Casey and the Clinic Closings: When “Protecting Health” Obstructs Choice
abstract. We offer a fresh understanding of how the Supreme Court’s abortion jurisprudence addresses laws that invoke not potential life, but women’s health as a reason to single out abortion for burdensome regulation that has the effect of closing clinics. The current wave of health-justified restrictions—including laws that require abortion providers to secure admitting privileges at nearby hospitals or to become the functional equivalents of hospitals themselves—is destroying the clinic infrastructure on which women depend in order to exercise their constitutional right to end a pregnancy.
How should judges evaluate the states’ claims that such laws protect women’s health? We argue that such laws must actually serve the ends claimed for them if they are not to circumvent constitutional limits on the means by which states can protect unborn life. Careful judicial scrutiny is essential to vindicate values at the core of the Court’s decisions in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey and Gonzales v. Carhart.
We ground our argument in the principles of the undue burden standard as explained in Casey and applied there and later in Carhart. Casey modified Roe v. Wade to provide that from the beginning of pregnancy, states may protect two interests, unborn life and women’s health. States may express a preference for childbirth by trying to persuade a woman, through a twenty-four hour waiting period and the provision of information, to forgo abortion. But states cannot express a preference for childbirth in ways that obstruct women from acting on their constitutionally protected choice.
Casey and Carhart allow the government to express respect for the dignity of human life by means that respect the dignity of women. Regulations that close clinics in the name of women’s health, but without health-related justification, do not persuade: they prevent. In adopting such regulations, states—along with the courts that defer to them—violate the principle at the core of the Supreme Court’s protection for the abortion right.
authors. Linda Greenhouse is the Joseph Goldstein Lecturer in Law, Yale Law School. Reva B. Siegel is the Nicholas deB. Katzenbach Professor of Law, Yale Law School. For comments on the manuscript, we thank Jack Balkin, Walter Dellinger, Elizabeth Deutsch, Neal Devins, Michael Dorf, Cary Franklin, Dawn Johnsen, Douglas NeJaime, Robert Post, Neil Siegel, Priscilla Smith, and participants in faculty workshops at Yale Law School and the University of Texas at Austin School of Law. We are indebted to Elizabeth Dervan, Olivia Horton, Emma Roth, and Rachel Tuchman for excellent research assistance.
Many recently enacted
laws restrict abortion not in the name of protecting unborn life, but in the
name of protecting women’s health. States require that doctors who perform
abortions have admitting privileges at nearby hospitals or require that
abortion clinics be outfitted as “ambulatory surgical centers.”1
These new laws single out abortion for burdensome, health-justified restrictions
not imposed on other medical procedures of similar risk.2 As legislators know or suspect, these requirements
are unattainable for many abortion providers.3
As a result, these restrictive laws are forcing large numbers of abortion
clinics to close their doors.4 Before Texas
intensified its regulation of abortion providers through changes in its
admitting privileges and ambulatory surgical center laws, there were forty-one
clinics remaining in the state; enforcing the new law would close approximately
three-fourths of them.5 Judges who strike
down6 and who uphold7 these restrictions all cite as authority the
same Supreme Court decision from nearly a quarter century ago: Planned Parenthood of Southeastern
Pennsylvania v. Casey.8 This is not as surprising as it might at
first seem. Casey was crafted by
moderates responding to concerns raised both by those who wanted to overturn Roe v. Wade9and those who wanted to preserve
constitutional protections for the abortion right.10 The framework these Justices crafted allowed
states more latitude to restrict abortion in the interest of protecting
potential life, but only as long as women could make the ultimate decision
whether to continue a pregnancy. Casey has
now been the law of the land longer than the unmodified Roe itself. Fifteen years after Casey,
a different majority—while more skeptical of the abortion
right—nonetheless applied the Casey
framework in upholding the Partial Birth Abortion Ban Act in Gonzales v. Carhart.11 In what follows, we
seek to understand how Casey
addresses laws that invoke not potential life—the interest at stake in Carhart—but women’s health as a
reason to single out abortion for burdensome regulation that closes clinics. A
sharp circuit conflict over how judges are to evaluate health-justified
restrictions on abortion has placed the issue on the Supreme Court’s docket in Whole Woman’s Health v. Hellerstedt.12 Some circuits read Casey and Carhart to
require courts to examine whether health-justified regulations actually and
effectively serve health-related ends. Others construe the cases to prohibit
judicial inquiry of this kind and mandate judicial deference to the states’
claims.13 We argue that Casey requires scrutiny of
health-justified restrictions to ensure that they actually and effectively
advance health-related ends and do not protect potential life in a manner the
Constitution prohibits. We ground this argument in an understanding of the
constitutional values at Casey’s
core. Casey both modified and affirmed Roe. Casey gave states
more latitude to protect potential life but only so long as states employed
means that respect women’s dignity: “[T]he means chosen by the State to further
the interest in potential life must be calculated to inform the woman’s free
choice, not hinder it”14 and cannot impose an “undue burden” on the
abortion decision.15 These values at Casey’s core should guide review of health-justified restrictions
on abortion. When states single out abortion for burdensome health regulations,
courts must confirm that the laws actually serve health-related ends and do not
instead provide a backdoor way of protecting potential life. Scrutinizing the
facts that justify laws targeting abortion for onerous health restrictions thus
serves a crucial anticircumvention function: it ensures that legislatures do
not employ health restrictions on abortion to protect unborn life by
unconstitutional means. Preserving the distinction between abortion
restrictions that protect women’s health and abortion restrictions that protect
unborn life secures constitutional protection for women’s dignity. Our reading of Casey thus generates a fresh approach to
health-justified restrictions on abortion, sometimes called “TRAP laws”
(targeted regulation of abortion providers).16 States are enacting a variety of laws that
impose special health restrictions on abortion—whether expressly or
impliedly on the ground that abortion is “exceptional” because it involves the
unborn.17 States play an important role in protecting
public health. But with an understanding of the protection that Casey provides for women’s choices, it
becomes clear why states cannot single out abortion for onerous health
restrictions not imposed on other procedures of similar or greater risk. Such
laws may protect the unborn in ways that Casey
prohibits.18 The undue burden
framework is the gateway for making these determinations. The undue burden
inquiry examines a law’s purpose and its effects, and courts must attend to
both.19 A weak factual basis for the health interest
asserted may supply objective evidence of a purpose to impose a substantial
obstacle to women seeking an abortion.20 Examining the factual basis of a
health-justified abortion restriction is also important in evaluating the law’s
effects. Considering the extent to which a law advances the state’s interest in
protecting a woman’s health is crucial in determining whether the burden it
imposes on women’s choices is warranted or “undue.”21 In a series of recent
judgments, courts have emphasized that Casey
requires inquiry into the facts that justify laws targeting abortion for
onerous health restrictions,22 but the Fifth Circuit expressly rejected
this view23 in the Texas case now in the Supreme Court, Whole Woman’s Health v. Hellerstedt.24 The Fifth Circuit
asserted that it is wholly improper for judges to examine the factual basis of
the state’s claim that a restriction on abortion promotes women’s health.25 The circuit applied deferential rational-basis
review, crediting without probing the state’s claim to regulate in the
interests of women’s health. To justify its use of hyperdeferential rational-basis
review, the Fifth Circuit invoked Gonzales
v. Carhart, the Supreme Court’s 2007 decision that upheld the Federal
Partial Birth Abortion Ban Act.26 But Carhart does not require judicial
deference to the state’s health justifications for closing Texas clinics as the
Fifth Circuit asserts. Very different kinds of abortion restrictions are at
stake. Carhart concerned a law
enacted to protect potential life, not women’s health.27 The law did not prohibit the “usual” method
for performing second-trimester abortions, but one less commonly employed.28 The law did not restrict access to abortion
before viability and closed no clinics. As the majority emphasized, “Alternatives
are available to the prohibited procedure.”29 As importantly, Carhart itself applied Casey’s undue burden standard and
insisted that “[t]he Court retains an independent constitutional duty to review
factual findings where constitutional rights are at stake.”30 In determining whether the ban on a
particular method of later-term abortion required a health exception, the Court
reviewed and rejected multiple findings of fact by Congress31: “Uncritical deference to Congress’ factual
findings in these cases is inappropriate.”32
Accordingly, the Fifth Circuit’s decision flouted not only Casey, but Carhart as
well in reasoning about the review of abortion restrictions as ordinary social
and economic legislation unconnected to constitutional rights.33 Our analysis proceeds
in two parts. In Part I, we develop a framework for analyzing health-justified
restrictions on the abortion right that is grounded in an understanding of the
