Romanticizing Democracy, Political Fragmentation, and the Decline of American Government
abstract. This Feature
was delivered originally as the 2013-14 Ralph Gregory Elliot Lecture at Yale
Law School. author. Sudler Family Professor of
Constitutional Law, NYU School of Law. I am grateful for comments received
there and at a presentation of these views at the NYU Faculty Workshop. I would
also like to thank Hélène Landemore and Nick
Stephanopoulos for comments. For excellent research assistance, I thank Nabil
Ansari, as well as the NYU library reference team, particularly Gretchen
Feltes. I am also indebted to discussions with former Senators and members of
the House, all of whom requested anonymity.
For many years now I
have been interested in developing more of an institutionalist and realist
perspective on the dynamics of democracy and effective political power,
particularly in the United States. By this I mean a focus on the systemic
organization of political power and the ways that legal doctrines and
frameworks, as well as institutional structures, determine the modes through
which political power is effectively mobilized, organized, and encouraged or
discouraged. This perspective emphasizes, among other elements, the dynamic
processes through which winning coalitions are built or destroyed in the
spheres of elections and governance. The mutually influential relationship between
these spheres ultimately determines the ways in which our democratic
institutions function or fail to function. This focus on the organization, structure, and exercise of actual
political power in elections and in governance is what, in my view,
characterizes “the law of democracy”—a systematic field of study in law schools
for only the last twenty years or so.1 To sharpen up this initial description, I would
contrast the approach of the “law of democracy” to those approaches to
constitutional law and theory that center on protecting and developing the
dignity, or the autonomy, or the “personhood” of the individual, and ensuring
the equal treatment of particularly vulnerable groups. These are the
aspirations of Taking Rights Seriously,
for example—the arresting book title that defines the approach of someone who
has been much on my mind lately, my recently deceased colleague, Ronald
Dworkin.2 Even more, however, I want to contrast my focus on the systemic organization
of political power to rights-oriented approaches applied to democracy itself.3 By rights-oriented
approaches, I mean approaches that focus on interpreting and elaborating in
normative or doctrinal terms the general, broad, political values of democracy,
such as participation, deliberation, political equality, and liberty, or the
associated legal rights to political association, to free speech, to the vote,
or to political equality. These rights-oriented approaches typically pay less
attention to the structural or systemic consequences—the effects on the organization
of political power—of concretely institutionalizing these abstract ideals in
specific settings. Rights-oriented perspectives also often rest, implicitly, on
a conception of democracy that envisions individual citizens as the central
political actors. We can see these approaches in constitutional doctrine, in
reformist advocacy about democracy, and in scholarship on democracy in political
theory, philosophy, and law.4 My suggestion,
however, is that these approaches can spawn, and have spawned, doctrines and
policies that undermine the capacity of the democratic system as a whole to function
effectively. Instead of this rights-based orientation, I want to encourage more
focus on how political power gets mobilized, gets organized, and functions (or
breaks down).5 In this Feature,
adapted from a lecture I gave at Yale Law School in November 2013, I will
illustrate this approach by addressing a problem on many of our minds, what my
title calls “The Decline of American Government.” In making this statement, I
mean to appeal to a broad consensus of such a decline. Therefore, I do not
refer specifically to an inability to act in areas of partisan conflict in
which one side has a substantive policy preference for the status quo (climate
change policy, for example). Rather, I refer to arenas where there is broad
consensual agreement that government must
act, in some fashion, but where American government now seems incapable of
doing so—or where government does act, but only after bringing the country or
the world to the edge of a precipice: government shutdown, the regular dancing
on the knife’s edge of the first U.S. government default, and the like. I do
not want to suggest that American government is in some state of extreme
crisis; American democracy has faced far more dramatic challenges before,6 and as democratic observers from de
Tocqueville to today have recognized, democracy is rarely “as bad as it looks”
at any particular moment.7 It is enough to recognize serious
dysfunction even in only particular areas to motivate a search for deeper
explanations, as well as directions for possible paths forward. I want to offer two
main ideas about how to think about the decline of America’s governance
capacity and effectiveness. First, I want to
suggest that we cannot understand how our democratic institutions are designed
and how they function without recognizing that a uniquely American cultural sensibility and understanding
of democracy—one that I view as excessively romantic, particularly in the forms
it takes today—informs a good deal of the ways we design and reform our democratic
institutions. This uniquely romantic conception of democracy has, I believe, perversely
contributed to the decline of our formal political institutions. This will be
one of my themes: the dangers of democratic romanticism. Second, in diagnosing
the causes of government’s limited capacity to function effectively, there is a
widespread temptation to focus on how polarized the two dominant political
parties have become (as well as on whether polarization is asymmetric between
the two parties).8 Much of the commentary on polarization has
focused on the difficulty of fitting America’s increasingly parliamentary-like
political parties into the Constitution’s institutional architecture of a
separated-powers system.9 The understandable concern that many have
today is whether in times of divided government—but not only then, given the Senate
filibuster rule, which remains in place on policy matters—the absence of a
“majority government” will make it too difficult to generate the kind of concerted
political action required for legislation. If the concern about
polarization is best understood as one about effective governance, then we
should perhaps refine the concern, particularly for pragmatists searching for
potentially productive directions of plausible reforms. To do so, we should
identify the issue not as political
polarization alone but as one of political
fragmentation. By “fragmentation,” I mean the external diffusion of political power away
from the political parties as a whole and the internal diffusion of power away
from the party leadership to individual party members and officeholders. My claim is that, for pragmatic reformers,
political fragmentation of the parties (most obviously visible, at the moment,
on the Republican side, but latent on the Democratic side as well) is a more
important focus of attention than polarization if we are to account for why the
dynamics of partisan competition increasingly paralyze American government. The
government shutdown and near financial default were not a simple product of
party polarization; they reflected the inability of party leaders to bring
along recalcitrant minority factions of their parties and individual members to
make the deals that party leaders believed necessary. The problem is not
that we have parliamentary-like parties. Rather, it might well be that our
political parties are not parliamentary-like enough:party leaders are
now unable to exert the kind of effective party leadership characteristic of
parliamentary systems. If this analysis is
correct, stronger parties—or parties stronger in certain dimensions—ironically
might be the most effective vehicle for enabling the compromises and deals
necessary to enable more effective governance despite the partisan divide. I will offer a quick
sketch of a few policy proposals designed to re-empower political party leaders
in order to make government more functional. But the specific proposals are
less important in themselves than as illustrations of a direction of reform
that might enable more effective governance in the enduring context of highly
polarized political parties. Let me begin by impressing upon you the uniqueness of America’s practices
and institutions of democracy, taken as a whole, compared to those of other
mature, stable democracies. Jacksonian-era
reforms have bequeathed us the world’s only
elected judges and prosecutors.10 Indeed, we elect more than 500,000
legislative and executive figures, vastlymore than any other country per capita (one elected official for every 485
persons): we elect insurance commissioners, drainage commissioners, hospital
boards, community college boards, local school boards, and on and on.11 Furthermore, we lack independent
institutions to oversee the election process, such as specialized electoral
courts, independent boundary-drawing commissions, and independent agencies—institutions
common in most democratic countries.12 This leaves partisan, elected, and mostly
local officials in control of much of the regulation and administration of the
electoral process, out of a perverse belief that doing so makes the process
more democratically accountable to “us.”13 Our administrative
state, in general, is far more subject to democratic control than those of
other well-established democratic countries. Although there have been periods
in which we embraced independent administrative agencies based on ideals of
