Contraception as a Sex Equality Right
“Not
only the sex discrimination cases, but the cases on contraception, abortion,
and illegitimacy as well, present various faces of a single issue: the roles
women are to play in society. Are women to have the opportunity to participate
in full partnership with men in the nation’s social, political, and economic
life?”
—Ruth Bader Ginsburg, 19781 “The
ability of women to participate equally in the economic and social life of the
Nation has been facilitated by their ability to control their reproductive
lives.” —Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 19922 Challenges to federal law requiring insurance coverage of
contraception are occurring on the eve of the fiftieth anniversary of the U.S.
Supreme Court’s decision in Griswold v.
Connecticut.3 It is a good time to reflect on the
values served by protecting women’s access to contraception. In 1965, the Court
ruled in Griswold that a law
criminalizing the use of contraception violated the
privacy of the marriage relationship. Griswold
offered women the most significant constitutional protection since the
Nineteenth Amendment gave women the right to vote,4 constitutional protection as important as
the cases prohibiting sex discrimination that the Court would decide in the
next decade5—perhaps even more so. Griswold is conventionally understood to have secured liberty for
women. But, we argue, the right to contraception also secures equality for women, as Ruth Bader Ginsburg
saw clearly in the 1970s and as the Court eventually would explain in Planned Parenthood v. Casey. Because Griswold was decided before the sex
equality claims and cases of the 1970s, the Griswold
Court did not expressly appeal to equality values in explaining the importance
of constitutionally protected liberty—as, for example, the Casey Court did.6
Yet as some contemporaries appreciated, in protecting decisions concerning the
timing of childbearing, the Griswold
Court was protecting the foundations of equal opportunity for women, given the
organization of work and family roles in American society. Today, those who appreciate contraception’s singular
importance to women call recent attacks on contraception a “war on women.”7
Yet even now, it may not be immediately clear that the right to contraception
is a sex-equality right. Both men and women use contraception, even if the
forms of contraception that they use are sex-differentiated. The Connecticut
statute banning contraception applied to both sexes. Analyzing the right to contraception in historical context
helps to clarify the ways in which the right to contraception secures equality,
as well as liberty, for women. As Griswold
turns fifty, we return to the historical record to demonstrate that the ban on
contraception struck down in that case was enforced in ways that reflected and
reinforced traditional gender roles. Even though the law was written to apply
to both sexes, the state applied the law to men and women differently. In
recovering this history, we show how the regulation of contraception is tied to
double standards in sex and parenting. Recognizing these deep and enduring
differences in gender roles demonstrates why denying women control over the
timing of childbearing denies them equal citizenship. With these concerns in
view, it becomes clear why judicial decisions and laws securing access to
effective and affordable contraception vindicate both equality and liberty
values.8 Contraception was first banned under federal and state law
not in the Founding era, but in the decade after the Civil War. The 1873
Comstock Act was premised on the view that it was obscene to separate sex and
procreation.9 Soon after, many states passed laws
modeled on the Comstock Act criminalizing contraception and abortion.10
Like the federal law, Connecticut’s ban on contraception drew
no formal distinctions by sex; rather, it prohibited “[a]ny
person” from “us[ing] any drug, medicinal article or instrument for the purpose
of preventing conception.”11 Even so,
contemporaries understood the judgments about nonprocreative sex in the federal
and state laws through Victorian mores concerned with differences in the
physical and social relations of reproduction.12
The Comstock Act, for example, was enacted a year after Justice Bradley
explained that “[t]he constitution of the family
organization, which is founded in the divine ordinance, as well as in the
nature of things, indicates the domestic sphere as that which properly belongs
to the domain and functions of womanhood.”13
Doctors reasoned that women who enjoyed sex while endeavoring to avoid its natural
procreative consequences engaged in “physiological sin”—and predicted that they
would suffer health harms as a result.14
Press coverage of the Comstock Act focused on women who were prosecuted for
defying the ban.15
The new bans on contraception applied to all at a time when
men and women were held to gender-differentiated double standards in matters of
sex and parenting. Men were entitled to breach prevailing sexual norms in ways
that women were not, and women were expected to assume parenting responsibilities
in ways that men were not.16 By the twentieth century, Connecticut and many other
jurisdictions relaxed enforcement of Comstock laws in ways that reflected these
role-based judgments about men and women. During World War I, the U.S. military
concluded that providing condoms to men significantly lowered the rates of
sexually transmitted diseases and authorized the use of condoms for preventing
disease.17
Following the federal government’s lead, the Massachusetts high court
crafted an exception to the state’s ban on contraception permitting use of condoms
to prevent the spread of venereal disease.18
The court recognized an implied exception to the ban that would protect men’s
health, even though two years earlier the court had reasoned that the ban was
absolute and prohibited the sale of contraceptives to married women on a
physician’s prescription to preserve their lives or health.19
The court granted a health exception to men—even when their lives were not
threatened by venereal disease20—after having
refused a health exception for women even when their lives were threatened by
pregnancy.21 Gendered assumptions about sex and parenting also shaped
enforcement of Connecticut’s ban on contraception, giving rise to sex equality
concerns of several kinds in Griswold.