core principles animating the Casey-Carhart line of cases. After developing this
approach to the health-justified restrictions on abortion known as TRAP laws,
we turn in Part II to contemporary litigation over admitting privileges
requirements for abortion providers, the most recent effort to restrict access
to abortion in the name of women’s health. We argue that courts applying both
the purpose and the effects prongs of the undue burden standard must examine
whether a health-justified abortion restriction actually and effectively serves
the state’s asserted health interests. Constitutional guarantees for dignity
require active review of this kind. In this Part, we
return to Casey and examine the
values that guided the Court’s decision in that case. We then draw on this
understanding of the constitutional values at the core of Casey to build a framework for reviewing health-justified
restrictions on abortion. In Casey, Justices who sought to reaffirm
and modify Roe prevailed over those
Justices who wanted either to reverse or to preserve Roe.34
Chief Justice Rehnquist, along with Justices Scalia and Thomas, failed in their
effort to replace Roe’s strict-scrutiny
standard with rational-basis review of abortion restrictions.35
Roe’s author, Justice Blackmun, also
failed in his effort to maintain strict scrutiny and to preserve the trimester
framework, which prohibited government from restricting abortion to protect
potential life until the interest was deemed compelling at fetal viability, in
the third trimester of pregnancy.36
What emerged, in an opinion jointly written by Justices O’Connor, Kennedy, and
Souter, was the undue burden standard—a standard that reaffirmed and
modified Roe. The authors of the
joint opinion addressed a nation polarized over abortion, acknowledged core
commitments of Roe’s critics and
proponents, and integrated these competing commitments into the new undue
burden framework. Criticizing Roe’s
strict scrutiny of previability abortion restrictions on the ground that it
“undervalues the State’s interest in the potential life within the woman,”37 the joint opinion asserted that the state’s
“profound interest in potential life”38
offered a reason for regulation of abortion throughout
pregnancy. But the joint opinion nonetheless imposed constitutional limits
on the means by which government can
protect its interest in potential life: “[T]he State may take measures to
ensure that the woman’s choice is informed, and measures designed to advance
this interest will not be invalidated as long as their purpose is to persuade
the woman to choose childbirth over abortion.”39 While government can restrict access to
abortion in the interest of persuading a woman to continue a pregnancy, it
cannot do so by means that impose an “undue burden” on a woman’s decision. The
joint opiniondefined an “undue
burden” as “a state regulation [that] has the purpose or effect of placing a
substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion of a nonviable
fetus.”40 It explained: “A statute with this purpose
is invalid because the means chosen by
the State to further the interest in potential life must be calculated to
inform the woman’s free choice, not hinder it.”41In this way, a majority of the Casey Court—the three authors of
the joint opinion and the two Justices who refused to modify Roe’s trimester framework42—reaffirmed
the Constitution’s protection for a woman’s decision whether to carry a
pregnancy to term.43 A different majority of the Court—the
three authors of the joint opinion and the four Justices who would have
construed Roe in a rational-basis
framework—allowed regulation of a woman’s decision whether to carry a
pregnancy to term in ways that Roe
had previously barred.44 From the struggle
within the Court thus emerged a holding that respects both a woman’s
constitutionally protected right to decide whether to continue a pregnancy and the government’s interest in
persuading her to do so. Where Roe forbade
all efforts to protect potential life before the point of fetal viability,45 Casey
permits government efforts to persuade a woman to choose childbirth beginning
in the earliest stages of pregnancy—so long as the government protects
potential life by means that do not unduly burden a woman’s right to make “the
ultimate decision” about whether to carry a pregnancy to term.46 This limitation is
crucial. It authorizes the government to protect potential life by means that
recognize and preserve women’s dignity: “These matters, involving the most
intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central
to personal dignity and autonomy, are central to the liberty protected by the
Fourteenth Amendment.”47
The Court thus designed Casey’s undue
burden framework to give legal form to two values—potential life and the dignity of women—and to
guide the coordination of these values48: “The joint opinion adopts an undue burden
framework that allows government to regulate abortion in ways that respect the
dignity of life, so long as the regulation respects the dignity of women.”49 It is because Casey vindicates multiple constitutional values that the government
is limited in the ways it can protect potential life. If government wants to
protect unborn life, it has to respectfully enlist women in this project and
cannot simply commandeer women’s lives for these purposes. In this way, the
joint opinion structured the undue burden standard as a framework in which
Americans might negotiate the conflict over abortion so deeply dividing the
nation. The Court allowed the community to give voice to deeply held
antiabortion sentiment while nonetheless insisting that the Constitution
protects a woman’s right to make her choice. These dual concerns guided the joint
opinion’s application of the undue burden standard to the provisions of the
Pennsylvania statute at issue in the case. In reviewing
Pennsylvania’s restrictions on abortion, Casey
dealt principally with regulations justified as protecting unborn life. We
begin by examining these more familiar portions of the decision and show how
the Court’s application of the undue burden standard requires that any effort
to protect unborn life use dignity-respecting modes of persuading women. We
then turn to a short section of the Casey
decision that upholds recordkeeping requirements as promoting women’s health.
Few attend to this portion of the opinion, but it is an integral part of the
undue burden framework and illustrates how courts ought to evaluate
restrictions that claim a health-based rationale. Pennsylvania’s
Abortion Control Act of 198250
promoted the state’s interest in potential life in several ways. The first was
a counseling requirement directing doctors to provide information about the
abortion procedure, the relative risks of abortion and childbirth, embryonic
and fetal development, and available resources should the woman choose to carry
the pregnancy to term.51 In the years before Casey, laws requiring statements intended to discourage abortion
had been held unconstitutional in the 1983 decision, City of Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, Inc.,52 as well as in a subsequent decision, Thornburgh v. American College of
Obstetricians & Gynecologists.53 The Court had held that such efforts at
dissuasion improperly deterred women in the exercise of a constitutionally
protected choice and interfered with the physician-patient relationship.54 Assuming that the
Pennsylvania statute required “the giving of truthful, nonmisleading
information,”55 Casey overturned
those precedents in significant part. The controlling joint opinion of Justices
O’Connor, Kennedy, and Souter said: “[W]e permit a State to further its
legitimate goal of protecting the life of the unborn by enacting legislation
aimed at ensuring a decision that is mature and informed, even when in so doing
the State expresses a preference for childbirth over abortion.”56
The Court reasoned that the decision remained the woman’s because, although the
state may have engaged in directive counseling at odds with normal
informed-consent practice,57 it did not supply false or misleading
information. The Court thus understood the state to vindicate its interest in
protecting unborn life by means consistent with the dignity of women. The second
Pennsylvania regulation the Court reviewed required a woman to wait twenty-four
hours after receiving the information about fetal development before she could
proceed with an abortion. Again the Court balanced the extent to which the
regulation advanced the state’s interest in protecting potential life against
the burden it imposed on a woman’s choice to end a pregnancy. Whether this
regulation imposed an undue burden was “a closer question,” the joint opinion
said, given that it required an additional doctor visit and would predictably
lead to additional cost and travel time.58
But “[t]he idea that important decisions will be more informed and deliberate
if they follow some period of reflection does not strike us as unreasonable,”
the opinion said.59 The Court allowed the state to impose modest
costs and burdens on the exercise of choice as
incidental effects of the state’s efforts
to persuade.60 “What is at stake is the woman’s right to
make the ultimate decision, not a right to be insulated from all others in
doing so.”61
Unlike Roe and the Akron and Thornburgh decisions, Casey
recognizes a community interest in dissuading women from choosing abortion and
authorizes states to facilitate that effort, even if it imposes modest
additional costs. States may engage women in conversation with the community
that seeks to change her mind, so long as they do so in ways that do not unduly
burden or obstruct her ultimate choice.62 In this respect as well, Casey understands the state to vindicate
its interest in protecting unborn life by means consistent with the dignity of
women. The third significant
regulation the Court considered in Casey was
the requirement for a married woman to notify her husband before obtaining an
abortion: doctors who provided an abortion without receiving a signed statement
to that effect would lose their license and would be liable to the husband for
damages. The Court concluded that the burden imposed by this requirement was
undue. At least two different kinds of considerations informed this conclusion.