political independence and expertise, such as in the Progressive and New Deal Eras,
the dominant and distinct characteristic of American administrative government
has been the emphasis on political control (legislative or executive) over
administrative agencies or what is often called “democratic accountability.”14 Indeed, the ever-increasing American skepticism
of “expertise” and pressure for more and more “popular” or “democratic” control
over our institutions makes it doubtful, in my view, that the political force
could be marshaled today to create an independent central banking system, such
as the Federal Reserve System created in 1913, if we were facing the issue for
the first time now. As another reflection
of the degree of political control over public administration perceived to be
necessary in the United States, there are roughly 1,300 positions in the
federal government that require Senate confirmation, from the Supreme Court to
the fifteen members of the National Council on Disability, not to mention the
vast amount of time that administrators spend after appointment subject to the
political pressures of myriad congressional committees before which they
testify constantly.15 As another institutional example, our
democratic culture produced an extraordinarily fragmented banking system for
most of American history, from the 1830s until around the 1990s; this made
American banking exceptionally unstable and prone to crises relative to the
banking systems of some other democratic countries (averaging one crisis every decade).16 Democratic understandings and politics made
our banking system uniquely subject to local, popular political control; our
laws generated a highly disaggregated, decentralized system of tens of
thousands of “unit” banks (individual local banks, with no branches) that were
regulated overwhelmingly at the state level and thus politically controlled by
coalitions of local bankers and agrarian populists. Indeed, the leading
political history of banking systems in different countries characterizes the
American banking system throughout the 1830-1990 period as “crippled by
populism.”17 Even more to the
point for my purposes now, Progressive Era reforms, such as the state-imposed
requirement that political parties choose their nominees through primary
elections, have long made our political parties more subject to “popular
control” than in virtually any other democracy.18 We take for granted both that we vote for individual candidates, rather
than for political parties, and that the parties must choose their candidates
in primary elections, including for the most powerful elected office in the
world. But primary elections are not the norm around the world—parties and
their leadership choose their standard-bearers in many democracies.19 Indeed, our parties
are unique in other ways that reflect our unusual understanding of popular
sovereignty. Our parties have long been relatively “skeletal” organizations
that do not require the regular payment of party dues, in contrast with
political parties in most other countries, as well as most non-party
organizations.20 To “join” a party in the United States is
simply to check a box on a form or take a party ballot during a primary
election. Patronage hiring and firing once played a role analogous to the role
that membership dues in other countries play, but that, we have concluded,
violates the First Amendment.21 In the absence of dues and the power of
party leadership to choose the parties’ nominees, our parties have always been
less tightly structured than those in European democracies. The discipline of
party control is particularly firm in countries that use closed-list
proportional representation electoral systems, in which voters can vote only
for parties, not individual candidates. But weakened political parties do not
empower “the people”; they empower the organized interests that are most able
to take advantage of a system of political parties lacking sufficient
organizational strength to countervail private forces. In at least twenty-three
states we bypass formal institutional politics altogether through practices of
direct democracy such as ballot initiatives, referenda, and recall tools that
no other democracy uses to such an extent, especially since the revival of
direct democracy in America that began in 1978 with the symbol of the “property
tax revolt,” California’s Proposition 13.22 One of the best comparative accounts of the way in which the unique features
of American democracy combine to affect both elections and governance remains
Anthony King’s book, Running Scared: Why
America’s Politicians Campaign Too Much and Govern Too Little.23 Using the concrete experiences of specific
candidates and elected officials in the United States, Great Britain, and
Canada, King identifies several features of the American democratic process
that make American politicians “more vulnerable, more of the time, to the vicissitudes
of electoral political politics than are the politicians of any other
democratic country.”24 The unique features
that combine to create this extreme vulnerability are the extremely short terms
of office in the House; the use of primary elections in addition to general
elections; the weakness of American political parties, which requires American
candidates to be much more dependent on their own ability to raise money and
get their message out; and the high costs of campaigns in the United States
compared to those in several other democratic countries.25 The fact that American democracy exhibits these unique structures and features
across so many different institutions in so many different domains is no
accident. Underlying our institutions and practices is a singular democratic political
culture that has always rested on a
unique vision and understanding of the ideas of “popular sovereignty” and
“self-government.” Indeed, I believe the very term “popular sovereignty” is
invoked much more commonly in the United States than anywhere else. Put simply,
I would say that American democratic culture has long had a distinctively individualistic way of understanding the
“right” of self-government. This vision and the design of our political institutions
have been mutually constitutive and reinforcing; as this unique understanding
of popular sovereignty has led to institutional structures more subject to
unusually direct popular control, the longstanding existence of these institutions
has helped entrench and validate the cultural understandings. I will refer to
the feature of American democratic culture embodied in the ideas and institutions
that I have been describing as the “individualistic conception of democratic
government.” More specifically, our culture
uniquely emphasizes—I would say, romanticizes—the role and purported power of
individuals and direct “participation” in the dynamics and processes of
“self”-government. This culture too often envisions an individualized form of
political action, in which the key democratic elements are individual citizens,
often pictured in splendid isolation, and a democratic politics that arises
through spontaneous generation. This vision obscures the ways in which
participation must be mobilized, organized, and aggregated to be effective;
even worse, the pull of this vision often has led reformers and scholars to
fail to appreciate the way in which “reforms” are likely to work in practice,
given that the most effectively organized and mobilized actors will seize the
advantage these reforms open up. As part of this romanticized picture of
democracy, we uniquely distrust organized intermediate institutions standing
between the citizen and government, such as political parties. We can observe
elements of this idealized image as far back as the Federalist Papers. Despite
the brilliance and realist convictions of the Federalist Papers, these documents
conceive of elections and government essentially in a kind of political vacuum.
They offer no account of the critical role for intermediate political actors in
mobilizing and organizing voters in elections (indeed, they conceived of
elections as affairs of acclamation, not competitive political contests).
Similarly, they do not provide an account of the need for organized,
intermediary groups within elected government, such as caucuses and parties, to
enable the concerted action necessary for government to function effectively.26 Like other eighteenth-century political thinkers, the Framers disdained
political parties; recoiled when government soon divided into two distinct and
warring Federalist and Republican camps; and viewed this division as a necessary
temporary evil, not a permanent, legitimate feature of democracy.27 The worldview at the time of the
Constitution’s framing encompassed citizens, elections, and government—but not
the connective tissue of political parties, caucuses, and organizations that
are so essential to organizing effective political power within the spheres of
elections and governance. Of course, the eighteenth century’s vision of
political representation was more elitist than ours, but its blindness to all
of the critical intermediate organizations among citizens, elections, and
government reflects a characteristically American way of thinking about
democracy that has endured. We can see this in American foreign policy as well,
in the naïve view that immediate elections will bestow legitimate and meaningful
democracy on places emerging from non-democratic pasts, without regard to
whether various underpinnings of democracy, such as a plurality of organized
political groups competing for power, or a robust, independent press, have had
a chance to develop. The individualized
conception of democratic government has pervasively shaped, and continues to
shape, American democracy. We see this in institutional design, common
critiques of democracy, and reformist efforts to “improve” American democracy.
