Border Checkpoints and Substantive Due Process: Abortion Rights in the Border Zone
abstract. This Note assesses the constitutionality of Texas House Bill 2 (H.B. 2), which regulates abortion providers, as applied to clinics located in the area between the state’s border with Mexico and internal federal immigration checkpoints. Should these statutory provisions go into full effect and lead to these clinics’ closure, undocumented immigrants living in the border zone will need to pass through the internal checkpoints to reach abortion clinics elsewhere in the state. The Note evaluates the Texas statutory provisions as applied to border-zone clinics using two distinct analytical frameworks: the undue burden analysis specific to abortion jurisprudence and the doctrine of unconstitutional conditions. The Note concludes that under either approach, H.B. 2, as applied to these clinics, violates the reproductive rights of undocumented immigrants and is therefore unconstitutional. The rights burden created for this group by Texas’s law regulating abortion clinics illuminates both the way in which federal-state allocations of power in the border zone may endanger substantive due process rights and, more broadly, the relationship between geographic space and substantive due process.
Yale Law School, J.D. expected 2016. For comments and conversations, I am grateful to Aurelia Chaudhury, Hilary Ledwell, Urja Mittal, and Joshua Revesz. Thanks to Zayn Siddique, Rebecca Lee, and Michael Clemente for thoughtful editing. I am especially grateful to Judith Resnik and Michael Wishnie for guidance and incisive suggestions.
United States Border Patrol checkpoints lace the interior of
Texas and other southern border states, typically lying twenty-five to
seventy-five miles from the border with Mexico.1 Federal law permits immigration
officers “to board and search for aliens . . . any railway car, aircraft,
conveyance, or vehicle” located “within a reasonable distance from any external
boundary of the United States.”2 At the checkpoints, agents may,
pursuant to the Supreme Court’s holding in United
States v. Martinez-Fuerte, “brief[ly] det[ain] . . . travelers” and
“require[] of the vehicle’s occupants . . . a response to a brief question or
two and possibly the production of a document evidencing a right to be in the
United States.”3 For those within the “border
zone”—the area of land between federal interior immigration checkpoints
and the international border—travel to the rest of the country
functionally requires an encounter with federal immigration enforcement.4
As a result, unauthorized immigrants living within the border zone avoid such
travel and find their world effectively circumscribed by the checkpoints.5 State laws and regulations with
spatially disparate effects, such as recently enacted Texas legislation that
compels widespread closure of abortion clinics, therefore have particular
significance for undocumented immigrants in the border zone.6 In 2013, the State of Texas enacted Texas House Bill 2 (H.B.
2), which regulates abortion providers and could result in the closure of all
abortion clinics south and west of internal immigration checkpoints in the
state.7
H.B. 2 requires that all abortion clinics in Texas meet the facility
requirements for ambulatory surgical centers and that all doctors performing
abortions have hospital admitting privileges within thirty miles of their
clinics.8
The legislation has led to the closure of many clinics in the state9 and has engendered both controversy
and litigation. An as-applied challenge, focusing on the extent to which courts
ought to probe legislatures’ health-premised justifications for narrowing
abortion availability, has reached the Supreme Court.10
The abortion providers in Texas’s border area are among those unable to meet
H.B. 2’s requirements: both the Whole Woman’s Health Clinic in McAllen, a city
in Texas’s southern Rio Grande Valley, and the two clinics in El Paso, the
metropolitan area at Texas’s westernmost tip, have not been able to do so.11 Because of H.B. 2, undocumented immigrants living in southern
and western Texas face the potential closures of the only three abortion
clinics in the state that do not require travel through internal immigration
checkpoints from the border area. Roughly 822,500 women live in the Rio Grande
Valley and the nearby city of Laredo, within the border zone in the southern
part of the state.12
Roughly fifty thousand have neither citizenship nor legal immigration status
and are of reproductive age.13 Were the McAllen clinic to close,
the border checkpoints would physically stand between these women and obtaining
an abortion under medical care. The undocumented women in the area would not be
able to obtain an abortion under medical care unless they were to risk
deportation by traveling through the checkpoints, risk death by attempting to
circumvent them, or successfully obtain lawful presence in the country before
the point at which abortion becomes illegal.14
In west Texas, roughly four hundred twenty-five thousand women live in the
largest metropolitan area, in El Paso County.15
Closure of the El Paso clinics would mean that the approximately twenty-four
thousand undocumented women of reproductive age living in that area would also
need to cross a border checkpoint in order to obtain an abortion in Texas.16 However, these individuals can
currently reach a clinic located south of border checkpoints in New Mexico.17 Whether H.B. 2 and the checkpoints create a constitutionally
impermissible barrier to abortion access remains significant for this group of
women three years after the statutory provisions became law. The Fifth Circuit has
issued an injunction partially limiting the law’s effect by preserving access
to the McAllen clinic for undocumented immigrants living in some but not all of
the counties within the border zone in South Texas.18
However, the injunction terminates if a clinic opens closer to the Rio Grande Valley
yet beyond the checkpoints and its enjoinment of the admitting privileges
requirement extends only to a single, part-time doctor named in the opinion.19 Because the injunction is
underinclusive with respect to undocumented women in the border zone and may
terminate, and because the limited relief may not prevent the closure of the
McAllen clinic, the separate question of the checkpoints’ import to H.B. 2’s
application to the clinics persists. If access to abortion rights must be
evaluated within the confines of one’s state,20
then the El Paso clinic poses constitutional concerns as well. From a
theoretical perspective, the broader question of how to think about potential
barriers to vindication of substantive due process rights posed by the
conjunction of federal immigration enforcement and state regulatory law remains
open as well. This Note identifies and explicates an overlooked
constitutional problem with H.B. 2, as applied to the border-zone clinics: in
light of the backdrop of federal immigration enforcement, the Texas law
violates the reproductive rights of more than eighty thousand women. In
evaluating the potential rights burden imposed on undocumented women in the
border zone by H.B. 2, the Note applies two analytical frameworks of
constitutional law: the undue burden analysis specific to substantive due
process abortion jurisprudence and the unconstitutional-conditions doctrine.
The Note determines that H.B. 2 violates the reproductive rights of
undocumented immigrants in the Texas border area under either analysis. Part I
characterizes the spatially selective immigration enforcement regime that forms
the backdrop to state legislation and notes the omission of the spatially
disparate effect of H.B. 2 from litigation challenging the law. Under the undue
burden framework, Part II argues, H.B. 2 has the effect of deterring
undocumented women from seeking an abortion. Under the unconstitutional-conditions
framework, as Part III explicates, the law violates undocumented women’s
abortion rights by conditioning abortion access on exposure to immigration
enforcement. The causal set that gives rise to the rights burden is unusual: it
is comprised of federal immigration enforcement, state statutory provisions
regulating abortion clinics, and unauthorized immigrants’ (lack of) immigration
status. Part IV addresses an important set of counterarguments: it argues that
on either framework analysis, and notwithstanding the other elements of the
causal set, the state legislation is causally responsible for the violation.
This conclusion is both doctrinally accurate and most consonant with constitutional
commitments to individual rights in the border zone. This Note is the first work to analyze the implications of
the confluence of state laws with spatially disparate effects and internal
checkpoints for the fundamental rights of undocumented immigrants. This
confluence highlights the way in which the area along the U.S.-Mexico border
inverts federalism protections for a vulnerable minority group that can exercise
neither exit nor voice. It also provides one example of the significance of the
undertheorized relationship between substantive due process rights and
political and physical space. The interior Border Patrol checkpoints create a system of
spatially selective immigration enforcement within the United States.21 Individuals driving north from the
cities, towns, and ranches along the international border must, eventually,
stop at a roadblock set up along the highway.22 Implementing regulations interpret
the “reasonable distance” contemplated in the federal statute authorizing
immigration searches as “within 100 air miles from any external boundary of the
United States or any shorter distance” determined by certain Department of
Homeland Security officials.23 At a
checkpoint within this “reasonable distance,” a Border Patrol agent asks all
occupants of the vehicle if they are United States citizens.24 The agent may then refer individuals
to secondary screening for further questioning as to their legal status in the
United States.25
If the Border Patrol agent determines that there is probable cause, individuals
may be searched, detained, and, eventually, either charged with a crime or
entered into immigration removal proceedings.26 The Supreme Court has upheld
warrantless vehicle stops without particularized suspicion at Border Patrol
checkpoints against a Fourth Amendment challenge.27 Consequently, for those within the border zone, traveling
into the interior of the United States requires reckoning with this legal and
physical architecture of empire.28 In Texas, the border zone encompasses
the cities of El Paso and Laredo, the area of southern Texas called the Rio
Grande Valley (including the cities of McAllen and Brownsville), and the
smaller towns and ranches that dot the border. It is home to more than 2.4
million people in the state.29 The Border
Patrol maintains a web of “permanent” checkpoints—with physical
buildings, electronic sensors, and remote-surveillance capabilities—and
“tactical” checkpoints on secondary roads, which lack permanent physical
structures.30
Other than by passing through the highway checkpoints or Border Patrol
screening at one of the airports in the region, there is no practical way out
of the border zone and into northern Texas.31
In 2012, more than 120 people died trying to evade the Rio Grande Valley’s
eastern checkpoint by walking through semiarid scrubland.32 Figure 1. border patrol permanent checkpoints along the southwest border Courtesy
of the U.S. Government Accountability Office. Note that this map includes only
permanent, not tactical, checkpoints.