First, the state had structured the decision-making process in a way that
risked endangering those women who would not voluntarily discuss the decision
with their husbands as, the Court observed, the overwhelming majority of women
do63: “We must not blind ourselves to the fact
that the significant number of women who fear for their safety and the safety
of their children are likely to be deterred from procuring an abortion as
surely as if the Commonwealth had outlawed abortion in all cases.”64 But the fact that the
decision-making process was structured to expose women seeking an abortion to
the risk of domestic violence was not the only constitutional flaw in the
spousal-notice requirement. In a remarkable four-page discussion, the Court
explained that the state could not vindicate its interest in protecting
potential life by requiring a woman to notify her husband before obtaining an abortion
because structuring the decision-making process in this way reflected and
perpetuated a long-standing, but now unconstitutional, understanding of the
marital relationship.65 “The husband’s interest in the life of the
child his wife is carrying does not permit the State to empower him with this
troubling degree of authority over his wife. The contrary view leads to
consequences reminiscent of the common law.”66 Casey
prohibits the state from requiring a woman to place her constitutionally
protected decision in her husband’s hands, even to save potential life;
instead, it requires the state to save potential life only by means that
respect women’s dignity. “A State may not give to a man the kind of dominion
over his wife that parents exercise over their children.”67 These passages of Casey do more than prohibit the
government from coercing women into continuing a pregnancy. Casey goes farther and limits the manner
in which the government may persuade women to continue a pregnancy. For
example, Casey allows the government
to dissuade women from choosing abortion, but only by providing information
that is “truthful” and “nonmisleading.”68 The government may not provide a woman false
or misleading information that might persuade her to continue a pregnancy,69 presumably because it would transform the
woman into the government’s instrument for childbearing. In barring this mode
of persuasion, Casey prohibits the
government from protecting potential life through means that deny women liberty
and equality. A principled understanding of this kind also led the Court to
strike down the spousal-notice provision. The government may not require a
woman to tell her husband of her decision to end a pregnancy, even if it begins
a conversation that saves a potential life, because persuasion under these
conditions perpetuates the husband’s historic forms of authority over his wife.70 Casey holds
that governments may not structure the decision-making process in this way,
even in nonabusive relationships, because it denies women liberty and equality.71 These different applications of the undue
burden framework show Casey’s core
values at work: the government may persuade women to forego abortion and thus
to protect potential life—but only if the government employs modes of
persuasion that are, in the Court’s view, consistent with the dignity of women. In reviewing the
Pennsylvania statute, Casey addresses
health-justified regulation of abortion as well as fetal-protective
restrictions. The joint opinion begins its discussion of how Casey governs the regulation of abortion
with a statement of principles setting forth how its undue burden standard
separately applies to laws promoting each of these state interests.72
The joint opinion makes clear that some health-justified regulations are
permissible, while others are not: As with any medical procedure, the State may enact
regulations to further the health or safety of a woman seeking an abortion.
Unnecessary health regulations that have the purpose or effect of presenting a
substantial obstacle to a woman seeking an abortion impose an undue burden on
the right.73 The Court thus allows
regulation of abortion in the interest of protecting women’s health to the
extent that it is consistent with ordinary medical practice (“as with any
medical procedure”).74 But the Court prohibits as an undue burden
health-justified regulations that are “unnecessary” and have the “purpose or
effect” of making access to abortion substantially more difficult.75
As we discuss below, singling out abortion for onerous regulation not applied
to other medical procedures of similar risk is thus suspect in this framework.76 A final section of
the joint opinion applies these principles to the one provision of the
Pennsylvania statute at issue that regulated abortion in the interests of
public health. The Pennsylvania law required providers to report information to
the state about their practice of abortion.77 The Court viewed Pennsylvania’s reporting
requirements as protecting women’s health, distinguishing that interest from the
state’s interest in protecting potential life by dissuading women from ending a
pregnancy: Although [the
requirements] do not relate to the
State’s interest in informing the woman’s choice, they do relate to health.
The collection of information with respect to actual patients is a vital
element of medical research, and so it cannot be said that the requirements
serve no purpose other than to make abortions more difficult. Nor do we find
that the requirements impose a substantial obstacle to a woman’s choice. At
most they might increase the cost of some abortions by a slight amount. While
at some point increased cost could become a substantial obstacle, there is no
such showing on the record before us.78 In this passage, Casey discusses how the undue burden
analysis applies to restrictions on abortion justified on the grounds, not of
protecting unborn life, but of protecting women’s health. In applying undue
burden analysis, the Court separately considers both the purpose and effect of
the regulation. In this passage, it is clear that a regulation enacted for the
putative purpose of protecting women’s health must in fact promote health to justify imposing increased costs on the
practice of abortion. A restriction on abortion enacted for the claimed purpose
of protecting women’s health is not constitutional if it “serve[s] no purpose
other than to make abortions more difficult.”79 But the Court does not examine purpose as
the sole criterion of constitutionality. The undue burden framework is equally
concerned with effects, leading the Court to inquire whether the reporting
requirement “impose[s] a substantial obstacle to a woman’s choice.”80 The Court allows regulation that promotes
health, even if the health regulation had the incidental effect of increasing
abortion’s cost “by a slight amount”—reserving the question of the
conditions under which increased costs become a “substantial obstacle.”81 Few have engaged
seriously with these passages discussing the application of undue burden
analysis to abortion restrictions enacted in the interest of protecting women’s
health as distinct from protecting fetal life.82
In what follows, we discuss the constitutional values and practical
considerations that might guide courts reviewing health-justified restrictions
on abortion, known as TRAP laws. Casey applies the
same undue burden framework to restrictions on abortion enacted in the interest
of protecting both potential life and women’s health. Yet, as we show, Casey requires applying undue burden
with attention to the differences between these two regulatory interests. In discussing the
application of the undue burden standard to health-justified restrictions on
abortion, Casey expresses concern
about health restrictions that are needed and those that are “unnecessary” or
pretextual.83 What might prompt this concern? When the
Court cautions against “[u]nnecessary health regulations”84 or health-justified restrictions that “serve
no purpose other than to make abortions more difficult,”85 the Court seems to be concerned about
legislative subterfuge: while talking in terms of women’s health, the
legislature may be trying to make access to abortions “more difficult” to
protect unborn life. Presumably it is the effort to evade constitutional
restrictions on the means by which government may protect unborn life that
would animate subterfuge of this kind. Recall that Casey imposes constitutional limits on the means by which
government can protect its interest in potential life: “[T]he State may take
measures to ensure that the woman’s choice is informed, and measures designed
to advance this interest will not be invalidated as long as their purpose is to persuade the woman to choose childbirth over abortion.”86 To preserve Casey’s core protection for a woman’s
decision, judges have to review health-justified restrictions on abortion in
order to ensure that they actually serve health-related ends and do not instead
protect potential life by unconstitutional means—that is, by obstructing a
woman’s access to abortion without attempting to reason with her about her decision. Yet how are judges to
distinguish between constitutional and constitutionally suspect forms of health
regulation? States are, of course, entitled to regulate the practice of
medicine as a matter of their police power,87 and judges, as a longstanding matter of
federalism, will be loath to interfere with that prerogative. For example, five
years after Casey, the Court in Mazurek v. Armstrong, a brief per curiam
opinion, upheld a Montana law providing that only a doctor could perform an
abortion.88 The Court emphasized that physician-only
requirements of this kind had been sustained in its prior cases, including both
Roe and Casey.89 As the regulation at issue in Mazurek would not force any woman “to
travel to a different facility,” the Court judged its effects minimal.90 The Court declined to find Montana’s
physician-only requirement unconstitutional in purpose in light of the Supreme
Court’s several cases sanctioning physician-only requirements, the
requirement’s minimal effects on abortion access, and the fact that similar
rules existed in forty other states.91 But at some point the
state’s police power may be exercised in such a way as to violate a
constitutionally protected right. Casey
itself seems to offer some guidance for courts in distinguishing between
