inevitable, but is the product of choices—choices made by officials acting under historically and institutionally contingent pressures and imperatives. Two examples, of the many that could be drawn from the historical sources, illustrate this point. First, the protracted effort of American women to secure the right to transmit citizenship to their children—a right denied married women entirely until 1934—demonstrates that “the event of birth” has not served as an inevitable basis for citizenship transmission in American law. During the century and a half that married women were unable to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children, the birthing process was decidedly not a salient event in the regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship. Rather, it was understood that the husband-father was the head of the household, that his citizenship would determine that of his marital children, and that married women (as dependents themselves) had no such power.376 In order to change this law, women’s organizations engaged in a sustained multi-decade campaign in order to secure the right of married mothers to transmit citizenship to their foreign-born children. In the course of that campaign, they had to overcome fierce resistance that recognition of women’s equal citizenship would seriously compromise the efficacy of the racial exclusion laws and national origins quotas that characterized American nationality law at the time.377 But they eventually prevailed. They prevailed not because legislators came to understand the “event of birth” as having particular importance in the law of citizenship—nor because a majority of legislators abandoned their commitment to exclusion laws and quotas378—but because women’s organizations convinced legislators of the merits of recognizing women’s equal citizenship rights, or at least convinced them that it was politically expedient to do so.379
The historical sources also do not support the view that generous recognition of mother-child citizenship transmission for children born out of wedlock was animated by administrators’ or lawmakers’ belief in a connection between “the event of birth” and citizenship. Rather, the administrators who developed the rule, later adopted by Congress, largely reasoned in the vein of pragmatic maternalism, acknowledging that, “as a practical matter, it is well known that almost invariably it is the mother who concerns herself with [the illegitimate] child.”380 Sociolegal norms concerning the roles and responsibilities of mothers for children born outside marriage, not theories of “biological inevitability,” provide the best explanation for the recognition of American mothers’ ability to transmit citizenship to their nonmarital foreign-born children.
A second example drawn from the historical record speaks to the other half of the Nguyen Court’s assertion: That in the case of the unwed father, the opportunity to develop ties with his child “does not result from the event of birth, as a matter of biological inevitability.”381 This, the Court urges, was a special concern in the case of servicemen stationed abroad, thus demonstrating “the critical importance of the Government’s interest in ensuring some opportunity for a tie between citizen father and foreign-born child which is a reasonable substitute for the opportunity manifest between mother and child at the time of birth.”382 What the Court’s formulation elides—and what the historical record illuminates—is that during key moments in the development of jus sanguinis citizenship law, government officials facilitated some men’s “opportunity to bond” with their nonmarital foreign-born children, while thwarting others’ opportunity to do the same. The disparate treatment of nonwhite children of servicemen renders the Court’s formulation especially troubling. Congress and the military marshaled extraordinary political and material resources in order to bring the non-Asian brides and babies of World War II soldiers home to the United States. Meanwhile, military policies that prohibited and limited interracial marriage between U.S. soldiers stationed in Asia and local women frustrated the efforts of those servicemen who sought recognition of, and American citizenship for, their children.383 This sorry history calls into question the suggestion that a father’s lack of an opportunity to bond with his child at birthcan reasonably be understood as a “biological inevitability.” Instead, it reveals the limitation of citizenship transmission between the American father and his nonmarital foreign-born child as the product of choices of officials charged with enforcing and developing the rules that governed membership in the polity—rules that were constructed and construed in ways that tended to exclude nonwhite children from citizenship.384
These examples also demonstrate a crucial point that, while obvious from the history provided here, is easily overlooked if one focuses exclusively on how jus sanguinis citizenship is regulated according to the gender and marital status of the citizen parent without attending to the fact that the laws were designed to determine the child’s citizenship. The officials who implemented and developed American jus sanguinis citizenship law were not agnostic as to the child’s birth status, and they also were not agnostic as to the child’s race. Instead, at key junctures, judges, administrators, and legislators enlisted gender- and marriage-based citizenship laws in an effort to limit recognition of nonwhite children as citizens: The “illegitimate half-castes born . . . of American fathers and native women”; the children of Chinese American fathers born, it was feared, on polygamous “stock-farms”; the children of the dust. In so doing, officials charged with policing the bounds of the polity helped create racial sociolegal hierarchies using birth status designations that had been used for similar purposes in American domestic law.385 In the context of nationality law, these designations were formulated and enforced through the blunt instrument of exclusion from membership in the polity.
My purpose in offering these observations is not to provide an ultimate resolution to questions concerning the constitutionality of current gender-based citizenship laws—questions that would take different forms in different cases. Nor do I propose an alternative system of citizenship designation. Rather, my purpose is to urge that a historical account attentive to the origins and operation of the jus sanguinis statutes calls for open acknowledgment of the ideological and political commitments that have informed the development and continued vitality of the gendered construction of the parent-child relationship in American nationality law.386 However we might parse the history of gender-based and racialized regulation of jus sanguinis citizenship law, by portraying the gender-asymmetrical regime we have in place today as an “inevitable” consequence of physiological differences between mothers and fathers, the analysis offered by modern jurists and advocates defending those laws—and now memorialized in the United States Reports—risks eclipsing the different ways those laws have been, and may continue to be, shaped and informed by premises that are no longer accepted as reasonable and legal bases for citizenship determinations.387 Those commitments have been animated not only by gender-traditional modes of reasoning about parental roles, but also by racially nativist understandings of citizenship.
Conclusion
It is possible that the Supreme Court will revisit the questions surrounding the constitutionality of gender-asymmetrical derivativecitizenship laws in the future. It is even possible that the Court will constrain the choices of modern legislators and administrators by finding certain aspects of our current gender- and marriage-based nationality laws unconstitutional.388 But even if it does so—and in the more probable event that it does not—officials in the political branches will continue to grapple with how to regulate derivative citizenship and immigration preferences that are premised on the parent-child relationship.389 Legislators will be confronted with proposals to grant citizenship to Amerasian children of American soldiers and to expand the geographical reach of immigration preferences currently given to some Amerasian children.390 In their everyday work, administrators will exercise discretion in interpreting parent-child derivative citizenship statutes and other laws that recognize the parent-child relationship for immigration and naturalization preferences. Federal judges will sit in review of those determinations and will be confronted with a host of statutes that make birth status a factor in determining an individual’s membership in the polity. Government attorneys will be called on to defend those laws against challenges alleging interpretive errors and constitutional violations. Whatever the institutional context, and whatever the particular issue, the history provided here suggests that officials charged with these tasks would do well to reconsider the commonplace—but oversimplified—understanding that derivative citizenship laws operate to ensure “family unity.” Such laws, and the principles and processes used to implement them, do not simply incorporate pre-existing notions of “family” in drawing lines between citizen and noncitizen. Rather, officials borrow, adapt, and reformulate family law principles to determine what relationships count for membership in the polity. In that process, officials’ conceptions of what counts as a family have been shaped by gender-traditional conceptions of the parent-child relationship that, in turn, have been—and may continue to be—used to shape the ethno-racial composition of the polity. Like their predecessors, modern jurists, administrators, and judges are engaged in an ongoing nation-building project of the most fundamental sort. How they enlist the family in the furtherance of that project need not be determined by the choices of their predecessors.