The conception is largely taken for granted, if recognized at all, let alone
questioned. Since at least the Jacksonian era, the appeal to more “popular
empowerment” or participation as the cure for political corruption has been a
constant cultural and political theme in American democracy28—even as we struggle to correct for the
dysfunctions that previous generations of reform in this direction have brought
about.29 For example, in 1974 when Congress
overturned the old seniority-based congressional committee system to dilute the
power of committee chairs—at the time, conservative Southern Democrats—the
result was the proliferation of committees and subcommittees. Yet some have
argued that by undermining the power of committee chairs and diffusing power
within Congress in this more “democratic” way, the net result has been to
increase the power of private interest groups to block legislation by expanding
further the number of veto points in the system, thereby diluting political
power.30 Indeed, the central
impulse behind many of our democratic reform efforts is not to criticize or
challenge the individualist conception of democracy, but to insist on yet more
“participation” and other ways of “empowering” individual citizens as the
solution to our democratic disaffections. We require so many of our
institutions to be chosen through elections, for example, on the view that
“citizen” control will keep officials hewing closer to the common good, without
any realistic assessment of how the electoral process actually works; with romanticized
views of how much interest most citizens will take (or rather, fail to take) in
voting for lower-level offices; and without regard for the degree to which organized
private interests will be able to dominate in low turnout, low-salience
elections. This approach is a longstanding one. For example, not only do we
elect school boards in many parts of the United States, but Progressive Era
policies urged that these (and other) local elections be held on a separate
timetable from general elections, so that local decision making would be “more pure”
and not entangled in broader political issues.31 Yet if turnout in school board elections is
exceedingly low, it is even lower when these elections are held off-cycle; not
surprisingly, the one interest that is always well represented in school board
elections, no matter when they are held, is that of teachers, who have among
the most direct stake in school board policies. Perhaps also not surprisingly,
recent empirical work “is strikingly clear” in demonstrating that the lower the
turnout in such elections, the more electoral and political influence teachers
have—and the higher teacher salaries become as a result.32 Our culture seems to reel from one
democratic dysfunction, to which the solution is more citizen empowerment, to another,
in which we must face up to the perverse consequences of this prior solution,
only to try yet another way to ensure more transparency and citizen control. I want to push back a
bit against that culture and the romantic vision of individualistic
self-government animating it. To begin to do that,
I now turn to my analysis of why our political institutions have become so
paralyzed in recent years. It is well-known that
our era of governance is constituted by what I have called “hyperpolarized
political parties.”33 By all conventional measures, the parties in government are more
polarized than at any time since the late nineteenth century.34 But keep in mind that partisan polarization is not necessarily bad, or
all bad, from a broader democratic perspective. Political polarization, from my
point of view, is a concern primarily insofar as it affects the capacity for
governance. Others might be troubled with a political culture characterized by
divisiveness, lack of civil disagreement, and the like, but my dominant concern
is polarization’s consequences for effective governance. Indeed, polarization
might well involve tragic conflicts between the domains of voting and
governance, a much more general conflict in democratic practice than democratic
theory has recognized. As responsible party government advocates have long
argued, coherent and sharply differentiated political parties increase voter
turnout, make the most salient cue in voting—the political party label—more
meaningful, and through that cue enable voters to hold officeholders more
meaningfully accountable.35 As a result, party polarization has distinct
electoral benefits; it is not a matter of all cost and no benefit. We should therefore
view partisan polarization as a significant problem only if and when its costs
are substantial enough to outweigh these electoral benefits. Preventing government
from taking effective action, even when broad agreement exists to the effect
that government must act in some form, signals that the costs of polarization
outweigh its benefits substantially enough to justify searching for measures
that could mitigate these costs, including institutional design measures. To understand what
measures might be most effective—and to justify my argument that our search
should move in a dramatically different direction than is typically suggested
by those troubled by extreme partisan polarization—I need to begin by
explaining the causes and suggested “cures” for our world of hyperpolarized
political parties. What has caused the dramatic partisan polarization of our
era? Polarization is not, in my view, a product of recent, or relatively
contingent, forces or individual personalities. I have argued that
the hyperpolarization of today’s parties is overwhelmingly a product of
long-term historical and structural forces.36 These forces were launched into motion with
the Civil Rights Era of the 1960s, particularly the Voting Rights Act, as
African Americans (and many poor whites) began the process of becoming full
political participants.37 It is easy to forget that, from roughly the
1890s until the Civil Rights Era, the entire South was an artificially created
one-party monopoly of the Democratic Party.38 The process of ending this unnatural
political monopoly began in 1965, but the full effects of this change did not
take place overnight; it took several decades of dynamic and mutually reinforcing
processes for the Democratic Party in the South to move toward the left, for a
robust and fully competitive Republican Party to rise, and for conservative
whites to shift their party identification for Senate, House, state, and local
elections to the Republican Party.39 Not until the 1990s,
remarkably enough, do we see the kind of two-party political system in the
South that the rest of the country had throughout the twentieth century.40 In my view, the racial redistricting regime of the Voting Rights Act
(VRA) contributed to this process. The VRA took hold for the first time in the
redistrictings of the 1990s as a result of the 1982 amendments to Section 2 of
the VRA and, perhaps even more importantly, the Supreme Court’s 1986 Thornburg v. Gingles decision.41 The post-1990s redistricting regime shifted
the political representation of the Democratic Party in the South towards its
most liberal wing, dramatically reduced the number of officeholding moderate
white Democrats in the South, and facilitated the rise of many more
overwhelmingly conservative and Republican districts.42 Through this
revolutionary set of historical changes, the two political parties, at both
national and state levels, became “purified” into far more ideologically
coherent entities. Voters now sort themselves into the two parties overwhelmingly,
and correctly, by ideology, so that nearly all liberals are now Democrats, all
conservatives now Republicans.43 This simply had not been the case for most
of the past century. If you accept my view
on this, then it follows that the highly polarized partisan structure of our democratic
politics should not be seen as aberrational. It should be understood as the
“new normal.” Instead of being the product of contingent features of our
present institutions or our present political moment, it is the result of deep
and long-term historical processes. In other words, polarization should be
accepted as a fact likely to be enduring for some time, not something that we
can design away. Nonetheless, a great
deal of intellectual and reformist energy has been spent on the search for
reformist solutions to extreme partisan polarization. This energy has been
directed to restoring “the disappearing center” in American democracy.44 Given the recommended remedies for polarization that I describe below,
it becomes necessary to explore briefly why certain solutions for polarization
are likely to be unavailing and indeed, why such “fixes” might even be
perverse, if the goal is to enable a more effective set of political institutions
capable of overcoming current paralysis. “Fixes” for polarization can be categorized
into two forms. The first involves changes to the institutional structures of elections that will shift the mix of
candidates and officeholders to empower a critical mass of more centrist officeholders
who can bridge partisan divides. These institutional-design proposals include
familiar ones that have been offered—open primaries; independent commissions to
perform redistricting, perhaps with instructions to maximize competition;
changes to internal legislative rules—and less familiar ones: eliminating laws
banning “sore-loser” candidacies;45 moving to instant-runoff voting; or even
more radically, abolishing primaries altogether and returning to a system of
candidate selection by party leaders. On the institutional
front, the two fixes that have received the most attention are ending
gerrymandering and opening up primary elections to a broader electorate than
just party members. These changes might be desirable for many reasons, but in
determining whether institutional-design changes in these areas are likely to
make a meaningful contribution to reducing partisan polarization, we ought not
be too sanguine about this prospect as more empirical evidence mounts.46 I continue to be more optimistic that
changes to the structure of primary elections could make a difference, but
there is little systematic empirical evidence to support this hope.47 The second category
of reforms, on which I would like to focus more, seeks to reduce polarization
in government by empowering “the people” more effectively. The idea is that
greater citizen participation will be a solvent for political dysfunction and
polarization. This idea is premised on the assumption that partisan polarization is not in us, but in our political
parties; polarization in our formal politics is a corruption or distortion of
the more moderate, centrist politics that we would have if only we could find
ways to give “the people” more direct control or influence over elections and
governance. The idea is part of a recurring wish or vision throughout American
political history. But there are good reasons to distrust this idea and even to
think that institutional efforts to reflect popular empowerment would make
polarization worse, not better. While earlier
academic work suggested that “the public” was more centrist than those holding
public office, more recent works reveal that polarization in government is not
so obviously a distortion or corruption of the larger public’s less polarized
views. Alan Abramowitz has shown that “politically engaged citizens” are just
as polarized as the parties in government.48 Being “engaged” in this sense means little
more than taking part in the most basic forms of democratic participation, such
as: voting; trying to persuade a friend or neighbor to vote; displaying a
bumper sticker or yard sign; giving money; or attending a campaign rally or
meeting. Abramowitz’s findings therefore pose a serious challenge to the idea
that more participation will translate into less polarization.49 Shanto Iyengar and
his co-authors have found that partisans are far more uncomfortable today than
in the past with their children marrying those who identify with the other
party.50 And while citizens overall might not be as
ideologically extreme as they are partisan, we are highly sorted along partisan
terms today; 92% of Republicans are more conservative than the median Democrat,
while 94% of Democrats are more liberal than the median Republican (twenty
years ago, the figures were 64% and 70%, respectively).51 The percentage of those who are consistently
liberal or conservative, rather than having a mix of such views, has doubled
from 10% to 21% over the past two decades.52 As Marc Hetherington and others report,
those who identify with one party express far more negative feelings about the
other party than in the past; those of the opposite party to the President now
largely report not trusting the government at all.53 A major recent study by the Pew Research
Center finds that in 1994, only 17% of Republicans and 16% of Democrats had
“very unfavorable” views of the opposite party, while today 43% of Republicans
and 38% of Democrats hold such views.54 Other social scientists suggest that the
public is even more extreme in its policy views than those in office or, at the
least, that those whose views are categorized as “moderate” are actually
ideologically polarized too.55 In addition, citizens, activists, and
elected officeholders now see more issues in one-dimensional, partisan terms.