regulations of the practice of medicine that are a legitimate exercise of the
police power and regulations of the practice of medicine that may run afoul of
a constitutional right. In upholding Pennsylvania’s reporting requirement, the
Court emphasizes that “[t]he collection of information with respect to actual
patients is a vital element of medical research.”92 The Court reasons that the reporting
requirement conforms to the general regulation of the practice of medicine
outside the abortion context, and that benchmark seems to guide the Court in
upholding the law against constitutional challenge.93 The reporting
requirements upheld in Casey differ
in this important respect from TRAP laws enacted across the nation that target
abortion providers for burdensome regulation.94
Such regulations impose requirements on abortion providers that are not imposed
on other medical practices of similar or even greater risk.95 It is increasingly common for state health
and safety laws to single out abortion in various contexts—including the
licensing of clinics and the regulation of practices such as telemedicine,
admitting privileges, and prescribing drugs off-label—and judges have
raised concerns about this differential treatment as an indicator of unnecessary
regulation and potential unconstitutionality.96 What does Casey have to say about abortion
exceptionalism of this kind? Judges differ profoundly in their understanding of
how Casey’s undue burden framework
applies to laws that single out abortion for health-justified restrictions. A
debate among judges on the Fourth Circuit illustrates the nature of this
disagreement. At issue was the constitutionality of a South Carolina law that
targeted physicians’ offices and medical clinics performing five or more
first-trimester abortions a month with special licensure and operational
requirements.97 The District Court struck down the
regulations as imposing an undue burden. The requirements were “medically
unnecessary,” the court said, imposing “costs and other burdens” that were “not
justified by the stated interest in protecting the health of the women
undergoing the procedure.”98 The Fourth Circuit reversed, over a dissent
objecting that the state law “singles out and places additional and onerous
burdens upon abortion providers which are neither justified by actual
differences nor rationally related to the state’s legitimate interest in
protecting the health and safety of women seeking first-trimester abortions.”99
The majority upheld the regulations as protecting women’s health and explained
the justification for treating abortion differently: It is regrettable that our good colleague in dissent
would rule on the basis that abortion is like any other simple medical
procedure that is directed at injury or disease. Thought of in this way, it is
understandable that he, like the district court, might find many of South
Carolina’s regulations unnecessary. Why
have inspections, keep records, and minimize the medical risks for only the
abortion procedure, when such a protocol is not mandated for comparable medical
practices addressing injury and disease? But the importance of the deeply
divided societal debate over the morality of abortion and the weight of the
interests implicated by the decision to have an abortion can hardly be
overstated. As humankind is the most gifted of living creatures and the
mystery of human procreation remains one of life’s most awesome events, so it
follows that the deliberate interference with the process of human birth
provokes unanswerable questions, unpredictable emotions, and unintended social
and, often, personal consequences beyond simply the medical ones.100 As these unusually
frank judicial exchanges demonstrate, abortion exceptionalism denotes something
more than the fact of singling out abortion for special, health-justified
restrictions. Visible here, but more often submerged in neutral language, is
the notion that there is a special moral valence to abortion that, because it
concerns the unborn, warrants special forms of health regulation not imposed on
procedures of comparable risk. Setting the Fourth
Circuit’s opinion alongside Casey shows
how Casey rejects abortion
exceptionalism of this kind.101
Casey treats with utmost gravity the
state’s interest in regulating abortion in the interest of protecting unborn
life.102 It provides the community a means of
vindicating this interest: dissuading women from having an abortion. Yet the
Court does not permit regulation justified as protecting women’s health to
function as an additional means of protecting the interest in potential life. Casey allows health-justified regulation
of abortion where consistent with the ordinary regulation of the practice of
medicine. However, Casey objects to
“unnecessary” health regulation whose purpose or effect is to deter women from
acting on a decision to end a pregnancy: “As with any medical procedure, the
State may enact regulations to further the health or safety of a woman seeking
an abortion. Unnecessary health regulations that have the purpose or effect of
presenting a substantial obstacle to a woman seeking an abortion impose an
undue burden on the right.”103 As this passage
shows, the undue burden framework prohibits laws that single out abortion for
“unnecessary” health regulations that obstruct access to abortion. Under Casey, government may not mix regulatory
interests and use health-justified regulations to obstruct access to abortion
by nondissuasive means. For this reason, judicial scrutiny of the facts that
justify laws targeting abortion for onerous health restrictions is necessary to
prevent legislatures from circumventing constitutional limitations that protect
women’s dignity. In recent years,
states have enacted laws that impose increasingly burdensome health
restrictions on abortion providers not required of others who perform health-care
procedures of similar risk.104 Some laws require providers to acquire
admitting privileges at hospitals that for reasons of politics, religion, or
stigma want nothing to do with doctors who perform abortions;105 others require the clinics to be retrofitted
as small hospitals at unaffordable expense.106
The practical impact of these health restrictions appears to be much greater
than that of fetal-protective laws designed to dissuade women from having an
abortion; the latter communicate to one woman at a time the state’s message
that abortion is the wrong choice, while the former can shut down clinics, thus
impairing or preventing access altogether. In this way, the
recently enacted health restrictions dramatically shrink abortion providers’
infrastructure, closing clinics and disabling doctors from serving their
patients.107
For example, in overturning Mississippi’s admitting privileges law, the Fifth
Circuit concluded that the law imposed an undue burden because it would have
the effect of closing the sole remaining abortion clinic in the state.108
In Texas, the district court blocked House Bill 2 after observing that the
number of abortion clinics in the state had already shrunk from more than forty
to half that number since the law’s admitting privileges requirement took
effect in late 2013.109
On appeal, the Fifth Circuit largely reversed the district court’s injunction,
permitting a reduction in the number of clinics to “at least eight” in the state of Texas.110
Judge Posner, in affirming a preliminary injunction against Wisconsin’s
admitting privileges law, which gave doctors one weekend to come into
compliance, noted in his opinion for the Seventh Circuit that the law would
have shut down two of the state’s four abortion clinics.111
In Alabama, three of the state’s five abortion clinics sued to block the
state’s admitting privileges law, informing the district court that if the law
went into effect, they would be forced to stop performing abortions.112
Louisiana District Court Judge deGravelles issued a preliminary injunction of
the state’s admitting privileges requirement, finding that enforcement of the
law would leave four of the five clinics in the state without an abortion
provider and the last remaining clinic with only one provider.113 Key officials involved in enacting these laws expressed open
hostility to abortion, even as they claimed a health-protective purpose. Shortly
after the Texas admitting privileges and ambulatory surgical center bill was sent to the House, then-Lieutenant
Governor David Dewhurst tweeted a photo of a map that showed all of the
abortion clinics that would close as a result of the bill, writing: “We fought
to pass SB5 thru the Senate last night, & this is why!”114 Dewhurst quickly backpedaled, tweeting: “I
am unapologetically pro-life AND a strong supporter of protecting women’s
health. #SB5 does both.”115 Lawmakers have
offered similar observations in Mississippi, where an admitting privileges law
threatened to shut down the last clinic in the state. In a “state of the state”
speech delivered on the forty-first anniversary of Roe, Governor Phil Bryant said: I believe we have also done an admirable job in
protecting our children, both born and unborn. By strengthening the Child
Protection Act and by requiring that abortionists obtain admitting privileges
at local hospitals, we are protecting women’s health. But let me be clear, on
this unfortunate anniversary of Roe versus Wade, my goal is to end abortion in
Mississippi.116 It is unsurprising
that states enacting and defending admitting privilege statutes assert that the
laws protect women’s health.117
Acknowledging a fetal-protective justification for the laws—given the
laws’ role in forcing clinics to close—would plainly violate the
constitutional limits Casey imposes
on the means by which states can protect unborn life.118 In this Part, we
briefly examine the most recent health-justified restrictions on abortion. Our
focus is on the laws requiring abortion providers to have admitting privileges
at local hospitals. We begin by showing that these laws rest on highly contested
factual premises. Some but not all courts examine the state’s justifications
for health-related restrictions when applying Casey. Beginning with Judge Posner’s 2013 decision in Planned Parenthood of Wisconsin, Inc. v. Van
Hollen,119 some courts read Casey as requiring an inquiry into the question of whether a
health-justified regulation of abortion will actually protect women’s health.