As others have noted,33the Supreme Court’s treatment of Border Patrol checkpoints and standards
for searches within the space between the checkpoints and the international
border make the area what Gerald Neuman has called an “anomalous zone”: a space
“in which certain legal rules, otherwise regarded as embodying fundamental
policies of the larger legal system, are locally suspended.”34 In the border zone, these suspended
rules include the typical Fourth Amendment limitations on searches and
seizures.35 In areas in Texas and other states
on the southern border, Border Patrol agents require only a reasonable
suspicion that an individual is a noncitizen—not probable cause—to
effectuate a stop south of the checkpoints.36
And exiting this area and reaching the rest of the state (and country) requires a warrantless seizure, without particularized
suspicion, at the checkpoint.37 The Supreme Court has justified
these deviations from ordinary Fourth Amendment restrictions by explaining that
the Border Patrol seeks to keep undocumented persons from moving into the rest
of the country, beyond the border zone.38 But, as the Court has also recognized, the border zone is not
just a place of transit: it is also a place where many people live and work,
and that many call home.39 Justice
Powell’s majority opinion in United
States v. Brignoni-Ponce, upholding roving patrols near the border, noted
that major cities, including San Diego, El Paso, and the cities of the Rio
Grande Valley, lie within the border zone.40 In requiring reasonableness for
stops in this area, Justice Powell explained that the lack of such a requirement
“would subject the residents of these and other areas to potentially unlimited
interference with their use of the highways.”41
The opinion expressed the view that while undocumented immigrants use roads in
the region to obtain “transportation . . . to inland cities”—“seeking to
enter the country illegally”—highways in the area “carry . . . a
large volume of legitimate traffic as well.”42
The next year, in upholding brief seizures at fixed checkpoints, the Court
explained that the enforcement was part of a larger effort to “[i]nterdict the
flow of illegal entrants from Mexico” who “seek to travel inland” for
employment opportunities.43 As the conception of the border area in these opinions
illustrates, courts do not necessarily recognize and respond to the border zone
as a site where not just citizens and those with lawful immigration status but
also undocumented persons reside.44
The dichotomy depicted in the Fourth Amendment border-area cases—between
citizens and lawful permanent residents who live in the border zone, on the one
hand, and undocumented immigrants who pass through the area in order to enter
into the interior to obtain work—does not capture the reality of the
space. Estimates suggest that at least two hundred fifteen thousand of those
living in the border zone are unauthorized immigrants—over seventy-five
percent of whom have lived in the United States for at least five years, and
over fifty percent of whom have resided in the country for at least ten years.45
These are not individuals treating the area as a transient space. The many undocumented persons living in southern Texas are
therefore subject to an enforcement regime that this Note calls, as a
shorthand, “spatially selective immigration enforcement.” This enforcement is
spatially selective in that it involves specific questioning as to immigration
status at the internal checkpoints, for those who attempt to travel beyond the
border zone.46 Within the border zone, an encounter
with the Border Patrol is not certain and requires reasonable suspicion. It is
an attempt to travel beyond the border zone that leads to exposure to spatially
selective immigration enforcement and its attendant potential for deportation.47
The fact that many undocumented immigrants remain in southern Texas for a
decade or longer indicates that, by staying within the border zone, individuals
are able to remain within the American community—but only within a
spatially restricted part of that community.48 Legal scholarship has highlighted the constitutional
challenges posed by “anomalous zones” more generally49
and by the border zone in particular.50 The border-area scholarship has
primarily focused on the Fourth Amendment issues engendered by the border and the
related Supreme Court jurisprudence.51
Scholars have also probed race-based immigration policing in the border zone.52
Yet, the functional restriction on undocumented immigrants’ movement created by
the checkpoints also implicates access to certain substantive rights where
exercise of those rights requires travel. Potential ramifications of this
anomalous zone for substantive due process rights remain unexplored. Analyzing
H.B. 2’s effect on unauthorized immigrants’ abortion rights therefore provides
a case study that illuminates the unique constitutional conundrum posed by the
checkpoints: spatially selective immigration enforcement functionally bars
movement out of the area, preventing individuals from exercising their rights. In the context of H.B. 2, the spatially selective nature of
immigration enforcement intersects with a spatial dimension to substantive due
process—specifically, here, to abortion access.53 Much recent abortion litigation has
centered on how the exercise of the right depends on the ability to travel and
spatial proximity to clinics. In particular, the passage of state laws aimed at
closing clinics has generated litigation regarding the undue burden posed by
increased travel time.54 The Seventh
Circuit’s most recent opinion evaluating the effects of travel, in the context
of a potential preliminary injunction, included a map that charted out travel
distance in concentric circles from a town where a Planned Parenthood clinic
would close if the law were not enjoined.55
The potential closure of all abortion clinics in Mississippi implicated the
spatiality of abortion rights in a slightly different manner, raising the
question of whether a state must ensure access to a fundamental right within
its borders.56
H.B. 2, against the backdrop of the checkpoints, creates a third variant of these
spatial questions: whether the closure of clinics, requiring an encounter with
law enforcement in traveling to abortion clinics, violates the reproductive
rights of the group of people for whom that law enforcement is relevant. Travel
time raises questions in terms of spatial access as a sliding scale; H.B. 2 and
the checkpoints threaten to create, for a certain group, a de facto bar to
vindication of the right. The Mississippi regulations raise questions about
horizontal federalism; H.B. 2 and the border zone lead to questions about
rights vindication in the context of federal-state allocations of power in
anomalous zones. The significance of the closure of abortion clinics in the
border zone—and deeper theoretical implications for understandings of
federalism and individual rights in the border zone—is also unexplored in
legal scholarship. Scholars have analyzed the significance of the Texas
abortion restrictions in thinking through legal disabilities experienced by
Latinas living in southern Texas57 and in analyzing the ways that
courts fail to perceive rights barriers created by the nature of rural areas.58
Yet, while media reports have highlighted the major hurdle that checkpoints
could pose to undocumented women seeking an abortion, scholarship has not
separately explored this potential burden.59 The doctrinal puzzle raised by H.B. 2 and the
checkpoints—whether there is in fact a violation of fundamental
rights—has also been largely missing from the litigation surrounding H.B.
2. In examining the law’s effects, the two challenges brought by reproductive-rights
advocates have primarily focused on the distance
women must travel to access abortion clinics. In the first case, Planned Parenthood v. Abbott, the Fifth
Circuit upheld H.B. 2’s requirement that doctors performing abortions have
admitting privileges at a hospital within thirty miles, against, inter alia, a
facial Fourteenth Amendment substantive due process challenge.60 At trial, a reproductive health
clinic executive testified as to the barrier that women with border-crossing
cards—statuses for Mexican nationals that restrict lawful presence to
within a certain distance from the border—would face in attempting to
cross through internal checkpoints to reach the nearest abortion clinic.61 A Fifth Circuit motions panelnoted this testimony but determined in
one sentence, “This obstacle is unrelated to the hospital-admitting-privileges
requirement.”62 The second challenge to H.B. 2, Whole Woman’s Health v. Hellerstedt, has involved a facial and an as-applied
challenge to the provision requiring abortion facilities to meet the required
standards for ambulatory surgical centers and an as-applied challenge to the
statute’s hospital admitting privileges requirement, for the McAllen and El
Paso clinics.63
Discussion of H.B. 2’s effects in this litigation has also centered on travel
distance: the Fifth Circuit’s ruling provided some relief as applied to the
McAllen clinic because of the undue burden created by travel time.64 The plaintiffs’ trial brief and some
testimony from a witness for the plaintiffs at trial noted the barrier faced by
women with border-crossing cards.65 The district-court
opinion listed “immigration status and inability to pass border checkpoints”
among eight “practical” obstacles beyond travel distance that, together,
indicated that the statute created substantial obstacles for women.66
Neither the motions panel nor the merits panel at the Fifth Circuit treated
“immigration status” distinctly or discussed the checkpoints. An amicus brief
at the Supreme Court argues that the law creates an undue burden for Latinas in
Texas in part because of “[f]ear of immigration stops . . . near the Mexican
border” when traveling, including fear “of passing immigration checkpoints.”67 The border checkpoints pose, though, an independent legal
obstacle for rights access in the border zone. Irrespective of travel-distance burdens, the next three Parts
argue, state legislation leading to clinic closure in the border area gives
rise to problems of rights access that make that legislation constitutionally
impermissible. Even if there were no travel-distance problems and no other
factors burdening abortion access—even if there were clinics just on the
other side of checkpoints located close to the border—state regulations forcing
clinics to shutter, such that immigration enforcement is physically positioned
between an undocumented individual and the locus of rights vindication, would
be unconstitutional. H.B. 2 provides a case study of the relationship between a
spatial administrative enforcement regime that functionally bars travel for
certain individuals and access to substantive due process rights premised on a
presupposition of the ability to travel. Parts II and III analyze H.B. 2 as
applied to the clinics in southern and western Texas using two different
doctrinal methodologies: in Part II, the undue burden test first articulated in
Justice O’Connor’s plurality opinion in Planned
Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey,68
and in Part III, the transsubstantive unconstitutional conditions doctrine.