As Carsey and Layman find: “The data are clear: across all three major
domestic issue areas—social welfare, race, and culture—there has been a steady
increase in the gap between Democratic and Republican citizens, elected
officials and activists.”56 In state
politics, we see a pattern similar to that in Congress. On average, state
legislatures are becoming significantly more polarized.57
If political
engagement correlates with increased polarization, as Abramowitz documents,
then we should be skeptical about whether finding ways to increase popular
participation will temper polarization. In addition, participation does not
sprout up spontaneously, like mushrooms after a rain. Participation has to be
energized, organized, mobilized, and channeled in effective directions—all of
which requires the very organizations, and the partisans, that “citizen”
participation is meant to bypass. Moreover, political engagement might not just
involve individuals who self-select for partisanship, but might itself be an
experience that generates polarization. Furthermore, despite all the cynicism
about politics today, “Americans [now] are more interested in politics, better
informed about public affairs, and more politically active than at any time
during the past half century.”58 More and more of us are engaged in the ways
that idealized democratic citizens are thought to be. And we are partisans.
Cause and effect are difficult to disentangle here. But do you know many
politically engaged people who are not partisans, outside of groups like the
League of Women Voters, whose membership has dropped nearly in half since 1969,
according to Putnam?59 Extremism in the name of moderation is no
vice (that is certainly my own temperament), but it doesn’t raise a lot of
money or draw a lot of volunteers. We should be wary of romanticizing a more
engaged public as a vehicle that will save us from hyperpolarized partisan
government. Appealing to more
“participation” as a cure for polarization thus reduces to a strange kind of
hope that when the politically non-engaged become more engaged, they will not
behave like those who are already politically engaged. They will pass untouched
through the maw of the machinery of democracy but remain the same politically
uninformed innocents as when they started. But their participation will have to
be mobilized, organized, directed, and at least modestly informed. Will this
not make them act in the same way as citizens who are already engaged? Let me make this
point concrete by turning to the specific, crucial issue of campaign financing.
I show how certain proposals that focus on empowering more citizen
participation are likely to have the unintended consequence of hindering effective
governance. I will state my
preference at the outset: I favor a system of public financing, but not the
kind of public financing centered on individual candidates that exists in the
United States (in the few places we have it).60 Instead, I want to suggest a system of
public financing in which more of the emphasis, and more of the flow of money,
is oriented toward the political parties rather than individual candidates. I
will return to this proposal shortly. But to stay on the
theme of empowering greater citizen participation, some proponents of public
financing have suggested that campaign financing work not through the state, as
in public financing around the world, but rather through individual vouchers
provided to all of us.61 This is a distinctively American proposal,
for it reflects, I believe, the peculiar and radically individualistic culture
of American democracy, along with our characteristic distrust of more organized
forms of political power. Yet it turns out that
individual donors are more ideologically extreme and more polarized than
non-donors—as we’ve just discussed, the politically engaged are more polarized
than the general public.62 Indeed, those who donate are more
ideological even than “active partisans,” defined as those who identify with a
political party and engage in more political activities than the mere act of
voting.63 Even more to the point, individual campaign donors are also more ideologically extreme than most
other donorsas well, such as PACs
and the political parties.64 PACs tend to focus on moderate candidates,
as well as incumbents; individual donors focus on more ideologically polarized
candidates. In general, groups that give for access-oriented reasons tend to
finance moderates and incumbents, while ideological donors favor challengers
and more extreme candidates.65 Put another way, the most ideologically extreme
money to campaigns comes from individual donors. Moreover, recent work
concludes that the voting patterns of senators most closely track the policy
preferences of their individual donors, rather than those of voters in the
state or even co-partisans in the state—and that this pushes senators to the
ideological poles.66 Democratic senators are more liberal, Republicans more conservative,
than their voters, but these politicians are reflective of the views of their
individual donor bases. Furthermore,
candidate campaigns have become dramatically more dependent on individual donors in recent decades than on all
other sources combined, such as political parties and PACs, even as our
candidates and parties have become more and more polarized. In other words, as
our campaign finance system has become more democratized, our politics has
become more polarized. In 1990, individual contributions to campaigns provided
about 25% of a campaign’s money, and PACs provided about half; today,
individuals are by far the largest source of direct money to campaigns (about
61% for Congress) and PAC contributions constitute less than 25%.67 Here is another fact
to keep in mind in seeking to understand individuals, polarization, and money:
a majority of individual contributions now come from out-of-state donors.68 Also not surprising is that out-of-state
donors are the most ideologically
extreme of all contributors. Consider the kind of individuals likely to give
out-of-state money to the campaigns of Elizabeth Warren and Ted Cruz, as
opposed to the more moderate senators or challengers about whom most
out-of-staters probably know little to nothing in the first place.69 Are many individual voters around the
country likely to send their money to Missouri for Claire McCaskill or to
Tennessee for Lamar Alexander? Democratizing
campaign contributions through vouchers might well, ironically, fuel the flames of political
polarization, as compared to public financing systems funded in the more
traditional way, through general revenues. Voucher proponents
might believe that the polarizing effects of individual donations will
disappear once “all the people” are empowered to donate through vouchers. But
this neglects the collective-action dynamics that influence all political
activity. People have to become both motivated and engaged enough to choose to
donate and to seek out information relevant to informed donations—just as they
must to vote—and informing and motivating potential donors will take political
organization and mobilization. Those who are most informed and motivated are
likely to be partisans, and thus the groups most equipped to take advantage of
these new political openings—as with other such openings—are also likely to be
more partisan. I say all this not to
pick on voucher proposals in particular but to illustrate a larger point.
Unless we attend to the ways in which political power is actually mobilized,
organized, exercised, and marshaled, then policy proposals based on an individualistically
driven vision of politics, or on non-grounded abstract democratic ideals such
as “participation” or “equality,” can perversely contribute to undermining our
institutional capacity to govern. If we want to adopt public financing in ways
least likely to fuel partisan polarization, then more traditional forms of
public financing through general revenues, rather than those based on
individual donations, might be more appropriate. Let me turn now to a different view: an institutionally and
organizationally centered approach to the relationship between elections,
governance, and effective political power. In thinking about how to enable effective democratic action through our
political institutions, we should focus less on individual citizens and turn instead
to the current or possible organizational entities that have the most powerful
incentives to aggregate the broadest array of interests into democratic politics—and
to force compromise, negotiation, and accommodation between those interests.
Organizational power inevitably exists in democracies; it cannot be wished
away, and it is in fact crucial in order for democracy to be able to work at
all. Of the various organizational entities that exist or that I can envision,
the political parties, driven by the need to appeal to the widest electorate,
remain the broadest aggregators of diverse interests. This proposition might sound ironic, in light of how polarized the
parties have become. But the electoral incentive means that it remains true.