The Fifth Circuit, by contrast, opposes judicial scrutiny of the state’s
claims, insisting instead on a rational-basis review of the state’s
justifications for enacting the regulation.120 We review the courts’ competing approaches
for their consistency with the Supreme Court’s decisions in Casey and Carhart. States claim to
protect women’s health by requiring abortion providers to have admitting
privileges at a local hospital.121 Yet there are deep questions about whether
evidence supports the alleged benefits to women’s health. Abortion during the
first trimester of pregnancy, when eighty-nine percent of abortions take place,122 is extremely safe, with complications that
require a hospital visit occurring in less than 0.05% of early abortions.123 Of this small number of complications, many
are minor, presenting symptoms similar to those of early miscarriage, which is
a common reason for emergency-room visits and a condition that emergency-room
physicians are accustomed to treating.124 Despite the safety of
abortion procedures, states single out abortion for restrictions not imposed on
procedures of comparable risk. In Texas, the district court found that at the
time of passage of the state law imposing admitting privilege and ambulatory
surgical center requirements on
abortion, “abortion in Texas was extremely safe with particularly low rates of
serious complications and virtually no deaths occurring on account of the
procedure. . . . [It was] much safer, in terms of minor and serious
complications, than many common medical procedures not subject to such intense
regulation and scrutiny.”125 (As the state’s safety record might suggest,
prior to passage of the Texas law, abortion procedures were already subject to
rigorous health regulation.)126
The district court found that, despite this safety record, the legislature had
singled out abortion clinics for restrictions that were not imposed on
facilities providing comparable medical services.127 In Wisconsin, the state stipulated before
trial that for no other outpatient procedures were doctors required to have
hospital admitting privileges.128
The state explained neither the reason for singling out abortion for special
treatment nor the rush to pass its law, which was enacted “precipitously” in
2013.129 In defending the need
for admitting privileges, states assert that the requirement serves important credentialing
and monitoring functions, assures necessary “continuity of care,” and prevents
patient abandonment.130
While the states’ claims imply that doctors who receive admitting privileges
are superior in quality, that is not necessarily the case. Requirements for
admitting privileges may have nothing to do with quality of care.131
Many hospitals condition the award of admitting privileges on a certain number
of patient admissions, setting quotas impossible for most abortion providers to
meet when their patients so rarely need hospital care.132 Hospitals may refuse to extend admitting
privileges to doctors who perform a procedure to which the hospital’s governing
body has religious objections,133
or may withhold admitting privileges for other unspecified reasons.134
Patient care is not likely to be improved by requirements that are medically
unnecessary and sufficiently burdensome to shut down the very facilities at
which patients seek care.135 A further concern
about the quality of the evidence supporting admitting privilege requirements
has emerged in recent litigation. An activist named Vincent Rue has organized
the set of witnesses who testify across state lines in support of the admitting
privilege statutes.136
(Decades ago, Rue played a central role in developing “post-abortion syndrome”
or “PAS,” the claim that abortion traumatizes and inflicts psychological harm
on women.)137 Rue not only recruits witnesses to appear in
court, but sometimes ghostwrites their testimony,138 and his conduct has drawn reproach from judges
in Alabama, Texas, and Wisconsin.139 For example, Judge Thompson, rejecting one
Rue-recruited expert, said, “Whether Anderson lacks judgment, is dishonest, or
is profoundly colored by his bias, his decision to adopt Rue’s supplemental
report and submit it to the court without verifying the validity of its
contents deprives him of credibility.”140 In the Texas case, Judge Yeakel had this to
say: The credibility and weight the court affords the
expert testimony of the State’s witnesses Drs. Thompson, Anderson, Kitz, and
Uhlenberg is informed by ample evidence that, at a very minimum, Vincent Rue,
Ph.D., a non-physician consultant for the State, had considerable editorial and
discretionary control over the contents of the experts’ reports and
declarations. The court finds that, although the experts testified that they
personally held the opinions presented to the court, the level of input exerted
by Rue undermines the appearance of objectivity and reliability of the experts’
opinions. Further, the court is dismayed by the considerable efforts the State
took to obscure Rue’s level of involvement with the experts’ contributions.141 How does the dispute
over the justification for admitting privileges laws arise in litigation over
the laws’ constitutionality? Factual questions concerning the health
justification of such laws are distinct from questions concerning their impact
on abortion access—the “effects” prong of the undue burden inquiry. Courts are divided
over the need to assess factual justifications for the restrictions. Led by the
Seventh Circuit, some courts require the state to demonstrate the factual basis
of its claim that restricting abortion promotes women’s health; these courts
apply undue burden analysis in a weighted balancing test that attends to the
strength of the state’s showing that the restriction achieves that goal.142
The Fifth Circuit, by contrast, asserts that it is wholly improper for judges
to examine the factual basis of the state’s claim that a restriction on
abortion promotes women’s health. The circuit applies deferential rational-basis
review, simply credits the state’s claim to regulate in the interests of
women’s health, and then determines whether the law’s impact creates a
substantial obstacle.143 In short, the Seventh Circuit reads Casey as requiring courts to evaluate
the factual basis of the state’s claim to restrict abortion to promote women’s
health; the Fifth Circuit reads Casey
to prohibit this very inquiry. In what follows, we contrast these two very
different approaches to applying undue burden analysis to health-justified
restrictions on abortion. The Seventh Circuit’s
approach to review of admitting privileges legislation, first articulated by
Judge Posner, makes factual support for the state’s health interest central in
applying the undue burden test. In December 2013, the Seventh Circuit affirmed
an order preliminarily enjoining enforcement of a recently enacted Wisconsin admitting
privileges requirement.144
Judge Posner observed that while the state justified the requirement solely on
the ground of protecting women’s health, the state’s lawyer at oral argument
“did not mention any medical or statistical evidence” and “[n]o documentation
of medical need for such a requirement was presented to the Wisconsin
legislature when the bill that became the law was introduced on June 4 of this
year.”145 The medical evidence was “feeble,” Judge
Posner said, “yet the burden [was] great.”146 He explained that the judge had to consider
the evidentiary basis of the state’s claim that it had health justifications
for restricting abortion when the judge applied the undue burden test: The cases that deal with abortion-related statutes
sought to be justified on medical grounds require not only evidence (here
lacking as we have seen) that the medical grounds are legitimate but also that
the statute not impose an “undue burden” on women seeking abortions. The
feebler the medical grounds, the likelier the burden, even if slight, to be
“undue” in the sense of disproportionate or gratuitous.147 Judge Posner derived
from Casey two crucially important
messages: that states seeking to justify a health-related restriction must
produce evidence supporting the health basis of their restriction, and that the
strength of this evidentiary showing is relevant in determining whether any
related burden on access is, in Casey’s
terms, undue. Judge Posner reaffirmed this understanding in a subsequent
opinion permanently enjoining enforcement of Wisconsin’s admitting privileges
law.148 Judge Posner’s
opinion adopting this weighted balancing test in Planned Parenthood of Wisconsin v. Van Hollen has proven
influential. Judge Thompson cited it in his Alabama admitting privileges decision
three months later, observing, “[I]t is not enough to simply note that the
State has a legitimate interest; courts must also examine the weight of the
asserted interest, including the extent to which the regulation in question
would actually serve that interest.”149 On this account, the “weight” of an interest
turns on a question of fact: how well the challenged regulation would in
fact—“actually”—advance the interest it is asserted to serve. Judge
Thompson explained that the court was to take the evidence the state amassed
justifying the regulation into account in applying the undue burden framework;
he reasoned that “the court examines the severity of obstacles created by the
regulation as well as the weight of the State’s justifications for the regulation,
and then determines whether the obstacle is more significant than is warranted
by the justifications.”150 Another recent
opinion requiring an inquiry into the factual basis for a health-justified
abortion restriction came from the Ninth Circuit in June 2014. In Planned Parenthood of Arizona v. Humble,
the panel preliminarily enjoined an Arizona law requiring doctors to use an
outdated protocol for administering the medication that causes an early term
abortion.151 States have increasingly attempted to curb
the growing popularity of medication abortion152
by forbidding doctors to deviate from the dosage on the FDA-approved
label—despite the fact that such “off-label” uses of approved medications
are common outside the abortion context,153
and the fact that the medical profession has concluded that, in this instance,
a smaller dose is safer and more effective.154 While we have not focused on the
medication-abortion controversy,155
Humble reviews a health-justified
restriction on abortion and so is directly relevant to our discussion. In Humble, the Ninth Circuit applies Casey with attention to the question of
whether restrictions on abortion are asserted to serve the state’s interest in
protecting fetal life or women’s health.156
In examining laws asserted to promote women’s health, the circuit employs a
weighted balancing test: [C]ompar[ing] the extent of the burden a law imposes
on a woman’s right to an abortion with the strength of the state’s
justification for the law . . . [t]he more substantial the burden, the stronger
the state’s justification for the law must be to satisfy the undue burden test;
conversely, the stronger the state’s justification, the greater the burden may
be before it becomes “undue.”157 Reviewing
Arizona’s restriction on medication abortion in Humble, Judge Fletcher observed that the Ninth Circuit’s approach
followed from Casey’s direction to
determine whether health regulations were “unnecessary,” and approvingly
referenced the framework Judge Posner had set forth in Van Hollen as “an approach much like ours”158: “The court in Van Hollen granted a preliminary injunction against the enforcement
of the Wisconsin law on the ground that ‘the medical grounds thus far presented
. . . are feeble, yet the burden great.’ Here, the ‘medical grounds thus far
presented’ are not merely ‘feeble.’ They are non-existent.”159 Judge Fletcher noted that “Arizona has
introduced no evidence that the law advances in any way its interest in women’s
health.”160 The Fifth Circuit’s
approach to applying Casey differs
dramatically. In a challenge to the Texas admitting privilege requirement in Abbott II,161
Judge Edith Jones asserted that she was following Casey’s undue burden framework, but she then invoked the Supreme
Court’s decision in Gonzales v. Carhart162to infuse the undue burden inquiry with rational-basis review.163