Before reaching these two analytical frameworks, however, two preliminary
clarifications are necessary: one factual and the other legal. First, this analysis starts from the factual point of
departure that the means for unauthorized immigrants to legally cross border
checkpoints put forward by Customs and Border Protection, parole in place, is
not a realistic alternative that enables vindication of the right to an
abortion previability. Media report that Customs and Border Protection has
indicated that parole may be the appropriate avenue for undocumented women in
southern Texas seeking an abortion.69 The executive branch has discretion
to parole any applicant for admission into the United States “for urgent
humanitarian reasons or significant public benefit.”70
This discretionary parole is available for those already within the territory
of the United States who entered without inspection.71 It is less than clear that
unauthorized immigrants trying to obtain abortions who sought this
discretionaryrelief would
necessarily receive it.72 Even if they
ultimately did receive relief, though, applications for humanitarian parole
“are generally adjudicated within 90-120 business days.”73 Unless one were to apply for parole within
two weeks of becoming pregnant, this time frame would extend beyond the twenty-week
limit on abortion in Texas created by H.B. 2. Second, noncitizens without legal immigration status who are
within the United States have substantive due process rights—as courts
routinely recognize.74 Though this point is well settled,
because it is essential to analyzing H.B. 2’s constitutionality as applied to border-zone
clinics, it merits explication. Textually, substantive due process’s extension
to all individuals within the United States seems evident on the face of the
Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause: “[N]or shall any state deprive any person of life, liberty, or
property, without due process of law.”75
As the Supreme Court stated in 1976 in Mathews
v. Diaz, “The Fifth Amendment, as well as the Fourteenth Amendment,
protects every one of these persons from deprivation of life, liberty, or
property without due process of law. Even
one whose presence in this country is unlawful, involuntary, or transitory
is entitled to that constitutional protection.”76
Since Diaz, both the Supreme Court
and lower federal courts have evaluated whether state action violates
unauthorized immigrants’ substantive due process rights without questioning
whether the Due Process Clause extends to these individuals.77 As one example, in a Ninth Circuit
en banc decision, both the majority and the dissent evaluated whether a state
statute barring the grant of bail to undocumented arrestees violated
substantive due process as a matter of course—without any question from
either side as to whether the Due Process Clause applied.78 As is widely accepted, undocumented
persons have substantive due process rights—and such rights encompass the
right to decide whether to terminate a pregnancy.79 Evaluating H.B. 2 as applied to the border-zone clinics
through the lens of abortion-specific doctrinal analysis highlights the way in
which the anomalous zone in border states, created by federal administrative
law and regulation, has implications for state legislation with spatially
disparate effects. Under the substantive due process doctrine governing
abortion, as delineated in Planned
Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey,80 the backdrop of spatially selective
federal immigration enforcement makes H.B. 2 unconstitutional as applied to
these clinics. Should the McAllen and El Paso clinics close, this Section argues,
undocumented women would experience a “substantial obstacle” to exercising the
fundamental right to choose whether to terminate a pregnancy. The clinic
closures would have the effect of deterring them from exercising that right,
because they would have to pass through the internal checkpoints to do so.
Applying the logic of Casey—particularly
as articulated in its analysis of a state statutory provision requiring spousal
notification, which is closely analogous to this context—shows that H.B.
2 violates the Fourteenth Amendment substantive due process rights of
undocumented immigrants and therefore is unconstitutional as applied to the border-zone
clinics. Substantive due process analysis of H.B. 2 in the border area
requires the use of the Casey
framework.81 Under the “undue burden” standard of
review established in Casey, a
regulation is a constitutionally impermissible undue burden on a woman’s right
to choose if it has either “the purpose or [the] effect of placing a
substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion of a nonviable
fetus.”82
While the litigation regarding H.B. 2 has centered on the purpose analysis, in
thinking about the intersection of border checkpoints and state law, this
aspect of the Casey previability test
is less salient: there is little to no evidence of any legislative intent to
restrict access specifically for undocumented women in the border zone.83
The key question is whether, as applied to the clinics in the border zone, H.B.
2 is unconstitutional because it has the “effect of placing a substantial
obstacle in the path of” women attempting to secure abortions, or whether the
legislation is permissible. And, to determine the answer to that question, it
is essential to consider the effect of clinic closures south of border
checkpoints on a particular group of women—unauthorized immigrants for
whom the clinic closures create a de facto bar to obtaining an abortion. Casey’s spousal-notification analysis illustrates
the proper approach for assessing the burden created by clinic closures in
southern Texas because of the close analogy between three elements of the undue
burden analysis: (1) the relevant classes, (2) the burdens imposed on those
classes, and (3) the lack of relevance of a particular legal status (marital and
immigration, respectively).84 In evaluating whether a statute or other state action has the
effect of creating a substantial obstacle, Casey
explains, the relevant inquiry is not the effect on all women but rather the
effect on a subset of women to whom the legal restriction matters.85 In Casey, theCourt struck down the spousal-notification
provision in the Pennsylvania law at issue because it created a “substantial
obstacle” to obtaining an abortion for women who were at risk of spousal abuse.86 The statute required that a married
woman provide her physician with a signed statement, affirming that she had
informed her spouse that she would be obtaining an abortion, before the
procedure could be performed.87 The woman
could alternatively provide a signed statement averring that she met one of the
statutory exceptions to the requirement.88
However, those exceptions did not cover all conditions of spousal abuse, nor
did they cover situations in which a woman otherwise would not have chosen to
notify her spouse due to “the husband’s illness, concern about her own health,
the imminent failure of the marriage, or the husband’s absolute opposition to
the abortion.”89 The State of Pennsylvania argued that, in determining whether
the statute had the effect of creating a substantial obstacle, the key question
was the percentage of women who sought an abortion who would be affected by the
law.90
The Casey opinion, though, explained
that this approach was incorrect.91 Rather, the
scope of the inquiry properly focused on “the group for whom the law is a
restriction, not the group for whom the law is irrelevant”—the key
question was, out of the group affected by the law, whether in “a large
fraction of cases” the statutory provision gave rise to a substantial obstacle.92 It was only once the group “of women
upon whom the statute operates” or, in other words, “those whose conduct [the
legislation] affects” was determined that a court could then determine whether
the imposed burden was undue.93 For the
spousal-notification requirement, the scope of the undue burden inquiry was not
all women in Pennsylvania or even all married women seeking abortions.94
For most married women, the Court explained, the statute would not change their
behavior, because “[i]n well-functioning marriages, spouses discuss important
intimate decisions.”95 Consequently,
in ascertaining whether the spousal-notification requirement posed an undue
burden, the inquiry as to potential burden was limited to “married women
seeking abortions who do not wish to notify their husbands of their intentions
and who do not qualify for one of the exceptions to the notice requirement.”96 Similarly, in determining whether the statutory provisions
compelling the closure of the McAllen and El Paso clinics are constitutionally
permissible, one does not evaluate the effect of the closures on all women in
Texas, all women in those cities, or all women in the border zone. Rather, the
scope of the inquiry focuses on “the group for whom the law is a restriction,
not the group for whom the law is irrelevant.”97
Following Casey, federal courts have
applied Casey’s limited-inquiry
approach in the context of clinic closures.98
In evaluating the appropriateness of a preliminary injunction of admitting privileges
requirements in Wisconsin that would lead to clinic closures, for example, a
district court explained that the scope of the relevant inquiry was “women
seeking abortions who are impacted by the closure of [two clinics], and the
reduction of capacity of [a third] clinic. The question is what percentage of
those women will be substantially
impacted.”99
Similarly, in evaluating the closure of the clinics in the border zone, the
appropriate focus is the group of women seeking abortions “for whom the law is
a restriction”—the group that experiences some sort of burden due to the law, whether due to travel time or
the need to pass through border checkpoints.100
Once the group that experiences some sort of burden is ascertained, the effects
analysis asks whether, for a “significant number” or “large fraction” of the
group who experiences some sort of effect, the burden is undue.101
The Casey Court determined that
Pennsylvania’s spousal-notification requirement was invalid because, “in a
large fraction of the cases in which [the statutory provision was] relevant, it
. . . operate[d] as a substantial obstacle.”102
This “large fraction” language has been the subject of attempts at judicial
line drawing since Casey.103
Casey itself, though, did not give
any precise ratio or number—there was no calculation in the opinion as to
the percentage or absolute number of women who experienced an undue burden from
the spousal-notification requirement.104
As noted above, Casey quoted the
district court’s findings as to a number of circumstances in which the spousal-notification
requirement might change women’s behavior—most significantly, in spousal-abuse
situations, but also in instances where the marriage was disintegrating, the
spouse was ill or opposed to abortion, or the woman was concerned with her own
health.105
In determining that spousal abuse meant that, in a “large fraction” of cases,
the law gave rise to an undue burden, Casey
did not estimate the numerical ratio of spousal abuse versus the other
situations it delineated.106 Rather, it
reasoned that women who were subject to potential domestic abuse were “likely
to be deterred from procuring an abortion,” that there were many such women in
the United States (“millions”), and that, consequently, in a “large fraction”
of the relevant cases, where behavior might change, the law created a
substantial obstacle to obtaining an abortion.107 The nature of this effects analysis—looking to some
subset of the burdened population for whom the burden may be undue—is
what makes the interior checkpoints so salient to analysis of the potential
clinic closures in the border zone. For undocumented women, closure of the
McAllen and El Paso clinics—of the clinics south and west of
checkpoints—means that they are “likely to be deterred from procuring an
abortion,” as those at risk of spousal abuse were likely to be deterred under
the Pennsylvania provision at issue in Casey.