By the mid-twentieth century, it was widely understood that
one could buy contraceptives in drug stores in Connecticut. The state deemed
the threat of venereal disease sufficiently compelling to make a health
exception to its law banning contraception. This exception allowed pharmacies
to sell condoms under the auspices of “disease prevention” as well as certain
products for “feminine hygiene” that might have contraceptive properties.22 Yet like Massachusetts, the
Connecticut Supreme Court rejected a health exception to the ban that would
allow doctors to prescribe contraception for women physically unable to
tolerate pregnancy or childbirth.23 The court
advised women with a medical need for contraception that they should simply
abstain from sex,24 but did not advise men to protect
themselves from the risk of venereal disease in this fashion. Instead, the
state allowed men to buy condoms on demand in the state’s drug stores, while
making no effort to ensure that men (particularly married men) actually were
using condoms to prevent disease, as opposed to conception.25
Connecticut’s crafting of a health exception for men, but not
for women, led to a second inequality in the state’s enforcement of its ban on
contraception. Connecticut enforced the ban so as to allow men easy access to
the most effective form of contraception for men (condoms), but to deny women access
to the most effective forms of contraception for women (diaphragms or the
pill).26 At oral argument in Griswold, Justice Brennan repeatedly
asked whether the plaintiffs were challenging this pattern of enforcement on
equal protection grounds.27 Law professor
Thomas Emerson, who with Catherine Roraback represented the plaintiffs,
responded that discriminatory enforcement of the statutes was part of the
plaintiffs’ due process claim.28 By providing health exceptions for men but not for women, and
by allowing men but not women access to the most effective forms of
contraception, Connecticut enforced its ban so as to give men more control than
women in separating sex and childbearing. Connecticut’s disparate treatment of
men and women was constitutionally significant because it reflected and
reinforced traditional gender roles in sex and parenting. Indeed, because of gender differences in the physical and
social relations of reproduction, laws restricting contraception present
equality questions for women, even if the restrictions on contraception are
evenly enforced against both sexes. Given the organization of education and
work, laws restricting contraception deny education and employment
opportunities to those who bear and rear children. Litigants expressed this
understanding on the path to Griswold
with increasing clarity. For example, law students at Yale who were represented
by Catherine Roraback argued that the state’s ban on contraception deprived
students of control over the timing of childbearing, which, they asserted, was
needed in order to obtain a professional education.29
Reflecting this understanding, the ACLU’s amicus brief in Griswold argued that Connecticut’s ban
on contraception violated equal protection: [T]he right of the individual to engage in any of the common
occupations . . . applies to women as well as men. . . . [I]n
addition to its economic consequences, the ability to regulate child-bearing
has been a significant factor in the emancipation of married women. In this respect,
effective means of contraception rank equally with the Nineteenth Amendment in
enhancing the opportunities of women who wish to work in industry, business,
the arts, and the professions. Thus, the equal protection clause protects the
class of women who wish to delay or regulate child-bearing
effectively.30 Remarkably, the ACLU uttered those
words in 1965. In the decade after Griswold, women challenged beliefs
about “separate spheres” that restricted women to childrearing and men to
breadwinning. In 1970, on the fiftieth anniversary of the ratification of the
Nineteenth Amendment, a “second wave” feminist movement organized a national
“Strike for Equality” in which it argued that equal citizenship required not
only equal suffrage and the ratification of an Equal Rights Amendment, but also
laws changing the work and family arrangements in which women bear and rear children.31 The
Supreme Court responded, reading the Equal Protection Clause for the first time
to prohibit sex classifications in laws that impose caregiver and breadwinner
roles on women and men.32 Yet
then and now, the Court’s sex discrimination cases allow, but do not require,
changes in the organization of work that would help women and men to integrate
caregiving and breadwinning.33 Today, no less than at the time of Griswold, control over
the timing of childbirth is indispensable if those who raise children are to
have equal opportunities to participate in the worlds of education, employment,
and politics. The right that the Court recognized in Griswold helps to secure equality as
well as liberty for women. (In fact, in extending the contraception right to
unmarried women and men in Eisenstadt v.
Baird,34
the Court applied the equal protection framework of Reed v. Reed,35 perhaps
reflecting a dawning recognition that equality values were at stake.) In Griswold, as in Casey and Lawrence v. Texas,
the Court protected equality values as an integral part of due process.36
Equality values anchor not only the individual’s right to
contraception free of government interference, but also the government’s
authority to help individuals secure access to contraception. The Court’s
decisions declaring compelling interests in eradicating race and sex
discrimination make clear that those compelling
interests encompass both core concerns of the community and crucial concerns of
the individuals who are the intended beneficiaries of the law’s protections.37
The Court’s decision in Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores38
reflects this understanding.39 Writing for
the Court, Justice Alito invoked the constitutional right recognized in Griswold in the course of discussing the
government’s compelling interests in providing employees insurance coverage of
contraception.40
Because women’s health, liberty, and equal citizenship stature are at stake in
ways that matter to individuals and to the society as a whole, governments have
compelling interests in ensuring access to effective and affordable
contraception.41
Neil
S. Siegel is David W. Ichel Professor of Law, Duke Law School. Reva B. Siegel
is Nicholas deB. Katzenbach Professor of Law, Yale Law
School. They thank Allison Day for extraordinary research assistance,
and Kate Bartlett, Cary Franklin, Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Serena Mayeri, Melissa
Murray, Doug NeJaime, and Ryan Williams for excellent suggestions. Preferred Citation:
Neil S. Siegel & Reva B. Siegel, Contraception
as a Sex Equality Right, 124 Yale
L.J. F. 349 (2015),
http://www.yalelawjournal.org/forum/contraception-as-a-sex-equality-right.I. contraception,
sex, and motherhood in the century after the civil war
II. griswold and disparate treatment