The overpowering need to put together coalitions broad enough to control one,
two, or three of our national political institutions remains the single
strongest unifying force capable of bringing together broad arrays of interests
into two large coalitions—and, in doing so, inevitably forcing compromise among
those interests. When African-American voters in the South were permitted to
vote for three decades or so after the Civil War, there were effective
office-holding interracial political coalitions, despite the era’s cultural
attitudes about race.70 Electoral incentives and the desire to wield the
tools of political power provide powerful motivations to compromise between
groups in the pursuit of winning coalitions. In first-past-the-post election
systems, the two dominant political parties serve as the principal vehicle for
these types of compromise. I see no other candidate on the horizon. Recently, proposals have emerged
to form multi-candidate PACs that would raise and donate to “moderate” candidates.71 If such entities
get off the ground, I am skeptical about how effective they will be. But of
course, the multi-candidate organization par
excellence that already exists is the political party. Indeed, the candidate
contributions made by political party organizations tend to empower the forces
in the center of the party; parties donate twice as much to candidates in the
middle of the ideological spectrum as to those at the extremes.72 Party-based contributions
to campaigns are a force for moderation compared to individual contributions. However, this is where the problem of political fragmentation becomes
acute. Parties, like all organizations, are complex entities composed of many,
sometimes conflicting, components, including elected officials, organizational
leaders, party voters, factions, and so on. Among these forces, it is the
elected party leaders who have the strongest incentives to internalize national
electoral incentives toward broad coalitions. The success of party leaders
depends to a significant extent on making the party brand as broadly appealing
as possible. There, I suggest, lies the problem. Political fragmentation has drained partisan elected leaders of much of the power
to control, unify, and discipline members of their own party. By “fragmentation,” I mean both the diffusion
of the power in elections away from the formal campaigns and the political parties—and
even more importantly, the diffusion of power in government away from the
leadership of the major political parties to their more extreme factions. While
some have characterized the parties today as “networks,”73 I believe “politically fragmented” better
captures the structure. Over recent election
cycles, we have become well aware of the fragmentation reflected in the
explosion of Super PACs, 527s, and 501(c) organizations that seek to influence
elections and policy. Many of these organizations have much narrower
ideological and policy interests than the parties as a whole. At the same time,
party leaders also have less capacity
to force party members to toe the party line. Members of the House and Senate are
much better able to function as independent entrepreneurs and free agents. As
Moisés Naím has documented across a wide array of public and private
organizations, organizational “power” is breaking down in general.74 A specific
representation of this phenomenon is the unprecedented power that senators in their first year in power have in
relation to their party leaders and consequently over our politics. Republican
Party leaders may have understood that shutting down the government and
threatening to default would be destructive to the party’s interests (they did
not permit the same mistake to be made twice). But today, they find it
difficult to stop one or a few individual senators, or a minority faction, from
doing just that. It is impossible to
imagine even as powerful a figure as Lyndon Johnson playing the kind of role in
his first years in the Senate that Ted Cruz has been able to play. To those who think
that this kind of political fragmentation is a problem only on one side, I
disagree.75 The same structural forces are at work and
the same kind of fragmentation lies latent in the Democratic Party; these
divisions will become apparent under the right set of circumstances. The forces
of economic populism—centered most directly for now on Elizabeth Warren, who
already allegedly wielded an effective veto over her own President’s pick to
chair the Federal Reserve76—do battle with the more centrist,
establishment forces within the Democratic Party. For now, the presence of a sitting
Democratic president exerts a sufficient unifying force to suppress these
conflicts, but once this presence is removed, we may well see more overt
political fragmentation within the Democratic Party. If you accept my conclusion that intense polarization of the parties in
government is likely to be an enduring fact for the foreseeable future, the
question must then shift to the following issue: from where are sources of
compromise and negotiation, deal-making, pragmatism, and the like most likely
to emerge in such an overall polarized structure?77 Polarization and
divided government make capacities and attitudes related to compromise more
necessary—and, of course, more difficult. In my view, elected party leaders are the most likely
sources of the kind of political compromise and pragmatism necessary to reverse
the decline of American government. In part, this is a numbers problem: negotiations between
three to five leadership figures are easier to conduct than hydra-headed
negotiations in which new factions or individuals pop up. In part this is
because the trust in negotiations that is essential to deal-making is
established by repeat players in ongoing relationships of regular deal-making.
Second, my focus on elected party leaders stems from an empirical belief,
reflected in academic studies, that party leaders in Congress tend to be
ideological “middlemen” of their parties.78
They have stronger incentives to forge compromises both because their election
requires appeal to broad constituencies within their parties and because they
bear more personal responsibility and blame for the failure of “their”
institution to function effectively.79
But party leaders can play this role only if they have the tools and the
leverage to bring along their caucuses in the direction that these leaders believe
best positions the party as a whole. Finally, then, let me explain why they
have lost that leverage. The problem is not that individual leaders are now “weak.” Part of the
American tendency to individualize politics is to focus on personalities as the
cause of political action or inaction. Personalities matter, but so does
structure. Both George W. Bush and Barack Obama campaigned, and tried to govern
for an initial period, in ways that reached across the aisle; both discovered
that the larger structure of hyperpolarized parties in Congress made this aim
exceedingly difficult.80 Furthermore,
broader structural changes, including legal ones, have disarmed party leaders
of the tools they previously had used to unify their members around deals that
were thought to be in the best interest of the party as a whole. What
institutional and structural changes might recapture some of the crucial
capacities that enable effective partisan leadership and thereby also enable
effective governance? Party leaders once
had their greatest leverage over their members through the power of committee
assignments. These assignments were valuable because they were the means to
work on substantive issues a member cared about, ways to raise the member’s
profile and stature, and ways to raise money for subsequent elections. But two major changes
have made committee assignments less meaningful when it comes to the ability to
raise funds and enhance one’s public status and visibility, at least for those
politicians who see themselves as upwardly mobile (that is, most of them): the
communications revolution and the current system of campaign financing.
Politically ambitious senators more and more now view the Senate as a quick
pass over to a presidential campaign, particularly in light of President
Obama’s success. Indeed, staying in the Senate for more than a brief period may
be considered a liability to pursuit of higher office, since longer tenure
means more need to take positions on divisive issues that will inevitably
alienate some potential constituencies. The first change is a
cultural one we all recognize: the revolution in communications and information
technology. According to Moisés Naím’s account, this revolution is the major force spawning the general
unraveling of organizational authority and effectiveness across public and
private sectors.81 Individual officeholders now have the
capacity to reach large, intensely motivated audiences of potential voters and
donors in ways that were simply not possible before; they are able to build a
personal brand apart from the party label. Does Senator Ted Cruz, for example,
spend more time on Twitter and television, including cable television, as well
as televised speeches on the floor in the post-CSPAN era, than he does meeting
with Republican Party leaders? What could Lyndon Johnson have done that would
have been comparable? Party leaders do not control and cannot shut down these
new channels of access to direct communication with voters and donors. At the
same time that these channels enable individual officeholders to reach out,
they also enable more widespread populist influence to reach in and factional
interests within parties can be more easily mobilized. Of course, there is no
way to unwind this communications revolution. The second force
behind the reduced leverage party leaders have over their members involves
legal changes. Here I will focus only on the way we have changed election
financing starting in the 1970s. We adopted the most aggressive regulatory
structure in American history for controlling money in national elections in
the early 1970s in the aftermath of Watergate. The system we created was a
candidate-centered system of financing, in contrast to the party-centered systems
used in much of Europe.82 The 1974 Federal Election Campaign Act
Amendments83 imposed contribution caps and spending limits
on campaigns in general, and they also treated political parties similarly to
corporate and union PACs: party committees could give no more than $5,000 to
candidates. In addition, individual contributions to the parties were capped at
$25,000 a year.84 When the Supreme Court struck down the
spending limits in this law in Buckley v.
Valeo,85 the Court gave virtually no independent
consideration to the Act’s regulation of political parties—either the
restrictions on party donations to candidates or the caps on individual
contributions to parties. Then, in the early 2000s, we added on the second big change to our system
of election financing: the McCain-Feingold campaign finance “reforms.” Before
that moment, the political parties raised nearly half their money in what was
called “soft money.”86 Without delving
deeply into details, soft money entailed contributions to the political parties
that were not subject to the caps in federal campaign-finance law.87 This soft money,
which was used for party-building actions (including television ads, positive
and negative, concerning specific candidates), was fully disclosed and
transparent when Congress eliminated it. Some of these contributions were in
huge amounts; around half of it came from individuals, the rest from
corporations and unions.88 From the perspective of reformers, soft money was corrupting. The “purist”
solution in McCain-Feingold was to ban the parties from receiving any soft money at all. From that point
on, all money given to the parties became subject to contribution caps. The
fact that Congress was willing to cut off the flow of soft money to the parties
was itself a signal of the candidate-centered nature of our financing system
and the reduced dependence of candidates (especially incumbents) on the parties
for their electoral success.89 But the practical result now seems to have been to
diminish the already-weakened political parties as a force in elections and to
create incentives for this party “soft money” to flow to independent groups.