Crossing border checkpoints to obtain an abortion risks detention and
deportation, including the possibility of permanent separation from family
members in the United States.108 As was
apparently true for those subject to spousal abuse in Casey, there appears to be no readily available empirical evidence on
the precise effect of this choice on women’s actions or the number or
percentage of undocumented women seeking an abortion in the border zone who
will be deterred from doing so.109 As in the
case of those at risk of spousal abuse, unauthorized immigrants are not easily
identifiable and likely reluctant to come forward for such research.
Nevertheless, the high stakes for undocumented women in crossing checkpoints,
coupled with anecdotal evidence that the checkpoints do function as a
deterrent,110
indicate that—like those deterred by spousal abuse in Casey—undocumented women who would
otherwise obtain an abortion are, if the clinics close, likely to be deterred
from doing so. For undocumented immigrants seeking abortions in light of
possible clinic closures and the background reality of internal immigration
checkpoints, the analogy to the spousal-notification requirement in Casey and its effect on potential
spousal abuse victims is particularly apt. Just as, in Casey, the background reality of a condition in certain women’s
lives meant that a new statutory burden made such women “likely to be deterred
from procuring an abortion,”111 the
background reality of the border checkpoints means that a significant number of
the women living in southern Texas without legal status will probably be
deterred from obtaining an abortion. Casey
noted that those in abusive situations “may have very good reasons for not
wishing to inform their husbands,” including possible abuse of themselves or
their children and their spouses’ ability to leverage potential disparities in
economic power. Similarly, the consequences of removal from the United States are
potentially enormous; undocumented women may also “have very good reasons” for
avoiding contact with internal border checkpoints. The parallel between the two statuses is especially
appropriate in that, just as married women “do not lose their constitutionally
protected liberty”112 because of
their legal status, neither do undocumented women. Governmental action on
behalf of the underlying legal regime related to a woman’s status—whether
that be marital status and regulation of marriage or immigration status and
regulation of immigration—may not, Casey
indicates, be a means of depriving women of their fundamental rights, where
they maintain those rights regardless of that legal status. While this point is
certainly not essential to the large-fraction analysis, it suggests the
particular aptness of the analogy to the spousal-notification requirement. If the analogy to Casey
is relatively straightforward, though, what should we make of the Fifth
Circuit’s brief analysis of the issue, which quickly discarded the “obstacle”
of border checkpoints as “unrelated to the hospital-admitting-privileges
requirement”?113
This determination reflects—in addition to a lack of record information
on the point114—an
erroneous understanding of Casey,
relying too much on language in the selective-funding case Harris v. McRae115 without considering Casey’s later analysis.116
It fails to recognize that Harris’s
language that the government “may not place obstacles in the path of a woman’s
exercise of her freedom of choice, [but] it need not remove those not of its
own creation”117
is at odds with Casey, unless read in the broader context ofthe selective-funding cases. Abusive spouses are not the creation of the
government, yet Casey found that
where their actions combined with Pennsylvania’s spousal-notification
requirement, the burden was undue.118
Harris, in determining that the
availability of federal Medicaid funds for pregnancy-related expenses but not
for abortion was constitutionally permissible, decided that such funds’
availability “leaves an indigent woman with at least the same range of choice”
as to whether to obtain an abortion;119
the spousal-notification requirement in Casey
and the closure of clinics south of border checkpoints, by contrast, restrict choice by removing access, such
that the option of abortion is functionally unavailable. H.B. 2 creates a substantial obstacle for a “significant
number” or “large fraction” of the women for whom the law is relevant: the
undocumented immigrants for whom the clinic closures impose a virtually per se
bar to obtaining an abortion. The numbers here cannot be obtained with
precision, but Casey indicates that
they need not be. The closure of clinics in the border zone creates obstacles
for those seeking an abortion, due to increased travel distance.120
That group of individuals—those burdened by distance—is analogous
to the group of women in Casey who
might have wished not to notify their spouse for reasons unrelated to domestic
violence. Casey did not attempt to
calculate this group’s precise number, or to compare it mathematically to the
number for whom the provision was a de facto per se bar due to spousal abuse.
Consequently, under Casey, it is not
necessary to determine the exact number of undocumented women in Texas’s border
zone. Rather, the point is that undocumented immigrants in southern Texas who
are burdened by the clinic closures—whether that group is framed as a
“large fraction” or a “significant number” of those burdened by the
closures—experience the burden on their right to abortion as a virtual
bar. There are likely more than eighty thousand undocumented women
of reproductive age in Texas’s border zone. Just as the Casey court was able to infer from the high number of women who are
subject to spousal abuse in the United States that a “large fraction” of those
who would not otherwise inform their spouses belonged to this group, in the
H.B. 2 context we can infer that a “large fraction” of those affected by the
clinic closures in the border zone are undocumented immigrants who now may be
functionally unable to obtain an abortion. A potential objection to this doctrinal understanding of the
burden posed by immigration checkpoints is the nature of the obstacle: one
might say that immigration enforcement is no obstacle to rights vindication in
this context at all, due to the availability of abortion in immigration
detention. Federal immigration-detention standards provide that “[a] pregnant
detainee in custody shall have access to pregnancy services including . . . abortion
services” and that every place of detention “shall . . . provide its female
detainees with access to” abortion.121 Either undocumented women will not
be detained at a checkpoint and will continue driving until they reach an
abortion clinic, or they will be detained and may avail themselves of access to
abortion care while detained. Consequently, the objection might run,
undocumented women in the Rio Grande Valley and El Paso face unfortunate
circumstances, but there is no absolute bar to abortion access: either outcome
could end in exercise of the right. How could there be any rights pressure,
then—let alone an undue burden? Evaluating the nature of immigration
enforcement as an obstacle implicates the functional nature of undue burden
analysis, which takes into account not whether there is some possible avenue to
rights vindication but rather the probability of deterrence due to cost-benefit
analysis associated with the barrier to vindication of the right. The key question in evaluating whether state action gives
rise to an undue burden under Casey’s
effects prong is whether the action “impose[s] a substantial obstacle,” such
that individuals are “likely to be deterred from procuring an abortion.”122
Casey explained that because those
subject to potential spousal abuse were likely to weigh the cost-benefit
analysis and not notify their spouses, out of “fear for their safety and the
safety of their children,” the requirement meant they were “likely to be
deterred from procuring an abortion as surely as if the Commonwealth had
outlawed abortion in all cases.”123
Formally, women in this situation could
tell their spouses, potentially incur abuse, and obtain abortions;
functionally, the Court recognized, the potential cost of doing so was so great
that these women were “likely to be deterred”—likely to choose not to
vindicate the abortion right.124 Similarly, the rights burden created in this situation by
H.B. 2is not because there is no
possible way for an unauthorized immigrant living in southern Texas to
vindicate her right to obtain an abortion. Instead, the rights burden exists because,
due to both the perceived very high risk of detention and deportation in
passing through checkpoints125 and the magnitude of the
repercussions of detention and deportation, undocumented women are “likely to
be deterred” from obtaining an abortion at
all. Removal from the United States can be personally catastrophic: an
individual is separated, perhaps permanently,126
from her home, her family, her community, and her work—in short, from the
life that she has created for herself.127
Those in families of mixed citizenship and immigration statuses face an
especially wrenching choice: to uproot everyone, potentially moving to a
country where some or all family members do not have ties or even speak the
predominant language, or to leave some family members behind for an indefinite
period of time.128 The Supreme
Court has described deportation as “the equivalent of banishment or exile.”129
It has recognized that deportation may cause the “loss of both property and
life; or of all that makes life worth living.”130 When a woman may obtain an abortion
only by placing herself at risk of losing “all that makes life worth living,”
it is reasonable to surmise that many women who would otherwise choose to
terminate that pregnancy will not do so. Moreover, even beyond the enormous harm of deportation, the
probability of losing one’s liberty131 by being placed in immigration
detention is likely to function as a deterrent in traveling through the
checkpoints for abortion purposes.132
Even for those without legal status who are not ultimately deported, because
they are granted a form of affirmative relief—asylum or withholding of
removal—the process for receiving affirmative relief may take years, and
if the immigration judge determines that they are a flight risk or a danger to
the community, they may spend those years in detention.133
Federal courts have recognized that, for sentencing purposes, time spent in
immigration detention either may be equivalent to time spent in prison134
or may qualify a convicted individual for a downward departure in sentencing.135 When weighing, in combination, the threat of removal and the
hazard of detention in passing through internal checkpoints, a “significant
number” of women without legal status are “likely to be deterred.”136
Even if potential detention is not an absolute bar to abortion, for many women
the utility analysis of the magnitude and probability of harm from being
detained and likely deported will itself function as a bar. Under the current
doctrinal analysis for violations of the substantive due process right to
choose whether to terminate a pregnancy, undocumented women—a “relevant
fraction” of the population affected by H.B. 2’s admitting privileges and
ambulatory surgical center requirements—experience an undue burden. This
specific doctrinal analysis demonstrates how, taking into account the backdrop
of federal checkpoints, state legislation may burden rights in the border zone. In the specific doctrinal context of abortion jurisprudence,
then, H.B. 2 as applied to the border zone violates the Fourteenth Amendment’s
substantive due process guarantee because it has the effect of creating a
substantial obstacle for undocumented women. Another means of thinking of the
harm of H.B. 2 for undocumented women in the border zone, though, is not merely
through the ramifications of the legislation—the functional inability to
access abortion services—but, more broadly, as creating a choice that is
constitutionally suspect: a choice between exercising one’s fundamental right
and avoiding exposure to immigration enforcement. Thus, another way to conceive
of the problem—ultimately arriving at the same conclusion, but with an
analysis generalizable to rights burdenings beyond the abortion
context—is through the doctrine of unconstitutional conditions. Framing
the problem in more general terms and examining H.B. 2 on these grounds
demonstrates the way that state legislation with spatially disparate effects may,
more generally, create constitutional problems given the reality of internal
checkpoints. Such legislation gives rise to unconstitutional conditions that
impermissibly pressure rights. The key insight of this Part is that we ought to
conceive of barriers to access engendered by the confluence of spatially
disparate state legislation and federal internal immigration checkpoints as an
unconstitutional-conditions problem. Evaluating the problem through the lens of unconstitutional
conditions provides a separate ground for H.B. 2’s unconstitutionality,
independent of the Casey analysis.