At issue was precisely the question we have been discussing: whether the undue
burden framework of Casey-Carhart requires judges to examine the factual basis
of a state’s claim to restrict abortion in the interest of protecting women’s
health. Judge Jones initially
characterized Carhart as “holding
that the State may ban certain abortion procedures and substitute others
provided that ‘it has a rational basis to act, and it does not impose an
undue burden.’”164
She then reversed the district court’s finding that the state’s admitting
privileges law had no rational relationship to protecting women’s health165
with a much more far-reaching claim
about the Casey-Carhart framework: Nothing in the Supreme Court’s abortion jurisprudence
deviates from the essential attributes of the rational basis test, which
affirms a vital principle of democratic self-government. It is not the courts’
duty to second guess legislative factfinding, “improve” on, or “cleanse” the
legislative process by allowing relitigation of the facts that led to the
passage of a law. . . . Under rational basis review, courts must presume that
the law in question is valid and sustain it so long as the law is rationally
related to a legitimate state interest. . . . As the Supreme Court has often
stressed, the rational basis test seeks only to determine whether any
conceivable rationale exists for an enactment . . . . A law “based on rational
speculation unsupported by evidence or empirical data” satisfies rational basis
review.166 In this remarkable
passage, the Fifth Circuit takes the language in Carhart that applies the undue burden test and uses it to
characterize the undue burden test as rational-basis review—the standard
of review championed by the dissenting
justices in Casey.167
Judge Jones suggests that it is beyond the proper role of a court in a
constitutional democracy to inquire into the factual basis of a legislature’s
claim that restricts the exercise of the abortion right: “Nothing in the
Supreme Court’s abortion jurisprudence deviates from the essential attributes
of the rational basis test, which affirms a vital principle of democratic
self-government.”168 She thereafter proceeds to reject the Van Hollen approach to applying undue
burden: “The first-step in the analysis of an abortion regulation, however, is rational basis review, not empirical basis review.”169 In so reasoning, the
Fifth Circuit breaks with the Seventh and Ninth Circuits, which, as we have
seen, understand the inquiry into the evidentiary basis of the state’s claim to
regulate in the interests of women’s health as
part of the undue burden inquiry. The Seventh and Ninth Circuits understand
it as part of the question of whether the health-justified law was “unnecessary”
and (un)warranted in light of the burdens it imposes on women’s access.170
In the Fifth Circuit, by contrast, a court has no reason to examine the state’s
factual support for a health-justified restriction on abortion because “[a] law
‘based on rational speculation unsupported by evidence or empirical data’
satisfies rational basis review.”171
The Fifth Circuit refuses to consider the strength of the state’s justification
for regulating as part of the undue burden inquiry.172 Judge Elrod explains
in the Fifth Circuit’s subsequent opinion in Whole Woman’s Health v. Lakey,173 admonishing the district court for
“evaluat[ing] whether the ambulatory surgical center provision would actually
improve women’s health and safety,” that “[i]n
our circuit we do not balance the wisdom or effectiveness of a law against the
burdens the law imposes.”174 Objecting that examining the factual basis
of the state’s claim to protect women’s health would “ratchet[] up rational basis review into a pseudo-strict-scrutiny
approach by examining whether the law advances the State’s asserted purpose,”
she reasons that “[u]nder our precedent, we have no authority by which to turn
rational basis into strict scrutiny under the guise of the undue burden inquiry.”175 The Fifth Circuit has recently reaffirmed
this line of cases, applying rational-basis review to the claim that Texas’s
interest in protecting women’s health justified enacting the law.176 Is a court required
to examine the factual basis of a health-related regulation, or is it forbidden
from doing so? Casey and Carhart offer a clear answer to the
question. In what follows we show how fundamentally the Fifth Circuit has
misapplied those decisions. The Fifth Circuit has
collapsed the Casey-Carhart framework into a form of rational-basis
review that accords virtually no protection to the abortion decision as a
constitutionally protected right. We show, first, that the Fifth Circuit’s use
of rational-basis review is inconsistent with the Court’s reasoning in Carhart. We then demonstrate that the
Fifth Circuit’s use of rational-basis review destroys the distinction between
the state’s interests in protecting potential life and its interest in women’s
health, and in so doing, permits states to violate the restrictions Casey imposes on the means by which the
state may protect unborn life.177 Finally, we show that the weighted balancing
test employed by the Seventh and the Ninth Circuits is faithful to
constitutional values underlying the Casey-Carhart framework, whereas the Fifth
Circuit’s rational-basis review is not. The Fifth Circuit’s
claims about rational basis are not entirely clear. In Abbott II, Judge Jones initially acknowledges that Carhart applied the undue burden
framework,178 but she thereafter characterizes the undue
burden framework as a rational-basis test,179 as does Judge Elrod in Whole Woman’s Health v. Lakey.180 The Fifth Circuit’s per curiam decision in Whole Woman’s Health v. Cole181 again goes out of its way to reaffirm Abbott II’s rational-basis reasoning.182 Sometimes the Fifth Circuit treats only the
question of whether an abortion restriction serves the interests of women’s
health as subject to rational-basis review.183 At other times, the circuit makes a broader
claim: that the entirety of the undue burden framework is a form of rational-basis review.184 Whichever account the circuit embraces, its
rational-basis claims flout both Casey
and Carhart. The Casey framework is not rational basis.
As we have observed, rational basis was the standard of review championed by
the dissenting justices in Casey.185 Nor did the Court’s ensuing decision in Carhart collapse the undue burden
framework into rational basis review. Without a doubt, the Carhart decision bitterly disappointed the Justices who most
fervently defended the abortion right.186 That said, even as the majority emphasized
the government’s interest in cultivating respect for unborn life, the Court
upheld the Partial Birth Abortion Ban Act on terms that accepted the continuing
authority of Casey’s undue burden
framework and the protection it provides for first- and second-trimester
abortions.187 It is true that the Carhart Court refers to rational
basis—as we have seen, in the very sentence in which the Court expressly
invokes the undue burden framework.188 Whatever Carhart’s
reference to “rational basis” means, it is not directing extravagant deference
to the legislature of the kind the Fifth Circuit requires. In Carhart itself, the Court does not
simply defer to Congress. Significantly, in upholding the Partial Birth
Abortion Ban Act, Justice Kennedy observes, “The Court retains an independent
constitutional duty to review factual findings where constitutional rights are
at stake . . . . Uncritical deference to Congress’ factual findings in these
cases is inappropriate.”189 The Carhart
Court probed and, in two instances, rejected congressional findings invoked by
the government as reasons for enacting the Partial Birth Abortion Ban Act.190
Probing Congress’s reasons behind enacting the challenged statute is not rational-basis
review of the kind that the Fifth Circuit mandates, especially when the Circuit
observed that “[a] law ‘based on rational speculation unsupported by evidence
or empirical data’ satisfies rational basis review.”191 In Carhart, the Court does employ a form of
deference—though not rational-basis review that swallows or supplants Casey’s undue burden framework. In Carhart,the Court rejects the argument that Congress was obliged to
provide a health exception to the banned procedure, concluding that the statute
withstood at least a facial challenge.192 The Court grounds this conclusion in the
district courts’ findings that medical opinion was divided on the need for such
an exception,193 reasoning that “[t]he Court has given state
and federal legislatures wide discretion to pass legislation in areas where
there is medical and scientific uncertainty.”194 The condition of medical uncertainty is
established through judicial review—in Carhart itself, this was done through the factfinding of the
district courts. In Whole Woman’s Health v. Cole, the Fifth
Circuit seizes on this language as additional warrant for judicial deference,
asserting that “medical uncertainty underlying a statute is for resolution by
legislatures, not the courts.”195 The Circuit is wrong to rely on this
language as it does. The medical uncertainty of which the Court spoke in Carhart was anchored in the factfinding
of the two district courts whose judgments were on review. By contrast, the
Fifth Circuit finds uncertainty by rejecting
the factfinding of the district court. In the Texas case, the district court
probed the justification of the legislature for enacting H.B. 2 and found no
credible evidence to support either the admitting privilege requirement or the ambulatory
surgical center requirement.196 The Fifth Circuit found uncertainty in the
record, rejecting the district court’s findings and instead crediting the
State’s contrary assertions.197 Throughout, the circuit court chastised the
district court, admonishing that “[i]t is not the courts’ duty to second guess
legislative factfinding, improve on, or cleanse the legislative process by
allowing relitigation of the facts that led to the passage of a law.”198 In short, the “uncertainty” the Fifth
Circuit finds to warrant deference to the legislature is produced in significant
part by deferring to the legislature. If appellate courts can justify deference
to the legislature by invoking medical uncertainty that is untethered from
facts found and credibility determinations made by the trial court,199
they can easily erode protections for constitutional rights. Whatever deference
Carhart might be read to warrant, it
cannot be the extravagant deference to the legislature that the Fifth Circuit
practices here. At root, the Fifth
Circuit’s extravagantly deferential “rational-basis” decisions err in reasoning
about the review of abortion restrictions as if they were ordinary social and
economic legislation unconnected to constitutional rights. The Circuit fails to
protect the decisional right the Casey-Carhart framework recognizes. States may have a
right to regulate the practice of abortion, but, even after Carhart, that prerogative is by no means
unconstrained or absolute. In Carhart,
the Court emphasized that Casey’s
undue burden standard “struck a balance” between protecting “the woman’s
exercise of the right to choose” and the ability of the state to “express
profound respect for the life of the unborn.”200 To preserve this balance and protect a
woman’s right to make “the ultimate decision”201 about whether to carry a pregnancy to term, Casey imposed constitutional limits on
the means by which the state could vindicate its interest in protecting
potential life.202 Government must persuade women to continue a
pregnancy; it cannot obstruct women’s access to abortion. As we have shown,
protecting the woman’s exercise of the right to choose requires judges sharply to
distinguish between restrictions on abortion asserted to protect women’s health
from those asserted to protect unborn life in order to ensure that state
efforts to protect unborn life remain dissuasive in form, as Casey requires. Judicial review that
probes the factual basis of the state’s claim to restrict abortion in the
interests of protecting women’s health thus protects the exercise of the
decisional right that Casey recognizes.