Even “the ground game” in elections, the quintessential party electoral
activity, is increasingly funded outside the parties.90 At the same moment that legislators became able to brand themselves and
raise money independently of the parties, the parties were dramatically disempowered
relative to other groups. Even worse, the “reforms” to campaign financing
actively encouraged money to flow outside the parties to organizations that
supported narrower, more sectarian causes. That is why first-year senators can
now wield as much power within and over their parties as much more senior
senators, including the party leadership. Since we cannot undo
the communications revolution, I want to suggest three proposals for legal
change aimed at giving the political parties—and just as importantly, their
elected leadership—more influence in elections and hence over how their members
govern. Legal changes might not be necessary to re-empower party leadership; it
is possible that organic processes, driven by national electoral incentives,
will do so.91 But if legal changes turn out to be needed,
I offer these three initial suggestions. The first two changes are modest, the third more dramatic. The specifics
of any of these proposals are less important (and not developed here in any
detail) than the general conceptual re-orientation I have in mind: to empower
the political parties and their leadership so that the aggregative forces in
democracy have as powerful a role as possible, and as much leverage as
possible, in the democratic process. These proposals focus on shifting our campaign finance policies in ways
that would give a greater role to the political parties. As Ray LaRaja and
Brian Schaffner have recently demonstrated, states that have more
“party-centered” campaign finance laws tend to have less polarized legislatures
than those that impose significant constraints on the amounts and means through
which the political parties can support candidates.92 The mechanism
through which this occurs, they conclude, is that the parties tend to use their
financial resources to support moderate candidates more than other sources of
campaign money; consistent with the incentive structures I described above, the
elected officials who control party organizations internalize winning elections
over ideological purity. The empirical evidence shows that parties, more than
issue groups and other political committees, tend to concentrate their money on
moderates and not on ideologues. As a result, LaRaja and Schaffner argue,
states that give more freedom to political parties in the campaign-finance
system end up with less polarized legislatures.93 The federal campaign finance system imposes caps on how much the political
parties can directly contribute to the campaigns of their candidates.94 But the campaign finance
rules also treat an actor’s campaign spending that is coordinated with a
candidate’s campaign as equivalent to a direct contribution to that campaign.
Moreover, while the rules are more generous in dollar terms for the parties,95 these rules
similarly treat coordinated party spending beyond those amounts as prohibited
contributions to the candidate’s campaign. Thus, parties can engage in only
limited coordinated spending with their candidates.96 The fear is that
party spending in coordination with its candidate would be a conduit for
individuals to circumvent the contribution caps that exist on direct donations
to the campaign and that bans on earmarking party contributions for specific
candidates are not sufficient to address this concern. The effect (and intent) is to use campaign finance law to try to build
more of a wall between the political parties and their candidates when it comes
to spending money on elections. In
fact, the Federal Election Commission wanted to go even further and treat any money a party spent to support a
candidate as a direct contribution to the candidate, which would mean this
money would be subject to contribution caps. The Supreme Court put a stop to
this effort by holding that political party spending that is independent is
just as protected under the First Amendment as independent spending by any
other entity.97 But we still live
with the remaining constraints, which the Court endorsed, that impose limits on
the ability of political parties to coordinate election spending with their
candidates.98 Indeed, the Court
has rejected any view that it should apply stricter scrutiny to limits on
coordinated party spending than to that of any other entity.99 My first proposal, therefore—and it may sound startling—is to permit parties
to work more directly together with their candidates and coordinate the party’s
spending with campaigns. Contributors should continue not to be able to earmark
contributions for specific candidates,100 and one can raise
concerns about how effective those bans on earmarking might be, but the
question of potential corruption should be seen in comparative terms: in a
world in which individuals can contribute unlimited amounts to issue-advocacy
Super PACs, including Super PACs dedicated to one specific candidate or issue,101 are we better off
sharply limiting contributions to parties or their ability to engage in
coordinated spending with candidates? Parties, after all, are constituted by
numerous interests and many donors, including large donors; parties dilute the
role of money by pooling so many interests and donors. This dilution is far
from complete, of course, but again, it is probably better than the
alternatives. Instead of treating cooperation between parties and candidates as
potential vehicles through which individuals can corrupt candidates, we should
recognize that, on balance, party coordinated spending at least has the virtue
of linking parties and candidates more effectively. This link would help revive
a more central role for the parties’ national campaign committees in their
candidates’ success, and in turn give those in control of the parties more
leverage over candidates. My second modest proposal is to raise significantly the amounts of money
that can be donated to political parties for election purposes. It is important
to recognize, but complex to unravel, how the McCain-Feingold law’s ban on
soft-money contributions affected the overall money available to parties and
hence the role of the parties, in relation to other entities, in the democratic
process. Let me offer just two quick facts to illustrate how this law’s ban on
soft money immediately has affected election financing. McCain-Feingold, at
least as much or more than Citizens
United¸ accounts for the role of non-party entities in the way our
elections are run today. In the first election after the law was enacted, in 2004, the political
parties appeared to be able effectively to replace the soft money they had lost
through increased, successful efforts to raise more money from more
individuals, in part because McCain-Feingold also raised the amount of money
individuals could donate to the parties.102 But the law soon
also encouraged a dramatic rise in spending by groups outside the party
structure. From 2002, when the Act was adopted, until 2008—well before Citizens
United was decided in January 2010—independent spending by non-party
entities exploded, growing around 1122% in those 6 years (or 555% from 2000,
the presidential election before the Act).103 In the 2012 elections,
non-party spending grew only 207% from the 2008 election, even though the 2012
election was highly competitive to the very end.104 The money that had
been going to the parties, and no longer could, simply flowed now to direct,
independent spending by those who had formerly given to the parties. At the
same time, spending by the political parties now does appear to have taken a
significant hit.105 Keep this in mind the next time you hear Citizens United castigated as “the root of all evil” concerning
money in politics. This view is wrong, for too many reasons to go into here,
and Citizens United has become a
too-convenient whipping post for those concerned about an excessive role for
money in American elections.106 In fact, Citizens United has played a minor role
in the recent explosion of non-party money, partly because the logic of Buckley itself made it inevitable that the
First Amendment would prohibit caps on contributions to non-party entities that
engaged only in independent election spending.107 Reforms like the
McCain-Feingold soft-money ban created at least as strong an incentive for the
rise of the centripetal and fragmenting forces in democracy as has Citizens United. In a world in which the
potential pool of money to influence election outcomes becomes effectively
unlimited, because Buckley v. Valeo makes
any kind of spending limitations unconstitutional, restrictions on the flow of
money to candidates and campaigns will inevitably lead that money to flow
through other channels, as it did in floods well before Citizens United.108 For those who
remain concerned about the flow of money into the political parties, we can
debate appropriate limits on amounts and sources. But if we have limits on the
amounts that can be donated to parties from appropriate sources, then those
limits should be set at high levels to encourage a more effective role for
parties in elections and hence in governance. Both raising the caps on donations to parties and on party spending coordinated
with its candidates do raise concerns that donors would be able to use the
parties to corrupt those in office by making elected officials dependent upon large
contributions to the parties—contributions that are then passed through to
specific candidates who are aware of the ultimate source of the party’s
spending or contributions. My final, more extreme proposal therefore takes to
its natural conclusion the underlying idea of structuring the campaign finance
system to support a larger role for the political parties, in a way that
addresses this corruption concern. We could consider a shift to publicly financed
elections, but with the important twistthat
they be financed significantly through the political parties, rather than
having the individual candidates be the exclusive or overwhelming recipient of