Whether undocumented women are in fact deterred from seeking an abortion by the
closure of all clinics south of border checkpoints is not the relevant inquiry
under unconstitutional-conditions doctrine—instead, the question is
whether women must choose between a discretionary benefit and the exercise of a
constitutional right.137 The de facto requirement created by
Texas law that a woman without legal status must pass through an internal
Border Patrol checkpoint to reach abortion services creates an unconstitutional
condition on the exercise of the fundamental right, because of the coercive nature
of the choice. Such an unconstitutional condition is a violation of a woman’s
right to choose to terminate her pregnancy. This mode of analysis indicates that the situation that H.B.
2 creates for undocumented women in southern Texas is one instantiation of a
larger problem: the way that the conjunction of internal checkpoints and state
legislation with spatially disparate effects on access to rights may create a
constitutionally impermissible choice for undocumented individuals. This
insight—that unconstitutional-conditions doctrine provides an alternative
means of evaluating the problem—and the subsequent evaluation require
further interrogation. This Part’s analysis turns first to the nature of the
benefit at stake, then to an evaluation of whether there is sufficient
germaneness for an unconstitutional condition, and finally to the additional
complication of the multiple state actors who together give rise to the
condition. The functional requirement that an individual choose between
exercising a fundamental right—in this case, the right to obtain an
abortion—and forgoing questioning by Border Patrol officers as to one’s immigration
status implicates this transsubstantive doctrine. The underlying idea of unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine is, essentially, that the government cannot create an impermissibly
rights-pressuring choice.138 As the Supreme Court recently
explained in Koontz v. St. Johns River
Water Management District, in the individual-rights context the doctrine
bars “the government [from] deny[ing] a benefit to a person because he [or she]
exercises a constitutional right.”139
For example, a state may not make public employment contingent on an
individual’s giving up her right to free speech.140
Such a choice is impermissible even if the benefit is not one to which the
person has a “right . . . and even though the government may deny him the
benefit for any number of reasons.”141
Moreover, it is impermissible regardless of what
the individual ultimately chooses—whether she opts to pass up the benefit
or instead to forgo exercise of the right.142
Recent takings cases have required a “nexus” and “rough proportionality”
between the relinquishment of the rights exercise and the granting of the
benefit.143 Originally applied in the context of economic substantive due
process,144 unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine—or, as it is sometimes termed, the conditional-offer problem145—applies to a situation in
which the exercise of an individual constitutional right is conditioned.
Apparently not limited to any particular subset or constellation of rights, the
doctrine is a “multi-function doctrine”146
useful in evaluating situations in which state action leads to a situation that
conditions rights on forgoing a benefit, or vice versa. The Supreme Court has
used unconstitutional-conditions analysis to evaluate claims that state action
violates freedom of speech,147 free
exercise of religion,148 the right to
refrain from self-incrimination,149
the right to travel,150 and the
Takings Clause.151 Federal courts of appeals have recognized
the applicability of unconstitutional-conditions analysis to claims of
violations of freedom of speech, petition, assembly, and association;152 the Establishment Clause;153
freedom from unreasonable search and seizure;154
the Takings Clause;155 the Sixth Amendment
right to trial;156 the right to
appeal;157
and the right to access to a federal forum.158 One theorist has described unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine as triggered when governmental action creates the biconditional “if ~x, then y; and if x, then ~y.”159 This formulation dovetails with the
Supreme Court’s most recent explication of the doctrine, in Justice Alito’s
majority opinion in Koontz: that
whether the individual whose rights are under pressure chooses the benefit or
the right is irrelevant.160 Under this
conceit, the sort of situation created by border checkpoints and H.B. 2 is a
quintessential unconstitutional-conditions problem. If the individual chooses
to undergo questioning as to immigration status by the Border Patrol, she may
travel north to access abortion services; if she declines to exercise her right
to access an abortion, she may protect herself from such immigration
enforcement by remaining in the border zone.161
A state actor presumably could not directly create a barrier to an individual’s
travel to access abortion.162 The
unconstitutional-conditions doctrine means that the indirect creation of a
barrier, by legislating out of existence all the clinics within a given area
and consequently giving rise to the biconditional, is likewise impermissible.163 This straightforward formulation, though, elides some of the
messiness of the unconstitutional-conditions doctrine as formulated and
explicated by the federal courts.164
First, and least problematically, we might question whether abortion access is
a right that falls within the scope of unconstitutional-conditions doctrine at
all. Next, we might wonder whether the biconditional formulation is appropriate
here—whether not having to cross immigration checkpoints is a
“discretionary benefit” for the purposes of the doctrine. We might then ask whether
there is any conditioning at all and, if so, whether that conditioning is in
fact constitutionally impermissible. And, lastly, we ought to consider the fact
that the application of the unconstitutional-conditions doctrine in this
circumstance, where the decisions as to the grant or denial of the benefit and
the creation of the condition are due to the independent actions of a state and
a federal actor, implicates the role of intentionality in the doctrine. The unconstitutional-conditions analysis deserves a caveat.
The doctrine both is part of constitutional common law and applies in a variety
of doctrinal contexts regarding individual rights.165
Consequently, it is not the most straightforward area of doctrinal analysis;
like all human constructs, it is imperfectly articulated. But it is a
methodological tool that sheds particular light on situations in which
individual rights seem constrained rather than expanded by choice. This Part’s
analysis starts from the basic premises that unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine, while not perfectly contoured in all respects, is an ordinary feature
of constitutional law, and that its implications for the border zone deserve
attention.166 Unconstitutional-conditions doctrine has particular salience
in the abortion context, as is relevant to the fact-specific problem of H.B. 2.