The Texas law
demonstrates how a state can enact weakly justified health restrictions on
abortion that obstruct women’s efforts to end a pregnancy in ways that do not
involve reasoning with women or attempting to dissuade them as Casey requires. Strikingly, as it
defended the Texas statute, the state offered a series of different
characterizations of its underlying justification, over time coming to describe
the admitting privileges law as protecting both
women’s health and unborn life.203
Judge Yeakel criticized the state for attempting to supplement
health-protective justifications with fetal-protective justifications,
reasoning that under Casey it was
unconstitutional for the state to protect unborn life by creating “obstacles to
previability abortion” rather than by counseling against the decision to seek
an abortion: The primary interest proffered for the act’s
requirements relate to concerns over the health and safety of women seeking
abortions in Texas. To the extent that the State argues that the act’s
requirements are motivated by a legitimate interest in fetal life, the court
finds those arguments misplaced. In
contrast to the regulations at issue in Casey, the act’s challenged requirements are solely targeted at regulating
the performance of abortions, not the decision to seek an abortion. Here,
the only possible gain realized in the interest of fetal life, once a woman has
made the decision to have a previability abortion, comes from the ancillary
effects of the woman’s being unable to obtain an abortion due to the obstacles
imposed by the act. The act creates
obstacles to previability abortion. It does not counsel against the decision to
seek an abortion.204 Judge
Yeakel thus understood that preserving Casey’s
framework requires first, distinguishing fetal-protective and health-protective
justifications for abortion restrictions, and second, probing the factual basis
of health-justified restrictions to ensure they serve health-related ends. In reversing Judge
Yeakel and rebuking him for examining the evidence that supported the state’s
claim to restrict abortion in the interests of protecting women’s health,205
Judge Elrod never responded to his objection that Texas was protecting
potential life by nondissuasive means, and was therefore violating Casey’s protection for women’s
decisional autonomy. The Fifth Circuit’s hyperdeferential practice of rational-basis
review expressly sanctions this fusion and scrambling of rationales. One could explain the
Fifth Circuit’s failure to protect women’s decisional autonomy as an expression
of deference to the state’s interest in protecting potential life. But one
could also explain the Fifth Circuit’s failure to protect women’s decisional
autonomy as an expression of a very particular view of women, one that elevates
their reproductive capacity over other attributes of personhood in an explicit
manner not seen in a judicial opinion for many years. When the parties in Abbott II called upon the Fifth Circuit
to differentiate review of abortion laws enacted to protect potential life and
to protect women’s health, Judge Jones refused, reasoning that “no such
bifurcation has been recognized by the Supreme Court.”206 She then asserted that the two interests cannot be bifurcated because laws that
protect a woman’s health protect her as
a childbearer: “[T]he state’s regulatory interest cannot be bifurcated simply
between mothers’ and children’s health; every limit on abortion that furthers a
mother’s health also protects any existing children and her future ability to
bear children even if it facilitates a particular abortion.”207 As the Ninth Circuit
understands but the Fifth Circuit does not, Casey’s
undue burden framework requires
courts to differentiate the state’s interests in protecting potential life and
women’s health.208 In protecting women’s health, the government
is not protecting potential life, a
conflation of interests the Fifth Circuit sanctioned in Abbott II and the Fourth Circuit sanctioned in Greenville.209 The government has long regulated women’s
conduct with the view that women are defined by their role in childbearing, an
understanding the Court endorsed more than a century ago in Muller v. Oregon.210But Casey
rejects this traditional view of women211 and instead insists that respect for women’s
dignity requires giving women control over the decision whether to become a
mother.212 That is why
the undue burden test restricts the means by which the government may protect
unborn life: the government cannot prevent women from obtaining an abortion but
instead must, if it chooses, seek to persuade women to bring a pregnancy to
term through the provision of truthful, nonmisleading information. As courts outside the
Fifth Circuit understand, judicial review that differentiates between the
state’s interest in protecting potential life and the state’s interest in
protecting women’s health secures Casey’s
protection for women’s decisional autonomy. Ensuring that health-justified
restrictions actually and effectively serve health-related ends is, of course,
also required by Casey’s language
prohibiting “unnecessary” health laws that impose “undue burdens.”213 Outside the Fifth
Circuit, proper judicial review under Casey
takes at least two forms. First, judges look to weak evidence in support of a
health-restriction in finding violations of the undue burden standard’s purpose
prong.214 For example, in Wisconsin, Judge Conley
ruled that the state’s admitting privileges law was enacted for the improper
purpose of imposing a substantial obstacle to obtaining an abortion.215 He rested this judgment on classic indicia
of pretext: the state introduced no evidence in support of the admitting
privileges law, imposed the requirement with one weekend’s notice, and targeted
abortion providers only, exempting procedures of greater risk.216
In affirming the trial court’s finding of a purpose to impose a substantial
obstacle, Judge Posner additionally emphasized the fact that the state had
singled out abortion for health requirements that it hadn’t imposed on
procedures of greater risk: Opponents of abortion reveal their true objectives
when they procure legislation limited to a medical
procedure—abortion—that rarely produces a medical emergency. A
number of other medical procedures are far more dangerous to the patient than
abortion, yet their providers are not required to obtain admitting privileges
anywhere, let alone within 30 miles of where the procedure is performed.217 Inconsistent
conduct, singling out abortion, or weak factual support for the restriction can
supply objective evidence of unconstitutional purpose. (“Wisconsin appears to
be indifferent to complications of any other outpatient procedures, even when
they are far more likely to produce complications than abortions are.”)218 Yet proof of
collective purpose is difficult—even when purpose is not defined by
difficult-to-satisfy liability rules of the kind that prevail in the equal
protection area219—because judges are generally reticent
to accuse state legislators of bad faith.220 This problem seems especially acute in the
abortion context. Even if the legislators who enact a health-justified
restriction on abortion publicly announce their aim to limit access to the
procedure,221 judges may understand such legislators to
act for benign rather than bigoted ends, a difference that, for many, may
mitigate the legislators’ choice of unconstitutional means—especially if
the purpose of the law is considered without attention to the law’s impact on
women. Considering the
factual support for a health restriction under the effects prong of the undue
burden inquiry avoids some of the difficulties of a purpose-focused approach.