the funds. In the limited experiences of public financing in the states, the
money overwhelmingly flows through the candidates, not the parties—reflecting
the typical individualist-based American conception of democracy.109 Public financing through the parties would most directly accomplish the
aim of putting greater leverage into the hands of party leaders. It would also,
perhaps not coincidentally, bring our system of financing elections closest to
the most common system used in other well-established democracies.110 Of course, if we
were to encourage or require money to flow primarily through the major political
party organizations, it would become all the more important to focus on how the
leadership of party organizations gets constituted—and, given the much greater
significance that party organizations would have, the ways in which these party
leaders are chosen would inevitably change (particularly for the party that
does not control the presidency). Based on the views I have outlined here,
perhaps the ongoing party organizations, the Democratic National Convention and
Republican National Convention, would need to be put under the control of the
elected party leadership in government, at least for determinations of how to
use campaign funds. Elected national leaders of the party (a multi-member small
group of such leaders might be appropriate) remain the actors most likely to
internalize the incentives to make the party appealing to the widest
constituency. But fixing the details is less important than generating
discussion about this general direction for public financing schemes. It is possible, of course, that organic developments might move political
dynamics in this direction without formal policy change. The 2014 midterm
election cycle, for example, has seen the emergence for Senate races of an exceptionally
well-funded Super PAC on the Democratic side, The Senate Majority PAC, which is
funded by individual billionaires making large contributions (the largest to
date being $5.0 million) and labor unions.111 Much like the
broad electoral aims of a political party, the purpose of this Super PAC is to
preserve the Democratic majority in the Senate.112 The party has
therefore spent large sums to attempt to preserve the seats of vulnerable but
competitive incumbent Senators, which in turn means the most centrist Senators
in the Democratic Party, who hail from purple or red states, such as Senator
Pryor of Arkansas, Senator Hagan of North Carolina, and Senator Begich of Alaska.113 This PAC behaves much like a political party in the sense that its aim is
not to support ideological purists, but in more pragmatic, electorally oriented
terms, to support the party’s vulnerable candidates, regardless of specific
ideology. Given the theoretical and empirical account that I provided earlier,
it should come as no surprise that the organizers and leaders of this PAC have
strong professional connections to Senate Majority Leader Harry M. Reid,114 or that President
Obama has spoken at two of the PAC’s major fundraisers.115 Although Senator
Reid does not formally control this PAC, one might comfortably speculate that
if this PAC (as the biggest outside spender on the Democratic side) succeeds in
enabling the election of Democratic Senators, Senator Reid might well end up
with greater capacity to “persuade” those Senators to follow the leadership’s
positions. If similar PACs closely tied to the leadership emerge on both sides
of the aisle in both houses of Congress, party leaders might well end up with
greater leverage over rank-and-file members dependent on this source of
funding. These large contributions to independent-spending “non-party” entities
are flowing into this surrogate for the Democratic Party, rather than into organs
of the party organization itself (such as the Democratic Senate Campaign
Committee), because current law does not permit political parties to accept unlimited
contributions that will be used only to engage in independent spending. But
current litigation is challenging this restriction on First Amendment grounds,
based on the argument that political parties, like other entities, should be
able to accept unlimited contributions if they will be used only for the
party’s constitutionally protected right to engage in independent spending.116 There is little
doubt that if Democratic Party organizations could accept these unlimited,
independent-expenditure contributions, then an entity like the Senate Majority
PAC would disappear overnight, and all or nearly all of that money would flow
to the appropriate party organization instead (more ideologically oriented
Super PACs would continue to exist). Moreover, if this litigation succeeds, it
would significantly reduce the importance of the issues I have raised about
limits on party coordinated expenditures or caps on donations to the parties
for money that will be used for contributions to campaigns, not independent
spending. If the political parties were constitutionally entitled to receive
unlimited contributions dedicated for use only for independent party spending
on behalf of candidates, then we would likely see a significant reversal of the
flow of money from Super PACs to the parties. The Supreme Court’s recent decision in the McCutcheon case might already provide a gentle nudge in this
direction.117 That decision left
intact contribution caps on the amount an individual could donate to any
particular candidate or to a political party, but invalidated caps on the total
amount of money an individual (staying within these limits) could give to a
group of candidates or party organizations. Before the decision, an individual
could give no more than $123,200 in total to candidates and party
organizations.118 The decision has
triggered the formation of more joint fundraising committees; these enable a
group of candidates to raise money collectively and accept a single check,
which is then divided up legally among the candidates, and enable political
party organizations, such as a national party organization and a number of
state party organizations, to do the same thing.119 Despite claims
about the additional torrent of money that McCutcheon
would release through these vehicles, it remains unclear at this stage how
much money these joint fundraising committees will be able to raise.120 But if party-based
joint fundraising committees do turn out to be of considerable practical
significance, then the effect of McCutcheon
would likely be to cause more money to flow to the political parties,
rather than to non-party organizations that had never been subject to similar
aggregate contribution caps. If this occurs, McCutcheon would turn out to be the first Supreme Court decision in
this entire field with the practical effect of creating incentives for money to
flow to the parties rather than to non-party groups. Whatever else might be
said about the decision, it would therefore encourage, to some modest extent,
the forces inducing centralization of financing through the parties—emphasized
in this Feature.121 To be sure, there is still reason to be concerned about the role in
American elections of extremely large contributions or spending from single
individuals or entities. But we only began in the 1970s to attempt to regulate
the role of money in national elections in a comprehensive way.122 Moreover, as almost
half a century of effort using that approach has shown, it is extremely
difficult to limit the amount of money that flows into elections, as long as we
continue to have a privately financed system and an understanding of the First
Amendment that precludes limitations on election spending—a First Amendment constraint
attributable to Buckley v. Valeo,123 not to any more
recent decision. In light of this reality, the best policy we can achieve is
probably to create incentives to encourage this money to be channeled in one
direction rather than another. We should use these incentives to channel that
money to flow through the political parties to a much greater degree than is currently
the case. I have focused on
campaign finance laws merely as one point of entry into my larger theme: the
need to reinvigorate party leaders’ capacity to play a unifying leadership
role. If we turn reform efforts in this direction, instead of the paths more
often advocated, then other suggestions might start springing to mind. For example,
effective governance inevitably requires negotiation, particularly in our
separated-powers system. But little in academic work on democracy, or even
popular accounts of democracy, even addresses issues related to negotiation,
such as the institutional environments or structural conditions that enable
effective negotiations among political leaders. How could law and policy
facilitate these structures and conditions? Part of our
romanticization of democracy has been reflected in an extreme emphasis on
greater transparency as a solution to our democratic anxieties. In our culture,
it is difficult to defend the need for secrecy in negotiations. But compare the
environment in which successful international negotiations still work today (at
least before WikiLeaks) to the ways in which our laws and culture of
transparency have transformed the environment in which domestic negotiations
over policy take place. After the 1976
Government in the Sunshine Act required that congressional committee meetings
to be public, surveys of senators soon concluded that these open meeting
requirements were the largest single cause of a decline in the ability to
negotiate and to make politically difficult tradeoffs.124 Today, we have the unfortunate Federal
Advisory Committee Act,125 which extends these open-meeting
requirements even to bodies that only provide advice to the federal government and
ties these advisory groups in knots for little meaningful public benefit. If
negotiations among leaders are a key to effective governance, particularly in
polarized times, then we need a less moralistic, more realistic sense of the
conditions under which negotiations effectively take place. One structural
condition for productive negotiation in theory and practice is likely to be the
presence of long-term players who will interact over multiple negotiations.