Two selective-funding cases—Maher
v. Roe, challenging Connecticut’s funding of pregnancy expenses but not
abortions for indigent women,167 and Harris v. McRae, challenging similar
federal funding restrictions in the Medicaid program168—have
been interpreted as paradigmatic unconstitutional-conditions cases that shed
light on a germaneness requirement for a condition to be constitutional.169
Rust v. Sullivan, which held that
restrictions on federal funding for abortion counseling did not violate
individuals’ abortion rights because the restrictions did not change women’s
available choices, also used unconstitutional-conditions reasoning.170
More recently, the Seventh and Eighth Circuits have applied unconstitutional-conditions
reasoning to determine whether abortion rights were impermissibly burdened.171
The benefit involved in these cases,
selective funding, is different from that at stake in the context of border
checkpoints and H.B. 2. But the cases demonstrate that for the right at issue—abortion—application
of the unconstitutional-conditions doctrine is not unusual.172 More significantly, both case law and much of the academic
literature consistently describe the forbidden choice in an unconstitutional-conditions
problem as one between a right and a “discretionary benefit.”173
Is nonexposure to spatially selective immigration enforcement a “discretionary
benefit,” within the meaning of unconstitutional-conditions doctrine?174
It is—or, at the least, we ought to recognize it as such. The doctrine is
unclear, and there appears to have been no case implicating the border
checkpoints in which courts have applied unconstitutional-conditions analysis.175
But the best interpretation, most consonant with the purposes that underlie
unconstitutional-conditions doctrine, is to view it as such. In a way, such
extension would be novel—but it both is consistent with case law and
makes sense in light of the constitutional common-law nature of the doctrine.176 Most case law deals with situations involving governmental
withholding of affirmative benefits due to exercise of a right, rather than
governmental withholding of enforcement or punishment.177
Some cases, however, indicate that the denial of withholding of enforcement
qualifies as a “benefit.” At least two Supreme Court opinions have appeared to
apply unconstitutional-conditions doctrine in an enforcement or punishment
context, though neither explicitly situates itself within the doctrine. Zablocki v. Redhail overturned a state
statute requiring court approval of marriage for those required to pay child
support on the grounds that the statute “unnecessarily impinge[d] on the right
to marry”;178
United States v. Jackson overturned
the portion of the Federal Kidnapping Act that took the death penalty off the
table only if the defendant forewent exercising the right to a jury trial.179 This case law and, more broadly speaking, the common-law
nature of the doctrine’s elaboration counsel against an overly restrictive
interpretation of cases’ “discretionary benefit” language. Unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine has developed over time as a judicial understanding of a particular
way that governmental action may engender a harm rising to the level of a
constitutional violation.180 And, while
academic commentators have diverged over the underlying logic of the
unconstitutional-conditions doctrine,181 recent moves toward more coherent
and systematizing understandings of the doctrine as one of framing suggests
such a broader scope for “benefit.”182
Indeed, some scholars view the doctrine as, on a best understanding,
encompassing discretionary enforcement decisions.183 Interpreting the avoidance of a certain encounter with
immigration enforcement as a discretionary benefit therefore fits well within
the contours of existing unconstitutional-conditions doctrine. It also makes
sense in terms of the harm that courts describe unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine as intending to capture—the pressure that an individual
experiences to make a particular choice, given the incentive structure set up
by the choice architecture.184 In a situation like that engendered by H.B. 2, then, where
governmental action forecloses access to rights within the border zone, an
individual faces a choice between exercise of the right and avoiding spatially
selective immigration enforcement—the kind of “Hobson’s choice” that courts
have deemed impermissible.185 Under the
legal regime created by the current intersection of federal immigration
enforcement and state law—both of which have spatially distortive
effects—a person may either refrain from passing through border checkpoints
and therefore refrain from undergoing a search that exposes her to the risk of
selective immigration enforcement, or she may obtain an abortion. She cannot do
both. Consequently, the intersection of border checkpoints and
fundamental rights falls squarely on the nongermaneness side of the germaneness
or nexus requirement running through the case law. Case law indicates that, for
a condition placed upon a right to be constitutionally permissible, there must
be some sort of “nexus” and “rough proportionality” between the condition and
the right.186
For example, in the exactions context, a court must determine whether there is
a connection “between the legitimate state interest and the permit condition”
and then “must make some sort of individualized determination that the required
dedication is related both in nature and extent to the impact of the proposed
development.”187
Relying on this test, the Supreme Court determined in Dolan v. City of Tigard that requiring the grant of a pedestrian
and bike easement in order to obtain a permit for commercial expansion did not
exhibit the requisite rough proportionality.188 The distinction between germaneness and nongermaneness is
particularly vivid in the abortion-funding cases Maher v. Roe189and Harris v. McRae.190In these cases, the Supreme Court
upheld funding restrictions in which government-subsidized healthcare programs
recompensed individuals for pregnancy and childbirth expenses but not for
elective abortions.191 The Court in
Maher characterized the statute at
issue as creating no further obstacles to abortion, explaining that “[a]n
indigent woman . . . continues as before to be dependent on private sources.”192
It differentiated cases striking down durational-residency requirements to
receive welfare benefits on, apparently, germaneness grounds: denial of “bus
fares” to travelers, the Court implied, would have been permissible, but denial
of welfare was closer to “a criminal fine.”193
Similarly, Harris emphasized that the
denial of general benefits to anyone who secured an abortion would create a
“substantial constitutional question.”194
These cases—and the manner in which they differentiate the durational-residency
cases—indicate that something akin to the “nexus” and “rough
proportionality” requirements in the Takings Clause cases applies, as well, in
the abortion-rights context. While they do not use that specific language, the
underlying requirement of a sufficiently strong connection between the right
conditioned and the benefit appears to be the same. More broadly, the cases
suggest—particularly in combination with the later Takings Clause
cases—that the unconstitutional conditions doctrinal inquiry keys, at
least in part, to germaneness.195 There is no nexus between the enforcement of immigration law
and the seeking of access to abortion services. Unlike in the selective-funding
cases, state-generated closure of clinics within the border zone leads to
consequences beyond state “refusal to subsidize certain protected conduct.”196 Abortion access and immigration
enforcement are not linked by a common policy concern. The consequences if one
exercises the right are simply not germane. There is also a lack of proportionality between the exercise
of abortion rights and the enforcement of immigration law. The idea that
conditioning the right to abortion on hazarding detention and deportation
unconstitutionally “coerc[es]” undocumented women “into giving . . . up” a
substantive due process right is intuitive.197
Both the magnitude and the perceived likelihood of the harms of detention and
deportation are great.198 Requiring individuals, for the
exercise of the right, to risk the loss of home, community, and potentially
family and livelihood—potentially “all that makes life worth living”199—seems
more analogous to the “criminal fine” that the Maher Court suggested was impermissible.200
These costs are greater than others that the Court has found unconstitutional,
such as requiring that individuals give up a tax exemption,201
public employment,202 or the
possibility of unemployment benefits to exercise a fundamental right.203
A state actor could not directly impose a bar on an unauthorized immigrant’s
access to abortion, since doing so would be a violation of substantive due
process rights.204 The current
choice architecture conditions exercise of a constitutional substantive due
process right on the denial of something of great value—not having the government assuredly
perform a search to detect one’s immigration status, a search that is likely to
lead to civil enforcement of the immigration laws.205
Such a state-structured choice, if the absence of selective enforcement is a
benefit, is an unconstitutional conditioning of a person’s right to terminate
her pregnancy. The choice created for undocumented immigrants by the
checkpoints and potential clinic closures thus fits relatively comfortably
within unconstitutional-conditions doctrine, given the existing doctrinal
ambiguities and the open question as to this kind of administrative enforcement
discretion as benefit. Most if not all unconstitutional-conditions cases,
though, involve both a benefit and a rights burden engendered by a single state actor.206
Here, the federal administrative enforcement scheme provides the benefit, while
the state’s regulation places the burden on the right. Does a choice between
rights exercise and benefit brought about by the separate actions of two
different actors—one state and one federal—create an
unconstitutional condition? This question implicates whether unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine bars a coercive purpose or a
coercive effect—an area of the
doctrine that is unclear. If the doctrine is effects oriented, then H.B. 2 is
an unconstitutional condition. Even if it is purpose oriented, though, there
are reasons to think that on either analysis H.B. 2’s conditioning is
constitutionally problematic, due to the Texas legislature’s knowledge of the
border area. In analyzing governmental actions through an unconstitutional-conditions
lens, courts have not clearly distinguished between a coercive purpose and a coercive effect.207
This lack of clarity matters to situations with multiple actors, like the
border zone and H.B. 2. On the one hand, without purpose, the choice that
individuals face is no less rights pressuring—it presumably does not
matter to one’s decision as to whether to go through an immigration checkpoint
or forgo obtaining an abortion which governmental entities are responsible for
creating the choice. On the other, if the point of the unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine is to bar governmental actors from threatening or coercing
individuals—from tilting incentives in a way that the government prefers,
because of the asymmetrical power to grant or deny a benefit that the
governmental actor holds—then perhaps the presence of multiple actors
does matter. This unresolved tension is on display in Koontz. In one sentence, Justice Alito’s majority opinion explains,
“By conditioning a building permit on the owner’s deeding over a public
right-of-way . . . the government can pressure an owner into voluntarily giving
up property for which the Fifth Amendment would otherwise require just
compensation.”208 The emphasis
here seems to be on what the opinion then characterizes as “the government’s
demand”209—on
a governmental action. At the end of
that paragraph, though, the opinion concludes, “Extortionate demands of this
sort frustrate the Fifth Amendment right
to just compensation, and the unconstitutional conditions doctrine
prohibits them.”210 This
concluding sentence places the emphasis not on the act of demanding or some sort of mens rea requirement—not on
governmental purpose—but rather on the loss of just compensation.211
The tension is, perhaps, best encapsulated in Koontz’s characterization of the “overarching principle”: “the
unconstitutional conditions doctrine . . . vindicates the Constitution’s
enumerated rights by preventing the government from coercing people into giving
them up.”212 Whether such “coerci[on]” requires governmental
intentionality is not resolved in the constitutional common law of
unconstitutional-conditions doctrine. The Supreme Court’s unconstitutional-conditions
cases appear not to have explicitly confronted the issue. Language in lower-court
opinions diverges—some seem to place some emphasis on “purpose,” while
others do not require purpose.213 The opinions
in both Supreme Court and lower-court cases tend not to probe legislative
history to discern bad motive or otherwise engage in some sort of familiar
motive-based inquiry. Many cases focus on the situation created for
individuals, from needing to give up a right to just compensation in exchange
for a land-use permit, to being required to engage in certain speech to receive
money, to having to forgo unemployment benefits due to practicing one’s
religion.214
Among academic commentators, some view the intent of the state actor as
essential—as the constitutional
problem with unconstitutional conditions.215
Others see intent as not required for a rights-pressuring choice to be an
unconstitutional condition.216 Due to the doctrinal ambiguities and the lack of a specific
textual grounding for this multipurpose doctrine, whether one thinks intent
matters in unconstitutional-conditions doctrine may ultimately hinge on whether
one views the doctrine as rights regarding or regulatory. If the purpose is to
shield the individual from governmental choice, then governmental intent may
not matter, while a purpose of barring governmental actions with bad intent may
make intent more salient.217 The lack of
focus on governmental purpose or mens rea in case law may point to an existing
understanding of the doctrine as rights regarding. The coercion language,
though, is less clear. The idea that a pressured choice forced on an individual
by a governmental actor—regardless of the actor’s
motivation—creates an impermissible constitutional burden on a right may
have intuitive resonance. It parallels duress doctrine in contract law.218
Particularly, where liberty is at stake as the “benefit,” as in the detention
and deportation context, the conditioned choice may seem especially
constitutionally suspect: the effects
of the choice are likely far more pronounced. There are very good reasons to
think that intent does not matter;219
and if it does not, then H.B. 2 and the border checkpoints create an
unconstitutional condition. Even if intent does matter, though, state actors’ disregard
for the spatially disparate effects of H.B. 2 could conceivably cross a
requisite level of intent. The line for a governmental actor’s improper mens
rea in creating coercive conditions may not necessarily cut through specific
intent to deprive individuals of the right. Texas legislators are—or at
least ought to be—well aware of the conditions in their state, including
the conditions in the Rio Grande Valley, the many unauthorized immigrants who
live there, and the existence of border checkpoints.220 Media coverage surrounding
undocumented women and access to abortion began before the passage of H.B. 2.221
The debate over H.B. 2 focused in part on the particular challenges that the
bill would pose to individuals living in the Rio Grande Valley and El Paso in
reaching clinics.222 If knowledge or recklessness, not
purpose or specific intent to deprive, suffices for intentionality in the
unconstitutional-conditions context,223 then H.B. 2—and other
regulations with spatially disparate effects—crosses that threshold.