The weighted balancing test that Judge Posner employed in applying the undue
burden framework to health-justified restrictions can be understood as smoking
out unconstitutional motivation without ever requiring judges to identify direct
evidence of illicit purpose. Examining the facts that justify a health
regulation is also important in evaluating the law’s effects. Considering the
extent to which a law advances the state’s interest in protecting health is
crucial in determining whether the burden it imposes on women’s choice is
warranted: “The feebler the medical grounds, the likelier the burden, even if
slight, to be ‘undue’ in the sense of disproportionate or gratuitous.”222
A weighted balancing test of this kind seems to faithfully implement Casey’s directions to judges to
distinguish between necessary and “unnecessary” health regulations.223
The weight of the health justification for a law is thus relevant to the
effects as well as the purpose prongs of the Casey inquiry: as Judge Posner observed, if the state’s showing of
health need is weak, a judge has stronger grounds for finding the law’s impact
on access to be “undue.”224 This method of
incorporating the evidence in support of a health-justified restriction on
abortion into the undue burden inquiry seems to us unquestionably correct.
Undue means unwarranted. Undue means disproportionate. Undue is a relative judgment. As the judges who
employ the weighted balancing test understand, the question of what adverse
effects are “undue” depends on the strength of the state’s demonstration of a
health justification for the restriction on abortion—on whether a
restriction is “unnecessary” to protect women’s health and hence imposes an
“undue burden” on women’s access to abortion. Precisely because
undue means unwarranted or disproportionate, the judgment about which adverse
effects are undue requires balancing the extent to which a law advances the
state’s interests against the burdens the law will impose on the exercise of a
woman’s constitutional right. For this reason, judgments about which burdens
are undue will vary across contexts.
The proposition might seem unremarkable, but it stands dramatically at odds
with the practice of courts that derive rules from Casey about the kinds of adverse effects that are licit under the
undue burden test. Exemplary are
decisions of the Fifth Circuit that purport to derive from Casey rules of general application about driving distances and
undue burdens. Consulting the record in Casey,
Judge Owen observed: In Casey,
the Supreme Court considered whether a Pennsylvania statute that de facto
imposed a twenty-four-hour waiting period on women seeking abortions
constituted an undue burden. The Court concluded that it did not, despite the
fact that it would require some women to make two trips over long distances. An
increase in travel distance of less than 150 miles for some women is not an
undue burden on abortion rights.225 Judge
Jones approvingly affirmed and extended this reasoning: [T]he Supreme Court recognized that the 24-hour
waiting period would require some women to make two trips over these [long]
distances . . . [and] nonetheless held that the Pennsylvania regulation did not
impose an undue burden. We therefore conclude that Casey counsels against striking down a statute solely because women
may have to travel long distances to obtain abortions.226 Here, as elsewhere,
the Fifth Circuit distorts Casey. The
joint opinion evaluated the constitutionality of the driving distances in question
as effects of a statute imposing a
twenty-four-hour waiting period;227 the joint opinion judged these burdens
acceptable (not “undue”) because they
were an incident of the state’s effort to dissuade women from ending a
pregnancy. The opinion could not be clearer: “Because the informed consent
requirement facilitates the wise exercise of [the abortion] right, it cannot be
classified as an interference with the right Roe protects.”228 The form
of the restriction mattered centrally to authors of the joint opinion as they
determined what burdens on exercise of the right were undue: What is at stake is the woman’s right to make the
ultimate decision, not a right to be insulated from all others in doing so.
Regulations which do no more than create a structural mechanism by which the
State, or the parent or guardian of a minor, may express profound respect for
the life of the unborn are permitted, if they are not a substantial obstacle to
the woman’s exercise of the right to choose.229 As these passages of Casey illustrate, the question of
whether an adverse effect or burden is undue depends on the manner in which the
state is vindicating its interest in regulating abortion. Burdens that the
joint opinion found acceptable as an incident of the state’s efforts to dissuade
women from seeking an abortion do not
represent generally acceptable measures of the burdens the state may inflict on
women when it closes clinics for unnecessary or weakly supported health
reasons. Beyond this, the
deeper error of the Fifth Circuit’s reading of Casey is its claim to apply the undue burden standard—a
standard that vindicates a constitutional value—as a context-insensitive rule. The Court embraced the
undue burden framework as a way to protect women’s liberty: the conditions in
which women would exercise their constitutionally protected choice whether to
become a mother.230 Casey
protects women’s liberty by restricting the means by which the government may
protect potential life. If the government chooses to protect potential life, it
may not obstruct women’s access to abortion, but must persuade women to choose
motherhood by means that respect women’s dignity. In upholding a law
that was enacted for the nominal purpose of protecting women’s health, yet
would foreseeably shut down most abortion clinics in the state—leaving
millions of Texas women to exercise the choice Casey protects by driving hundreds of miles, if they can231—the Fifth Circuit mocks Casey,232 if not the Constitution itself. Casey’s language and its logic both point in the same
direction: Casey requires judges to
weigh the evidence supporting a health restriction on abortion against its
impact on women’s access. If judges do not do so, “unnecessary health
regulations” will erode constitutional protection for women’s choices. Casey requires states to protect
potential life by means that respect women’s dignity. The Court has
reaffirmed constitutional protections for dignity in Lawrence v. Texas233
(where Justice Kennedy quotes Casey
explicitly),234
and more recently in United States v.
Windsor235
and Obergefell v. Hodges.236
No less is required here. Casey is not the
opinion either of us would have written. Each of us believes the Constitution
rightly understood provides more substantial protections for a woman’s decision
whether to become a mother, especially given the exclusionary ways this nation
has treated those who bear and rear children. That said, there are
reasons for the Court to stand behind its quarter-century-old decision that
reach beyond stare decisis. We
understand Casey to represent the
Court’s good-faith effort to pronounce the Constitution’s meaning for a divided
nation. With Americans in bitter disagreement about the abortion question, the
Court invoked the Constitution as a ground on which they were united and on
which they could be asked to recognize each other’s views. In Casey, the Court interpreted the
Constitution in a “call[] [for] the contending sides of a national controversy
to end their national division by accepting a common mandate rooted in the
Constitution.”237 The Court allowed the states more latitude
to protect potential life ifthe
states did so by means the Court understood to respect a woman’s
constitutionally protected decision whether to become a mother. As a nation
divided, we need practices of mutual respect no less today than we did in 1992.
Casey did not
authorize health-justified restrictions on abortion that are in fact
unnecessary to protect women’s health and that obstruct women’s access to
abortion. Judges who are willing to accept Casey
understand this and strike down the regulations we have discussed here. Judges
at war with Casey defer to the
states’ rationales in the face of overwhelming evidence that the health
justifications for the restrictions offer a fig leaf for the expression of
antiabortion sentiment. The stakes are high
as the Court reviews a new generation of abortion restrictions that do not
simply communicate the state’s preference for childbirth but instead threaten
wholesale destruction of the clinic infrastructure that enables women to
exercise their constitutional right. Will states be permitted to restrict
abortion in ways the Constitution prohibits merely by relabeling an interest in
protecting unborn life as an interest in protecting women’s health? Sanctioning
laws of this kind threatens to make hollow the right Casey reaffirmed—all the more acutely so for the growing
number of women living in jurisdictions hostile to abortion. We have frequently
referred here to women’s dignity as a value that Casey sought to protect. At this crucial juncture in the
never-ending abortion controversy, we suggest that courts must also be
attentive to another claim to dignity: the dignity of law itself. If the
decision announced nearly a generation ago under an intense public spotlight
can be so easily manipulated and evaded, among the betrayed will be not only
the women of America, but the understanding that Casey affirmed: that constitutional law matters, and matters
especially in those precincts where we most deeply disagree.Introduction
I. understanding
casey: why courts need to differentiate
between life and health interests in reviewing abortion restrictions
A. The
Values at Casey’s Core
B. How
Casey
Applied the Undue Burden Standard to Life- and Health-Justified Restrictions on
Abortion
C. TRAP
Laws in the Casey Framework
II. the
clinic closings: prevention, not persuasion
A. The
Justification for Admitting Privileges Laws
B. Judicial
Review of Admitting Privileges Litigation
C. Returning
to Casey-Carhart
1. Rational
Basis and the Casey-Carhart Framework
2. How
Review of Health-Justified Restrictions Protects the Decisional Right Casey
Recognizes
3. Comparing
Review of Health-Justified Restrictions Across Circuits
Conclusion