One-shot bargaining games are notoriously more prone to strategic withholding
and manipulation of information, since there is no threat of future sanction in
subsequent negotiations. In the political realm, this suggests that whatever
the downsides to long-term incumbencies, one advantage that longer-serving
members of Congress are likely to have is greater informational knowledge about
what the other side values most and what it can afford to trade; which threats
are realistic and which are bluffs; and the ability to trade off issues across
time and policy spaces—an ability that can enable productive compromise.126 Once again, the presence of long-term
players is a structural condition that tends to favor the role of party
leaders, since they tend to have served for long tenures, along with other more
senior members. This is yet another
reason why changes that empower recent arrivals to Congress might also make it
more difficult to forge deals across partisan lines. To be sure, safe
homogenous seats can yield long series of terms of office for candidates who
can afford to appeal to more extreme poles of the spectrum without an electoral
cost; once again, we face tradeoffs between democratic values. But the
importance of repeat players to effective democratic negotiation in legislative
bodies brings out a downside to another romantic but counterproductive populist
“reform” of the democratic process: the movement for term-limits (especially
short ones) for state legislators, in an effort to elect more “citizen
legislators.”127 Yet term limits seem not to have any effect
on the composition of those elected to office.128 The term limit effort was also designed to
make legislators more accountable to the public. However, the effect of term
limits is to “weaken the legislative branch relative to the executive;”129 to empower legislative staff, who can invest
in long-term development of policymaking expertise; to boost interest groups,
upon whom less experienced legislators become more dependent for information;
and to force legislators to adopt shorter time horizons that are in tension
with the longer-term, repeat interactions that make for effective political negotiation
and problem solving.130 A second structural
condition for effective negotiation across political divisions is, as suggested
above, the ability for certain stages of the discussion and negotiation process
to take place outside the public eye. Indeed, contrary to the popular emphasis
on the pervasive importance of full transparency, studies of this issue now
cause leading social science reports to issue such strong statements as that
“the empirical evidence on the deliberative benefits of closed-door
interactions seems incontrovertible.”131 Perhaps the reasons this is so are obvious,
but they are nonetheless worth stating briefly, given the far greater emphasis
the “democratic” benefits of transparency have received in recent decades. When
the audience for a negotiation is public, the parties are encouraged to posture
for their own constituents and, sometimes, to stand for principle by refusing
to compromise. When negotiations take place in less public arenas, parties
typically feel free to take greater risks in revealing their positions, the
issues on which they have the most intense preferences, the issues on which
they can give, and the benefits they must attain in return for any compromises
they make. Similarly, negotiations work as part of packages of tradeoffs, but
disclosing any one potential compromise in isolation, before the entire package
of countervailing compromises has been agreed upon, can easily scuttle any
potential deal. That is why, of course, one effective tactic for undermining
negotiations is to leak the details of one potential dimension of compromise
before the full range of provisions has been settled. Open negotiations can
themselves foster polarization, which is why peace negotiations are frequently
carried out in secret.132 The demand for
greater transparency has been driven, of course, by genuine democratic
concerns, including concerns regarding corrupt deals—ones that do not adequately
take into account the full range of appropriate interests—or concerns that
important affected interests will not be heard. One way to reframe the costs
and benefits of transparency to democracy might therefore be to focus less on
demanding full transparency of processes
and more on asking for transparency of
the reasons and purposes that explain and justify outcomes.133 The adoption of the Constitution provides
one example: while the negotiations at the Constitutional Convention were held
in secret, there was a robust, public ratification debate in which the justifications
for various provisions, and the arguments against, were extensively tested in a
prolonged open process.134 Of course, any decision to permit greater
space for private democratic negotiation would itself be a decision that in
most contexts would have to be made publicly and be publicly justified—though
there are some contexts in which even the fact that negotiation is taking place
might have to remain secret initially to have any chance of success. Additionally,
insulating the processes of negotiation from constant public monitoring to a
greater degree would require policymakers to generate trust in the negotiating
process itself. This might in turn necessitate public disclosure of the participants
in the process, in order to ensure all relevant interests are represented, but
without necessarily disclosing the detailed, step-by-step substantive proposals
within the negotiation process itself. There are many controversial issues at
stake, to be sure, in advocating greater space for less public policymaking
negotiating spaces. However, we need to begin to take seriously the reality
that full transparency can be in considerable tension with the prospects for
productive negotiations and hence effective democratic governance in polarized
times. A third implication
of moving away from the romanticized model of democratic governance is as
follows. In a few short years we have learned that ending earmarks has
eliminated one of the most direct benefits that party leadership could bestow
upon recalcitrant members to generate their support on major legislation.135 A de-romanticized and less purist view of
democracy might also have to accept that certain kinds of public
side-payments—logrolling is itself an example, of course—are necessary to
enable the compromise and negotiation required for government to function more
rather than less effectively. Successful negotiation takes advantage of
differential intensities of preferences; members of Congress who are moderately
opposed or indifferent to legislation can have strong preferences for the
concentrated benefits that public projects in their state or districts offer.
Bans on bringing certain dimensions of policy into the negotiation dynamic can
make tradeoffs and productive compromises more difficult. Let me return to where I began. For many years now, private law scholarship
has focused on the consequences of its rules for the dynamics of private power
in contexts like market settings. My aim, and what I view as the aim for “the
law of democracy,” is to do the same for public law, in the context of democratic
elections and governance. This approach
recommends that we think in terms of measures that would encourage the forces
of centralized authority within the political parties and discourage the forces
of political fragmentation. Stronger parties are likely to remain the most
effective vehicle for enabling the compromises and deals that are necessary in
the face of what will be the ongoing polarization of the parties in government.
Put another way, the problem is not that we have parliamentary-like parties; it
is, I suggest, that our political parties are not parliamentary-like enough. The obstacles to any
changes along these lines will not merely be entrenched interests. In
overcoming these obstacles, it will be just as necessary and important to
confront head-on two powerful cultural trends that will generate resistance to
publicly financed elections through the parties and other measures that aim at
re-empowering political leaders. The first is
America’s exceptional and distinct ideology of “popular participation.” Any
change in the democratic system that aims to empower political leaders will be
cast in terms of Manichean conflict between “the people” and “the elites.”
America’s cultural self-understanding of democracy has always invoked a
rhetoric of “popular sovereignty” that is far more populist in meaning than in
other Western democracies. But it is increasingly becoming clear, in our era at
least, that the much greater participation enabled by the communication
revolution breeds polarization as well as fragmentation. Instead of viewing a
relentless expansion of participatory reforms as the cure for what ails democracy,
we should start recognizing a perhaps-tragic tradeoff between the desire to
make government more accountable, through measures like enhanced popular
participation, and the capacity for government to function effectively. In the
past, for example, I have supported matching private-public election financing
systems, such as the system used in New York City and now being adopted elsewhere.
But for the reasons I discussed earlier, I have become wary that these systems
will only exacerbate polarization and fragmentation. Indeed, one recent study
has found that in “clean-money” public financing systems, such as systems that
match public dollars to private contributions, candidates’ positions move
farther away from the ideological center of public policy preferences once the
clean money system has been adopted.136 The mechanism involved, this study suggests,
is candidates’ need to appeal to ideologically extreme individual donors to
qualify for public funds. Other studies do not reach such conclusions,137 and it is too early with these systems to
draw conclusions about whether individual donor-based public financing systems
will contribute to polarization. But we should be alert to the possibility that
they will, and we ought not take for granted that individual donor-based public
financing systems will inevitably and automatically reflect the actual
distribution of policy preferences among the general electorate. Second, efforts to
empower party leadership will run into America’s characteristic and unique
distrust of political parties. Part of the culturally distinctive understanding
of “popular sovereignty” in America has been a romantically individualist
vision of democracy: a vision that sees organizational intermediaries between
citizens and government, such as political parties, as a corruption of true
democracy. Furthermore, if parties must be tolerated, then they must be put
under the control of “the people” as much as possible; hence the Progressive
Era anti-party creation of the mandatory primary election. Therefore, a robust
ideological defense of political parties, as well as of party and political
leadership, will have to be willingly and forthrightly undertaken in order to
mobilize support for any set of practical measures that seek to re-empower party
leadership. If I am right that
the problem is effective governance; that political fragmentation might be a
more productive focal point for effective reform efforts than polarization per
se; and that the right direction for fresh thought is how to re-empower
political and party leaders, then it is also necessary to understand the deep
sources of resistance that must be engaged as a prelude to any practical
movement along this path. These sources lie in the distinctly American
attachment to a romantic vision of democracy centered on the individual
citizen, rather than on effective governance and the central role of organized
political power, particularly the political parties, in determining how well a
democratic system actually functions in delivering the appropriate level and
forms of public goods. American democracy has always rested on a balance between a
mythology of “popular sovereignty” and the reality of what is needed to
organize political and governing power effectively. The key to effective
democracy might be cast in the following way: we need to sustain the
appropriate elements of popular participation while maintaining a coherent and
decisive enough structure of political leadership to enable effective
governance. We have to be
careful not be seduced by an overly romantic and
individualized conception of democracy that has a deeper resonance in American
political culture and history than in any other nation. We should also be
careful about invoking democratic values, such as political equality, freedom
of association and speech, and participation, in overly idealized and abstract
terms that fail to attend to the actual consequences of institutionalizing
these values in particular ways on effective political power and governance.
This is a particular risk for legal scholarship and advocacy, both of which
tend to be based more on analysis and argument concerning values and principles
than on empirical facts about the actual organization of effective political
power. I realize there will be no rousing ovation for any of this. Who cheers
for centralizing more power in the political parties at a time when the parties
are at their least appealing? Who cheers, worse yet, for a particularly elitist
vision of the political parties, centered on empowering party leaders? People
will not “go to the streets” in favor of political parties and party elites.
All this runs counter to the DNA of America’s democratic sensibilities. But that is part of my purpose: to challenge those sensibilities. In the
midst of the declining governing capacity of the American democratic order, we
ought to focus less on “participation” as the magical solution and more on the
real dynamics of how to facilitate the organization of effective political power.
I have tried, today, to give you a glimpse into this alternative,
institutionalist approach to democracy and legal thought.Introduction
I. political
fragmentation
II. democratic romanticism
III. the causes of polarization
IV. political power, political
parties
V. structural
decline in the power of party leaders
VI. a
party-based campaign finance system
VII. making deal-making possible
VIII. less romanticized visions of
democracy
Conclusion