Because of the lack of doctrinal clarity, under a view of the doctrine as
regulatory or intent based, states’ reckless or knowing actions with effects on
undocumented immigrants’ choices in the border zone may satisfy intent and give
rise to an unconstitutional condition. On an effects-based view, of course, no
such intentionality is required—and the choice between exercising the
right to an abortion and avoiding exposure to immigration enforcement is an
unconstitutional condition. *** Viewing spatially selective immigration enforcement as an
unconstitutional-conditions problem—not only in the H.B. 2 context but
more broadly—comports with the underlying “nexus” or “germaneness” thread
running through the doctrine and concomitant intuitions as to which
government-structured choice architectures for rights are permissible. One’s
immigration status and the exercise of one’s right to determine whether to carry
a pregnancy to term are unrelated. This characterization of the problem, while apparently novel
in the immigration-enforcement context, also sounds in constitutional norms of
due process and an underlying anticaste principle.224 In considering the problem from a
due-process perspective, it is possible that deprivation of an unrelated
fundamental right is the penalty that one pays for an immigration violation,
for a tax penalty, or for punishment for the commission of a crime. But, even
assuming that is the case,225 such
deprivation should be due after the
government has determined that an individual is culpable, not before. The group
of people who will be ensnared through exposure to civil or criminal law
enforcement is larger than the group of people who will be eligible for
deportation, who will be guilty of the crime, or who will need to pay income
taxes—the list of potential “suspects” is almost always longer than the
list of those actually convicted or liable. In the immigration context,
individuals who are eligible for asylum may not be aware of the prevailing law
or may not have the resources to go through the legal process; those eligible
for withholding of removal may not want to risk exposing themselves to
immigration enforcement for the chance of receiving this discretionary relief.226 These persons are in fact able to
obtain status and remain in the United States, but they too will be swept up in
the enforcement and will need to extricate themselves, losing their liberty in
the meantime. From an antisubordination perspective, as Kathleen Sullivan
observes in the context of affirmative benefits,227
allowing the conditioning of fundamental rights on exposure to an enforcement
mechanism creates a two-tiered system of rights, in which only those subject to
enforcement face the coercive pressure. Because undocumented immigrants not
only have, as a class, less political power than those with legal status, but
also face potential enforcement consequences by asserting political voice, they
are, as a class, particularly at risk for the creation of impermissible
choices.228 The unconstitutional-conditions
framework does not doctrinally require either of these underlying resonances,
but they provide a sense that the doctrinal evaluation of the border-checkpoints
problem fits with the larger constitutional system. The checkpoints and state
legislation careless to its spatial effects, when they combine to pressure
individual rights in the border zone, are best understood as constitutionally
impermissible. Finally, part of the puzzle as to whether H.B. 2—or any
spatially disparate state regulation that removes access to a fundamental right
from within the border zone—violates undocumented immigrants’ rights is a
question of causation, which in turn implicates federalism questions. The bar
to rights vindication is the conjunction of state regulatory action and a
federal administrative enforcement scheme, predicated on spatiality, that
problematizes travel for individuals subject to enforcement. For purposes of
constitutional analysis, is a deprivation of the right to reproductive choice caused by Texas’s law leading to clinic
closures? The Fourteenth Amendment provides that no state “shall . . . deprive
any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.”229
But do the Texas abortion restrictions themselves “deprive any person” of the
right to reproductive choice—given that, in the absence of the
checkpoints, the closure of clinics requiring travel out of the border zone
could230
pose no barrier at all? This Part argues that when a state passes a law, like H.B. 2,
that removes access to a right within its borders from the area between the
international border and the checkpoints, the state is legally responsible for
that rights deprivation. This legal responsibility exists notwithstanding the
federal government’s actions in creating the anomalous zone and the lack of
immigration status that places individuals at risk of enforcement action. Both
the doctrinal-causation principles applied in evaluating Fourteenth Amendment
violations and larger constitutional commitments—to the vindication of
individual rights notwithstanding federal-state allocations of power—lead
to this conclusion. The Fourteenth Amendment and 42 U.S.C. § 1983 together create
a “species of tort liability” for those “deprived of rights,” as well as the
possibility of injunctive relief against state action.231
In this context, to determine whether there is sufficient causation to
constitute a “depriv[ation]” of rights, courts are “governed by . . . common-law
tort principles,”232 including
proximate cause233 and the idea
of a causal chain.234
Consequently, a state’s action that removes access to rights in the border zone
must be both a factual and a proximate cause of the resultant harm in order to
constitute a substantive due process violation, and there must be no
superseding cause that breaks the causal chain.235 H.B. 2 is plainly a factual cause of the resultant
harm—the infringement on the abortion rights of a particular segment of
Texas’s population.236 Were H.B. 2 not to take full effect,
women living in south Texas would still have access to abortion clinics within
the border zone; they would not need to travel beyond the checkpoints. The legislation
is also a proximate cause.237 As in situations in which the
Supreme Court has found sufficient proximate cause for constitutional
liability,238
the encumbrance on undocumented women’s reproductive rights is a “natural
consequence[]” of Texas’s action in enacting H.B. 2.239
As noted above, the state legislature was aware both that the checkpoints
existed and that the legislation threatened to close the clinics south and west
of the checkpoints.240 The
potential for clinic closures to ensue from H.B. 2 and the resultant inability
of undocumented women to continue to access abortion services were “reasonably
foreseeable,” in the language of tort law.241 The sharper (and more interesting) doctrinal question is
whether the two other factual causes of the rights violation—the federal
immigration enforcement scheme and individuals’ immigration status—break
the causal chain. Were there no border checkpoints, H.B. 2 would cause no
particular infringement on the abortion rights of unauthorized immigrants. And
if undocumented immigrants instead had lawful immigration status, the interior
checkpoints would give rise to no particular undue burden or unconstitutional
condition. Ultimately, both on a technical causation analysis and—as
Section IV.B argues—consistent with constitutional allocations of power,
neither suffices to overcome state legal responsibility for the deprivation of
the right. The State of Texas, or any state with internal checkpoints, is
responsible for substantive due process violations due to actions that remove
access to rights in the border zone.242 Under common-law tort analysis, intervening acts by
independent actors typically do not foreclose tort liability where those actions
were foreseeable.243 The Supreme
Court has previously followed such common-law interpretations of the
significance of actions by independent state actors that potentially break the
causal chain.244
It has determined that where “the common law recognized the causal link . . . we
read § 1983 as recognizing the same causal link.”245
Internal immigration checkpoints are foreseeable to legislators in states that
contain them. Indeed, the checkpoints have existed in some form for
decades—their presence is not a surprise.246
Moreover, the effects of the checkpoints on movements of persons are well known
in the areas where they exist.247 Additionally,
the presence of significant numbers of undocumented immigrants in the border
area is easily anticipatable from history and present demographics.248
The harm of certain persons in the border zone being deprived of the ability to
obtain abortions is a foreseeable risk of passing a bill that closes clinics in
the border zone—and so the foreseeable actions of the federal government
in maintaining spatially selective immigration enforcement do not remove legal
responsibility from the State of Texas for the deprivation of rights. Nor does the nature of immigration status obviate the rights
violation engendered by cutting off access to abortion within the border area.
A potential objection to seeing H.B. 2 as causal in this context might be,
essentially, a contributory-negligence argument. Sure, one might argue,
unauthorized immigrants might have substantive due process rights—but, the
objection might run, they are responsible for their presence in the border
zone. Consequently, any spatially uneven effects of state
regulation—anything that removes rights access from the border
zone—is not a constitutional problem, because the salient cause of the
rights violation is not the legislation but the action or presence of
undocumented persons. This argument fails both doctrinally, as a matter of common-law
causation, and constitutionally, in light of existing substantive due process
doctrine. Doctrinally, in the move from contributory negligence to comparative
fault in tort law, the plaintiff’s own actions are typically no longer regarded
as an intervening cause sufficient to break a causal chain and give rise to
liability.249
Instead, the plaintiff’s actions are ordinarily regarded as part of the causal
set and evaluated accordingly.250 As with
other potential superseding causes, the actions will not foreclose liability
(in this instance, liability on the part of the State of Texas) due to “risks
that made the actor’s conduct tortious.”251
Again, the presence of undocumented immigrants in the border area is
foreseeable.252
Constitutionally, to the extent that this interpretation is predicated in a
sense of moral or legal delict, it does not mesh with substantive due process
doctrine any more than it does with common-law doctrine. It makes little sense
to construe substantive due process doctrine as encompassing undocumented
immigrants,253
but then to exclude certain undocumented immigrants from substantive due
process protections, based on where in the United States—and in which
part of a particular state—they happened to reside. The border zone represents the failure of federal-state
allocations of power alone to protect or further individual rights. In Bond v. United States, Justice Kennedy
wrote for a unanimous Court, “By denying any one government complete
jurisdiction over all the concerns of public life, federalism protects the
liberty of the individual from arbitrary power.”254 The opinion theorized federalism as
rights protecting for individuals, both through this diffusion of power and in
the fueling of state innovation and responsiveness to individual voice.255 Federalism scholars have viewed the
LGBT marriage-equality movement as exemplifying this kind of rights-protecting
function of federal-state allocations of power. Heather Gerken sees marriage
equality as an instantiation of how “[f]ederalism and rights have long served
as interlocking gears moving us forward.”256 Ernest Young describes how exit and
voice in the federal system furthered the interests of same-sex couples and
fueled the LGBT-rights movement, because people were able to move to
jurisdictions where advocates had exercised power to enact marriage equality locally.257 Under this version of the story,
Albert Hirschman’s familiar framework258
indicates—in one way or another259—how
federalism may provide safeguards for minority rights. These posited means for the federal system to protect the
rights of particularly vulnerable individuals break down, though, for
undocumented immigrants in the border zone. First, the combination of a federal
administrative enforcement scheme and unrelated state regulation here does not
create the diffusion of power preventing “government act[ion] in excess of . .
. lawful powers” described in Bond.260
Instead, in order for federalism to safeguard individual rights in this
context, increased state attention to
the effects of federal exercise of power—and action in accordance with
that attention—is necessary. H.B. 2 demonstrates how the diffusion of
power between the federal and state governments may cause the rights of an
especially vulnerable minority group to fall through the political cracks. Second, functionally, both exit and voice are greatly
restricted for undocumented immigrants in this space—these individuals
are limited in both political participation and movement. The posited consumer
protections of federalism—shopping for the locale that maximizes utility261—are
unavailable due to the restrictions on movement created by the checkpoints.
Politically, undocumented persons cannot vote, and speaking out risks exposing
one’s immigration status.262 As a result,
any “democratic churn” is unlikely to be availing for this particular minority
group.263 Yet, the area between the internal checkpoints and the
international border is also within both the United States and a particular
state. And the Fourteenth Amendment is a constitutional commitment to shield all individuals, vis-à-vis state
governments, from the deprivation of substantive due process rights.264
The anomalous zone created by the border checkpoints may be an example of
“immigration exceptionalism” in the Fourth Amendment context.265
Border checkpoints and roving patrols by Border Patrol agents south of the
checkpoint are justified under the Fourth Amendment, the Supreme Court has
said, by the “valid public interest” in restricting the “inland movement” of
undocumented immigrants.266 There is no
congruent justification, though, for deprivation of access to a substantive due
process right. First, unlike Fourth Amendment or procedural due process
inquiries,267
substantive due process analysis is not a balancing test that gives weight to a
governmental interest.268 And even if
it were, the abortion right itself is not linked in any way to the checkpoints’
concern with movement into the rest of the country—unlike Fourth
Amendment rights.269 Immigration
exceptionalism—some sort of idea that the federal governmental interest
in creating and maintaining the administrative scheme overshadows the
vindication of individual rights—has no doctrinal purchase. It especially
does not make sense to read the federal interest as somehow overwhelming in
light of the federal government’s continued exercise of discretion in allowing
individuals to live for years or decades in the border zone. By contrast, construing Texas’s action in enacting H.B. 2 as
a “depriv[ation]” of undocumented immigrants’ abortion rights is consistent
with a federalism that “protects the liberty of the individual from arbitrary
power.”270
Understanding state regulatory action that burdens rights access in this
physical space as causal, such that it constitutes a “deprivation,” reflects
the constitutional guarantee of substantive due process protections
notwithstanding state exercises of power embodied in the Fourteenth Amendment.
The details of the causation doctrine cohere with constitutional commitments. This analysis, like the unconstitutional-conditions analysis
of rights infringement, extends beyond the specificity of abortion and H.B. 2.
One could imagine state regulations that diminish or foreclose access in the
border zone to other rights that depend on travel for
vindication—particularly contraception, marriage, or access to medical
care.271
Individuals report forgoing specialized medical treatment due to fear of
exposure to immigration enforcement at checkpoints.272 If California, Arizona, New Mexico,
or Texas passed legislation limiting who could dispense contraception, for
example—such that the individuals who fulfilled that role in portions of
the border area no longer could—a very similar problem would arise.
Similarly, imagine a situation in which the only available marriage officiants
offered by a state were located beyond the checkpoints. To the extent that
other fundamental rights are predicated on spatial access, state actions that
remove access in the border zone may pose constitutional problems. Texas’s restrictions on abortion clinics, if they reach full
effect, will impose constitutionally impermissible limitations on access to
abortion for undocumented women in the border zone. Under doctrinal analysis
specific to substantive due process, they create an undue burden on this
group’s right to obtain an abortion—such that the law is invalid as
applied to the clinics in the border area. At a greater level of abstraction,
they give rise to a constitutionally impermissible choice between vindication
of the abortion right and lack of certain exposure to immigration enforcement—impermissibly
conditioning a right within the denial of a “benefit,” under a broad construal
of that word that is most consistent with the unconstitutional-conditions
doctrine and an underlying purpose of preventing rights-pressuring choices.
This framework is applicable not only in the abortion context but also to other
substantive due process problems engendered by the checkpoints. Using either
framework, and irrespective of any other constitutional flaws, H.B. 2 deprives
more than eighty thousand spatially and legally marginalized women of the right
to decide whether to terminate a pregnancy. The border zone is a site of overlapping sovereigns’
regulatory actions—of federal immigration enforcement efforts and of
state regulation pursuant to state-level legislative goals. The pressure that
the independent exercise of these powers may place on the substantive due
process rights of those caught in the spatial vise of the border zone has not
been taken up. Spatially selective immigration enforcement’s cabining of the
movements of a certain set of individuals—undocumented
immigrants—poses problems for theories of how federal choice may enable
rights vindication for marginalized groups. As H.B. 2 demonstrates,
federal-state allocations of power in the border space may endanger fundamental
rights. The application of unconstitutional-conditions doctrine, in particular,
provides a way to think through the constitutional problems posed by that
endangerment. The relationship between spatial access and substantive due
process—and, inversely, between barriers to travel and rights
burdens—is not unique to the space between internal immigration
checkpoints and the border. Abortion cases frequently hinge on travel
distances.273
Recent North Carolina legislation permitting state magistrates to decline to
marry same-sex couples might lead to similar travel problems burdening the
right to marry.274 The Fifth
Circuit has struggled with the question of whether and when “a state can[] lean
on its sovereign neighbors to provide protection of its citizens’” substantive
due process rights;275 may a state
ever foreclose all in-state options for abortion, knowing that out-of-state
options exist?276 In the
extraterritorial context, the Supreme Court has weighed but reached no majority
consensus as to whether a citizen has a substantive due process right to live
in the United States with a noncitizen spouse.277
The per se bar to undocumented immigrants’ movement out of the border area
throws into sharp relief a burden on vindication of substantive due process
rights, in the form of barriers to travel, that typically take the form of a
sliding scale. This Note provides a case study of how the spatial
immigration enforcement regime created by interior checkpoints may burden
fundamental rights. This conclusion indicates that states that border other
countries must think carefully about the spatially disparate effects of
legislation that may place pressure on rights. More broadly, it demonstrates
the need to take into account the spatial nature of substantive due process: the
ways in which the exercise of fundamental rights depends in part on political
and physical geography.
Introduction
I. the
border zone and h.b. 2
A. Border
Checkpoints: Spatially Selective Immigration Enforcement
B. Reproductive
Rights and Spatiality: H.B. 2
II. h.b.
2 as undue burden
A. Casey’s
Undue Burden Analysis
B. Immigration Enforcement as
Obstacle
III. h.b. 2
and border checkpoints as unconstitutional condition
A. The
Right
B. The
Benefit
C. Conditioning
D. Intentionality?
IV. causation at checkpoints
A. Doctrinal
Causation
B. Individual
Rights: Federalism’s Failure?
Conclusion